NOTES ON:
Deleuze, G. (2004) Desert Islands and
Other Texts 1953-74, edited by David
Lapoujade, translated by Michael Taormina.
MIT Press: London.
[This is the sort of stuff you get when great men
get all their jottings and notes and memos
translated. Some pieces are very small
extracts from interviews. Most are short, thank
God, and pretty clear, relatively. Others are
really obscure and probably early stuff. Now
and then there is a cracking essay, but there are
also light Parisian witty reviews, often
connecting a recent book to some hero of
Deleuze's. I think it best to leave them to you, O
Reader]
Introduction
This is a collection of texts presented in order
of publication. Apparently, it is connected
with Negotiations, and there is even another
collection—Two Regimes of Madness and other texts.
Chapter one Desert
Islands
[Parisian salon stuff]. There are two kinds
of islands, both in science and
imagination—continental ones and oceanic ones,
ones which split from continents, and ones which
emerge from underwater eruptions. All sorts
of gripping and flowery commentary ensue—we
normally expect islands to be deserted, because
they are either before or after human
existence. There is always a place in
mythology and imagination, based on dreams of
separation or starting from scratch. In this
sense, they relate to the origins of human beings
in mythology, reflecting both human separation
from nature and human creativity. The notion
of a deserted island does not just refer to the
lack of people, but to their separation, their
continued awareness of the island as deserted—in
some circumstances, this desertedness can become
sacred, the dream of human beings, their awareness
of being uncommon, 'absolutely separate, absolute
creators, in short, an Idea of humanity, a
prototype' (11) [we can start to see echoes of the
essay in Logic of
Sense, on human beings encountering
nature at its most raw, unmediated by
others?]. This idea of some fundamental
origin and unity with nature arises in collective
imagination.
Although geography tends to downgrade the desert
island, it is important in human imagination as a
kind of 'egg of the sea'. Mythology has
always been important, as an example of something
that has been created by humans but no longer
understood. Literature is the same, based on
the 'misinterpretations' of consciousness
(12). This is shown in the classic novels of
the deserted island—Robinson and Suzanne and
the Pacific [a French text, by Giraudoux,
written in 1922]. Both of these indicate the
death of mythology, in the case of Robinson,
through a 'boring' theme of the value of property,
'the reconstitution of every day bourgeois
life from a reserve of capital' (12), affirming
'the close ties between capitalism and
Protestantism'. In the case of Suzanne,
nature provides a series of luxury as objects, but
she has nothing to create, and the objects are
meaningless or not connected with human relations,
like buying and selling or giving gifts.
What this shows us is that the deserted island
features recreation and new beginnings, 'a second
origin' (13), invoking a time of birth and rebirth
for the whole world, renewal after catastrophe
after an origin, as in the myth of the
flood. We can become aware of this at the
level of our own reproduction of life, via
appearance and reappearance of cycles, the origin
of 'the law of repetition, the law of the
series'. These second origins are seen as
something human, often in the form of 'exclusively
female communities… Such as the island of
Circe or Calypso' (14). It is this notion of
the second origin, and of something immemorial
that preceded them that makes deserted
islands meaningful.
[And then Professor Deleuze bade his fellow dinner
guests goodbye].
Chapter two Jean
Hyppolite's Logic and Existence
This was a commentary on Hegel and a new
interpretation. It argues that 'philosophy
must be ontology, it cannot be anything else; but
there is no ontology of essence, there is only an
ontology of sense' (15). In particular,
philosophy is not anthropology, 'the empirical
discourse of humanity in which the speaker and the
object of his speech are separate', where
reflection is on one side and being on the other,
so that movement is not the movement of the thing,
and subjectivity is a fact. Kant's notions
of reflection synthesises the identity of subject
and object, again by privileging the former,
making a synthesis of the imagination: 'he goes
beyond the psychological and the empirical, all
the while remaining within the
anthropological'. Thought is given, but
because objects presuppose thought. But
there is still no thing in itself.
In Hegel, this is an absolute identity 'between
what is given and what is presupposed'(16).
The movements between being and reflection arise
in the dialectic. Eventually, we will get to
absolute knowledge, but the conception of absolute
knowledge is already present, as moments of
consciousness. In other words, Being
is sense—we are not claiming a God like
knowledge of things in themselves [unlike Deleuze,
although he shrinks from claiming it is
absolute]. There is no separate world of
being. This is in fact an old argument,
already found in Plato, where the second world is
the sense of this world. Both he and Kant
would regard this as transcendental, however,
especially where 'the being of logic [depends on a
transcendental version of] the logical nature of
being'. Hyppolite reads Hegel in this way as
well. Sense does not strive to achieve the
knowledge of some absolute other or thing, but is
already available for development.
The problem is that absolute [philosophical,
logical] knowledge must include empirical
knowledge exclusively, and yet still be different
from empirical knowledge. Essentialism is
the usual answer to counter empiricism, but it is
still no more linked to reflection than simple
empiricism, and in this sense, both are opposed to
absolute knowledge as some kind of 'Total thought
that knows itself only in its determinations,
which are moments of form' (17) [we are back on
the familiar territory of saying the absolute
knowledge is really the same as empirical
knowledge, but these differences are produced by
Being itself—'my discourse is logically or
properly philosophical when I speak the sense of
what I say, and when Being thus speaks
itself. Such discourse, which is the
particular style of philosophy, cannot be other
than circular'. This is the opposite of the
anthropological stance [knowledge arises in Being,
the Absolute in hegelian terms].
This still leaves problems [!] based on the origin
of philosophy and its relation to history and the
development of human beings. There is a risk
of anthropologism again if we combine the two
histories too tightly, if sense is seen to
develop or become. All will be well, Deleuze
thinks, if we see both the development of humanity
and thought by seeing Being as 'identical to
difference, and which as such thinks itself and
reflects itself in humanity' (18). Hyppolite's
understanding is limited here, because he wants to
see difference as only a matter of contradiction,
relying on differences which are already
unified. Deleuze wants to argue for other
kinds of difference that do not 'go all the way to
contradiction, since contradiction would be less
and not more than difference' [and an obscure
argument ends this piece by talking about
expressions which show differences, and only
phenomenal aspects of expression which identify
contradictions].
Chapter three Instincts and Institutions
[The nearest he gets to any sort of
sociology. Fundamentally functionalist,
although he seems to have recognized some Marxist
problems as well].
Both the instincts and institutions are
'procedures of satisfaction' (19). Subjects
invents an original world extracted from elements
from the external world. The extent to which
this becomes 'artificial' produces different forms
of liberation from nature. That process
itself presupposes an existing milieu, either
species specific or institutional.
Institutions produce satisfaction—'sexuality finds
it in marriage and avarice in property'.
There are also secondary institutions such as the
State which presuppose institutionalized
behaviour. While law limits actions, the
institution provides 'a positive model for
action'[and then the bit that Hardt found in Deleuze's
reading of Hume—theories of law operate with
things like natural rights, outside the social,
and see the social as negative as in contract
theories, but a positive theory of the institution
sees the natural as providing negatives, needs, so
that society becomes 'essentially positive and
inventive'. This enables us to separate
tyranny, with lots of laws and few institutions,
and democracy. Tyrannical laws also operate
directly with people not on institutions.
However, the same sexual needs can result in a
number of institutions, producing 'the paradox of
society', (20) where institutions are procedures
of satisfaction, but these procedures are not
determined by natural tendencies. Such
tendencies are always 'constrained or harassed and
thus transformed, sublimated', even if this
produces neurosis. We have to ask a further
question—for whom is the actual institution
useful? For many, just a few 'the privileged
class', or for those who control the institution
'the bureaucracy'. This leaves sociology
with problems of explaining this particular form
of satisfaction. Is it 'the rituals of a
civilisation? The means of
production?'. This involves processes which
are not explained by tendencies or utility, but
something 'of which we are not conscious': thus
rituals embody the unconscious of the users [no
ideology?].
It is different with the instinct because that is
entirely determined by utility, 'except
beauty'. There are no instinctive
constraints, although the same instinct can
produce different behaviours in different species,
introducing another level of determinism—'species
specificity'. This produces a problem that
we can understand the effect of instinct at the
level of the individual or the species, another
version of the 'useful for whom question'.
The common problem is to explain the link between
tendencies and objects that satisfy them. At
the organic level, organisms require chemicals,
but find them in water and food. Sometimes
this is so well developed that it seems to provide
some original power of synthesis, but intelligence
can introduce variation. Even so, the
problem is to explain where this intelligence
comes from, given that it might require a long
period of time and some potetially lethal
experiments. [Then… He gets it…] 'We
are forced back on the idea of the intelligences
something more social than individual...What does
the social mean?' (21). The social must
provide some system of anticipation and
classification of natural elements—the institution
replaces the species. The institution
translates 'the demands of humanity' into actual
products [don't stop here Gilles, go on to ask
about how these products emerge]. The
mechanisms here are 'totemism and domestication',
for example [when classifying animals].
[Blimey! So near and yet so far!]
Chapter four Bergson, 1859-1941
Bergson created the concepts 'duration, memory, élan
vital and intuition'(22). We can start
by examining intuition. Bergson begins by
identifying the main form of mental activity as
organizing problems and separating out false
ones. Intuition was to be an adequate method
to eliminate false problems, seeing them as linked
to duration, a matter of time rather than
spaces. Intuition, when it becomes a
conscious method, examines the effects of
duration.
Intuition implies that something is
presented immediately rather than being
inferred. This raises the issue of
philosophy and science. Some philosophers
see science as adequate its own right, providing
knowledge that only needs to be criticised or
reflected upon. Bergson and others see
philosophy as offering quite another knowledge,
'and knowledge and a relationship that precisely
science hides from us' (23), because it never
considers the thing in itself, its interiority [a
familiar criticism of positivism, but based on
ontology]. In a way, this intuition is a
return, rediscovering something in things
themselves, requiring us to forget scientific
progress there can be seen as suffering from a
lapse of memory. We have to identify matter
as 'that in being which prepares and accompanies
space, intelligence and science'. Science
grasps one characteristic of being, one of the two
movements of nature which involves actualization,
and, properly developed, it can arrive at a total
comprehension.
Bergson operates with two movements, rather than
two worlds, one in which the movement congeals in
its products, produces something that interrupts
movement, and the other which works the other way
around, and 'rediscovers in the product the
movement from which it resulted' (24). It is
the first movement that tends to be seen as
natural, and the latter that has to be
rediscovered: the latter provides the first
movement. We must not think of movement is
made up of instants, which are really only
'virtual cessations'. It follows that the
present tense is equally misleading, since
presents are already produced by movements—the
past is what used to be, and it is linked to the
present, 'in the same duration, the one beneath
the other, and not the one after the
other' (24). The normal senses of present
and past time are produced by the same process: it
is the same world.
What is the immediate? If science focuses
only on the immediate, it risks losing an aspect
of being, especially 'the difference of the thing,
that which makes its being, that which makes
it this rather than that'(24). This is
the source of false problems such as questioning
why there is something rather than nothing, or
order rather than disorder. These false
problems take the immediate as indicating
something general, working with 'an immobile
ensemble' which can only be contrasted with
nothingness, which has no movement except in the
form of contradiction, order and disorder for
example. The unity of contradictory terms
like that would never produce an adequate grasp of
being, and has led to being being seen as an
abstraction.
Bergson is far more interested in questions such
as why something exists rather than something
else, why things have the proportion that they do,
why a particular perception invokes a particular
memory. Being for him is difference, not
immovable or undifferentiated and not
contradiction. 'Being is the difference
itself of the thing, what Bergson often calls the
nuance'(25), and it leads to a new form of
empiricism, one that produces concepts that are
properly adequate to things, possibly only to one
thing. We should not search for
generalities, but focus on individual things and
existences, and then trace the characteristics of
these things back to the source, 'the universal
light'. Science and metaphysics often allow
difference to escape [through generalisation or
abstraction]. We do need notions of
resemblance and opposition, but as a 'practical,
and not ontological categories', and seeking
resemblances should not dominate our theoretical
efforts.
It follows that we are after a particular kind of
difference, not an empirical one, 'a purely
exterior relation' in space, nor the kind of
difference that is determined by
contradiction. Rather, we should see things
as subject to alteration [rather than to strict
alterity], the alteration of substance.
Being is the alteration of substance.
Duration refer is to that which changes nature or
quality so that it differs from itself. The
mechanism involves 'a certain relaxation or
tension of duration'(26). So far, then,
intuition is a method that seeks difference at the
virtual level, something that articulates the
real. Science has been misled by focusing on
differences of degree rather than real difference,
and this only covers differences of nature.
Scientific methods can only grasp these
differences of degree, because differences of
nature are not immediately perceptible, [almost a
notion of scientific ideology here, but no
explorations of the politics of science] and we
must look for them within things not between
things, as different tendencies. Things are
never pure, but always composites: 'only the
tendency is pure', which gives it some sort of
greater reality.
Intuition divides composites into different
tendencies. This explains the dualisms in
Bergson, including those in the titles of his
book: 'quantity and quality, intelligence and
instinct, geometrical order and vital order,
science and metaphysics, the closed and the open
are its most known figures'. These dualisms
always lead back to matter and duration seen as
two movements, two tendencies 'like relaxation and
contraction'. Actually, only one of the tendencies
is pure or simple, and the other is seen as
introducing a disturbing impurity. In any
composite thing, only one characteristic will lead
us to duration. Duration shows us
difference, 'whereas matter is only the
undifferentiated, that which is repeated…
That which can no longer change its nature'
(27). In this way, the apparent dualisms are
in fact [rank ordered] —one half 'contains in
itself the secret of the other'. In this
way, duration first differs in itself and from
itself, so that the differences introduced by
matter are 'still essentially of duration'.
Duration encounters matter as a contrary movement
or obstacle that interrupts its 'impulse (élan)'.
Matter [actualization] introduces differences of
degree, but duration also is 'susceptible to
degrees because it is that which differs with
itself'[so here we are weaselling around again
between empirical differences that are different
even though they belong to the same thing. See May
in Boundas and Olkowski
for a good critique]. Matter is 'the lowest'
kind of degree of difference, only difference of
degree.
Nevertheless, it is important to show why matter
persists, why 'its vibrations still [occupy]
multiple instances', and this is a certain degree
of duration itself. Duration is differentiated in
two directions, and one way produces matter.
Duration contracts and expands, and when it
expands, it produces matter. This reconciles
dualism and monism.
It follows that intuition can not simply 'follow
natural articulations', but must pursue lines of
differentiation. This will lead to a
discovery of duration as a simple process, 'a
convergence of probabilities', 'what is simple,
indivisible… what persists'. In this
way, intuition confirms duration, as an élan
vital. Bergsten's work on evolution
demonstrates this, or with a process of
differentiation producing real differences, as
something which is 'realised actualised or
made'(28), in the form of divergent series, lines
of evolution. Élan vital is
duration itself as it is actualised, it is
difference passing into act. Other
approaches in biology such as mechanism and
finalism impose points of view on the emergence of
difference, and see it as a matter of the relation
between actual terms themselves. Duration is
virtuality. Here, Bergson moves away from
the notion of duration as a subjective
phenomenon. Here, it is 'the mode of being,
and is, moreover, in a way, being itself'.
'To be actualized is always the act of a whole
that does not become entirely actual at the same
time, in the same place, or in the same thing;
consequently it produces species that differ in
nature'.
[Luckily], 'it is the essence of the virtual to be
actualised', and we can grasp this by seeing
duration as memory, something that 'prolongs the
past in the present'. [So, is memory being used as
a handy illustration? As a useful rhetorical ploy?
] Again there are two movements, one where the
present reveals the effects of the past as
well. There is also empirical memory
('recollection memory') and some more essential
form ('contraction memory') (29). The latter
kind suggests that the past itself survives, and
not just as a subjective resource, not just
psychologically. The past has survived, but
it is simply that it has ceased to be
useful. This avoids false problems about how
the past is connected to the present [where it is
seen as simply something that was present, so how
does it pass --etc]. The past is the
unconscious, or the virtual, not something that
only exists after the present, but something that
'coexists with itself as present'. This
helps us see how the past can affect the present,
how it becomes present as well as past. The
past and the present are best seen in terms of two
forms of duration, one relaxed and one
contracted—the present is the most contracted and
the past stretches out from it like a cone in the
operations of our subjective, even though the
whole of it is actually available—'everything is
there, but everything coexist with
everything'. It is this coexistence which is
virtual.
Only this virtual coexistence can produce real
[actual?] successions. Only intuition can
grasp this, going beyond idealism and realism, the
exterior and the interior. Coexistence is
the key. Degrees of coexistence make
duration both virtual and capable of actualization
and differentiation. [It seems possible that
the actualization can also work in
reverse—'actually divergent series give birth to,
in duration, coexistent virtual degrees'
(30)]. We can even see intelligence and
instinct as two divergent series coexisting in
duration as 'different degrees of relaxation or of
contraction'. Duration initially appeared as
a psychological reality, but this is 'only our
duration, that is to say, a certain well
determined degree'. It would be a mistake to try
and explain this subjective duration.
Rather, one should 'inhabit it initially through
an effort of intuition'. When we do this, we
become aware of the tension in [our subjective]
duration 'whose determination itself appears as
the choice among an infinity of possible
durations'.
Overall, Bergson argues that not everything is
given in immediate facts, that the immediate
presupposes a movement that invents it, and we
cannot grasp this movement 'in the image of the
given'. This mistake arises in certain
conceptions of the possible. The virtual is
different—it is the whole, which need not be
completely detectable in the image of actual
things. Actual species differ from each
other, even though they are actualizations [which
seems to suggest a form of transcendental
deduction as the appropriate method, whereby one
examines a range of different things and tries to
deduce what it is that underpins them.
Deleuze would not accept the idea that this
underlying whole is transcendental in the usual
sense, however, not something that belongs to
another world].
The present is only a contracted degree of the
past which coexists with it, and this has an
implication for the future, since it shows that
the past can change nature and project it
forward. This explains Bergson's continual
'hymn in praise of the new, the unforeseeable, of
invention, of liberty' (30-31). This shows
the potential of philosophy to 'attain the thing
itself beyond the order of the possible'[and is
the basis of Deleuze's own phantasy
politics]. It goes beyond causality and
possibility which always are connected to actual
things in themselves and which assume [that all
relevant variables are pinned down]. Bergson
stresses indeterminacy by contrast, not to
celebrate irrationality, but to argue for a
broader sense of reason 'the true reason of the
thing in the process of being made', philosophical
reason stressing difference. The whole
system is displayed well in Matter and Memory—there
is a difference of nature between the past or
present, and between duration and matter, and it
is a mistake to work with what is immediately
given, 'a badly analysed composite' (31).
When exploring what a difference of nature
actually is, he shows that 'duration itself is
this difference', with matter as the most relaxed
degree. There are degrees of coexistence in
duration. We can add a dimension of time by
saying that duration 'is always differentiating
itself into past and present'.
We can find similar themes in English empiricism,
but Bergson's method was new.
[I can't go back now, but I think the terms
relaxed and expanded are used differently in
different examples?]
Chapter five Bergson's Conception of Difference
[I found this one slightly more obscure although
it covers similar ground to the one above]
Bergson's achievement is to focus on the
philosophy of difference, both in methodological
and ontological terms. In the first place,
we need to understand the differences between
things and things themselves properly, without
reducing them. In the second place if
difference is so important to being, it must tell
us something important about being. Both
tendencies are at work.
Previous philosophers have not understood natural
differences, and mixed them up with differences of
degree [the latter confusion includes not
realizing that differences between matter and the
perception of matter are only differences of
degree]. More commonly, differences of
nature have been grasped as differences of degree,
which is embarrassing because philosophy
claims 'to grasp the thing itself'(32), in other
words to decide how it differs from everything
else, internally. Internal difference is
hard to grasp, but it clearly is a feature, unless
we are to see difference as only ever exterior,
somehow outside things. It is common for
general ideas to offer composite groups when they
generalize [and the example is types of pleasure,
which have only in common the fact that human
beings have the same practical interest in them
and act towards them in the same way]. We
need to find proper differences of nature.
We know they exist because 'there exists
differences of nature between things of the same
genus' (33) [does he mean different types of
antelope? Surely these differences are
themselves relative, depending on what one sees as
a common features of the genus of antelopes in the
first place? Are differences of gender an
exception, a real difference in nature?]. If
philosophy is not interested in these differences
of nature, Bergson argues, this leaves it only
with the role of commenting upon or criticising
unreflected generalities provided by other
disciplines [can't have that]. Instead,
philosophy must find appropriate concepts that
grasp objects alone, even if this means that
concepts only applies to one thing. 'This
unity of the thing and the concept is internal
difference, which one reaches through the
differences of nature' (33). [not a very
helpful definition--replace 'is' with 'is based
on'? ].
Intuition is enjoyable [Spinozan joy?] because it
leads us to see difference. It actually
involves 'a plurality of acts, a plurality of
efforts and directions' (33). It first tries
to determine differences of nature, differences
between things. [empirical] Reality can be a
guide here since it already provides articulations
and distributions of things. However these
articulations are produced by 'factual lines',
which must also be intuited. These are best
seen as 'directions to be followed', lines of
probability, and Deleuze says that this can look
like positivism. Consciousness
[understanding?] is the result of factual lines
converging: intuition takes the form of an
hypothesis. We attempt to grasp the
articulations of the real in an empiricist manner,
and then to cross check it through hypothesising
factual lines. Both are consistent with each
other—empirical study of the real shows us the
differences of nature between things, while
intuiting factual lines 'show us the thing itself
identical to its difference, internal difference
identical to something'(34) [a Bergsonian notion
of essence? Eidetic variation?]
An overemphasis on genre 'is like lying to
philosophy'(34). Science simply relies on
differences of degree, while old metaphysics has
misunderstood the problem as differences of
intensity. Scientists operate as they do as
a result of 'conjugated operations of need, social
life and language, intelligence and space, though
space is what the intelligence makes of the matter
that lends itself to intelligence'[can't allow any
autonomy for intelligence]. In other words,
they offer utilitarian groupings, but this 'cannot
ground what makes it possible in the first
place'. [Do philosophers operate with
different conjugations?] Differences of
nature are already involved although not grasped,
because they appear in a non spatial form [and
apparently Bergson renders differences in terms of
some primeval numbering]. Experience and
understanding grasps only already formed
products. Things themselves differ in other
ways, not just those of proportion. Nor do
their characteristics differ in nature. What
differs are [not easily perceived] tendencies,
including tendencies to develop, as in biological
evolution. Even causes arise from
tendencies, since they are already 'derived
retroactively from the product itself'. Only
when things are separated from their tendencies in
thought, and causes substituted, do we arrive at
differences of degree [an equally 'correct status
of things' -- we don't want to diss
science?]. As an example, human brains as
products differ from animal brains as a matter of
degree, but when considered as a result of
tendencies, there is 'a complete difference of
nature' (35). Much depends on the point of
view [which starts to look a bit perspectival?].
'Things, products, results are always
composite'. Only composites appear in space
and can be grasped by intelligence, and they can
be understood in terms of apparent opposites, such
as closed and open, perception and
affection. Composites arise from tendencies
combined in such a way that the combination is
inaccessible. 'The homogeneous is by
definition composite', and only tendencies are
pure and simple. We have to grasp tendencies
if we are interested in proper notions of
difference. We should study composites in
order to arrive at 'tendency as the sufficient
reason of proportion'. We can also explain
evolution as the development of particular
tendencies and the characteristics associated with
them.
Metaphysics fail to grasp this except in terms of
differences of intensity [and it seems this is
where we get the metaphors of matter as relaxation
or lessening of being, with perfection at one end
and nothingness at the other]. Here, false
originating ideas are to blame, such as disorder
or nothingness. Ultimately, though, 'the
illusion of intensity at bottom depends on the
illusion of space'—so there is one problem at the
bottom of it all, which is the failure to
distinguish differences of nature from those of
degree.
Intuition can be guided by noting that 'tendencies
that come in paired opposites differ in nature',
and this opposition is at the heart of the
emergence of beings as expressions of tendencies
[sounds awfully like the dialectic]. We can
then divide composites into two tendencies, going
beyond a mere spatial analysis [distributions and
empirical generalizations] and description of
experience. We are not committed to
transcendental analysis, however, since tendencies
are given, lived, there is no distinction between
the absolute and the lived. This means that
we can experience these tendencies, and we can
limit intuition to reflecting upon 'the conditions
of real experience', not just speculating about
all possible forms of experience. This makes
Bergsonism 'a superior empiricism' (36).
This limit helps us seek concepts that are
identical to objects [not something
speculative]. An idea of sufficient reason
is at work here, says Deleuze—'reason must reach
all the way to the individual, the genuine concept
all the way to the thing, and comprehension all
the way to [a grasp of the] "this"' (36). We
want to know why this exists and not that, why a
perception calls up a particular recollection and
resonates with others. Bergson calls this
kind of reason nuance—there are no accidents,
everything is produced by nuance and we only
understand this once we find the concept that fits
objects themselves: until then, we are forced to
use several concepts to explain composite objects
and their proportions. Grasping tendencies
provides both a unified concept and a fully
explained object, one that is not just contingent.
However it is difficult to proceed from empirical
mixtures to tendencies [since we can't assume that
the proportion of empirical elements indicates the
proportion of tendencies]. Is there a
dominant tendency? There must [!] be because
it is the only one that can provide the unique
concept, while the other is better understood as a
kind of impurity that compromises and opposes the
dominant tendency [ie we want to eliminate
dualism]. Having said that, Bergson proceeds
to make some assertions—animal behaviour shows
instinct is the dominant tendency, human behaviour
intelligence, a perception is the pure tendency,
affection adds impurities. Is there a
rule? In the past, philosophers like Plato
relied on the idea of some transcendent Good
to produce the right choice, but Bergson 'refuses
help from finality, as though he wanted the method
of difference to be self sufficient' (37).
We need to think again about what the difference
is between tendencies. At the moment it
looks like another external difference. We
have only arrived at external differences again
using intuition, and some of Bergson's arguments
seem to operate like this—for example space is a
composite of matter and duration, the two
tendencies. [We cannot have external differences
since we would have to keep going to explain their
origin and the laws of their operation,which wold
presumably end in transcendentalism and
speculation -- hence the recourse to monism]
However, it is not just that matter is a
relaxation and duration or contraction, as some
eternal difference between tendencies.
Instead, we can argue that duration itself
produces differences internally [that slippery
notion of difference again, as discussed in Boundas]. So
Bergson eventually argues that duration differs
from itself, while matter 'is what repeats
itself'. The same point is made in a
discussion of intensity, where differences of
intensity are themselves generated by the
properties of sensation [pass].
Consciousness also generates differences—'in the
life of the psyche there is always otherness
without there being number or several'.
There are different types of movement, but 'the
essence of this movement… is
alteration… Qualitative change'.
Duration is a thing or substance that differs from
itself. It follows [!] that 'real time is
alteration, and alteration is substance [ that is
produced by a substance]'. The differences
of nature are themselves the result of this
substance, not simply produced by the difference
between two tendencies: [the very opposition of
tendencies is a part of nature]. This is
what we should really perceive when we start to
analyze composites, not only that there are two
tendencies, but the the difference between them is
produced by one of them. 'Difference has
become a substance' (38), and movement is also
substantial, not just a characteristic of
something else, presupposing nothing else.
[Then a difficult implication—duration is
difference of self with itself, 'and what differs
from itself is, in an unmediated
[emphasized] way, the unity of substance and
subject'. Does this mean human subjects?
Shouldn't it be objects? The bit below on human
consciousness suggests he meant human subjects
too].
Thus we should always choose duration as the
dominant tendency, and we should see detectable
aspects of the object as nuances [other
possibilities] [There is a strange recurrent
notion here of a left and a right side—I don't
think it has any particular significance, but I
think Deleuze is referring to the right side as
the purer of the two]. It is still difficult
because sometimes duration, in the form of the
elan vital, puts instinct above intelligence
['places intelligence on the left side' (38)] for
animals, expressing itself as instincts. In
human beings, intelligence is 'on the right side',
still an expression of duration although in the
human form. Intelligence is matter, for
Bergson, because it dominates matter, and gives us
the unique sense of duration [I still think this
is a bit unnecessarily philosophical—surely our
intelligence reveals to us that matter is affected
by duration, I don't see the need to say that
therefore it is matter, except for rhetorical
purposes]. Duration has these nuances,
because it differentiates itself from itself—and
matter is only a 'final nuance of duration'.
What is implied is that difference is not just
between two tendencies, but rather itself one of
the tendencies, and 'always on the right
side'. External differences reflect internal
differences [in silly philosophical rhetoric
'External difference has become internal
difference']. This is what helps us to
analyze things both ways, following the
articulations of the real and the factual lines
which emerge, and then tracing these factual lines
back to give us a convergent understanding of the
real so that we can separate out such matters as
what belongs to subjects and what to
objects. External differences affect only
appearances. We can already get some clues
about matters such as differences in nature as
opposed to differences of degree, but we cannot
see that duration is indivisible, and a substance,
that alteration is going on without becoming
plurality or contradiction. This is the difference
between Bergson and advocates of the dialectic,
whether Plato or Hegel. There can be
differences which do not 'go as far as
contradiction' (39), which are more profound, and
which are not easily grasped from the
outside. Internal difference is what becomes
absolute. [Renewed a couple of pages later:
Bergson would not accept the principle of finality
in Plato, as we saw above, where the Good is the
ultimate rule to govern choice. Bergson
rejects this finality on the same grounds that he
rejects empirical studies of appearances—both
should be replaced with the notion of duration,
difference as a thing in itself. The same
idea of primary difference would lead him to
reject Hegel, who sees difference as appearing by
contrast to things which an object is not, which
introduces an external determination, and the
method of constantly seeking contradictory
tendencies: the latter leads to a purely abstract
conception of difference, not one based on
tendencies in varying composites {this is the
argument that Deleuze himself advances in Difference and
Repetition}. It is an
abstraction compared to the concepts of
differences of degree and nuance. It is 'one
of the numerous retrospective
illusions'(42). What is really happening is
that a simple virtuality is actualizing itself,
and we see those effects in actual composite
things, although we cannot easily grasped primary
difference itself. There is no role for the
negative in Bergson—what looks like the emergence
of negations is really 'the positive actualization
of a virtuality that contains both terms at
once… It is our ignorance of the virtual
that makes us believe in contradiction and
negation' (42-3). The differences inherent
in duration are more profound and more primary]
Can we read off the characteristics of the two
tendencies produced by duration? We should
be able to, because even when duration produces
differences, it is still duration, these
differences are not total, as that which we find
in composites. Duration is differentiating
itself. There is therefore a double
differentiation found in composites—between that
which shows duration and that which does not, and
then differences within duration itself.
'Space is broken up into matter and duration, but
duration differentiates itself into contraction
and relaxation; and relaxation is the principle of
matter' (39) [I have always thought this should be
the other way about]. Similarly organic
forms have both matter and élan vital, but élan
vital also differentiates itself into instinct and
intelligence, and then intelligence transforms
matter into space. We have to further
examine this second kind of differentiation.
Bergson argues that duration both splits itself up
into fluxes, and then concentrates itself 'in a
single current' [although this still looks like a
matter of points of view]. He turns to the
concept of virtuality—in discussing memory, for
example the indivisible is not static, but rather
changes its nature when it divides, and it is 'the
virtual or the subjective' that changes its
nature. In Creative
Evolution, we see the notion of life
itself as the process of difference, including the
differentiation of species. Bergson wants to
argue that this is internal difference, not
something caused externally, and it never operates
as a simple determination, since this would be to
imply a relation between causes and ends or
coincidences, which would reintroduce
externalities. Instead, vital difference is
'indetermination itself' (40), producing
unforeseeable consequences. These are not
just accidents, though—the élan vital is the
source of variation. So differentiation does
come from actual encounters with matter, but it
also is produced by 'the explosive internal force
which life carries within itself', conceived
as working like a spray [sic] . The life
force itself powers this differentiation.
[However, Deleuze wants to argue that we can
generalize from the creation and evolution of
living beings, to the level of virtuality itself,
which must 'dissociate itself to actualize
itself']. This life force can produce more
concrete structures, such as organs, which are
produced through different means [so empirical
forces can have effects on matter once
actualised?], producing 'Divergence of series,
identity of particular apparatuses: this is the
double movement of life as a whole'. So we
get a combination of divergence and resemblance,
and indeed, in biology, resemblance is important
because it shows the same virtual being
actualised, 'the essence subsisting in change,
just as divergence shows that change itself at
work in the essence'[without this reservation, it
would be impossible to explain how divergent
series end with similar results, like the
development of eyes? We seem to have a closed
circle though, where both resemblances and
differences are produced by the same process?].
Bergson further introduces historical
differentiation, because divergent species can
never be fused back together. With human
history, it is different, since the same
individuals or societies [no need to differentiate
between them?] are those that evolve and can
sometimes go back. This is a result of self
consciousness, unique to humans. Even so, we
mustn't exaggerate its influence, since what it is
brought to consciousness is often 'what is already
there'. Indeed, human consciousness is a
part of duration, and there is a non human
consciousness in life itself. When human
beings change as a result of their consciousness,
they are only reanimating this latent force.
Human history only shows the reemergence of
consciousness, 'once it has traversed
matter'(41). What memory does is to
reconcile consciousness with past
differentiation. It follows that by
exploring memory, we can grasp the nature of pure
differentiation. [Too many simple analogies
between the workings of human consciousness and
the workings of duration?].
[Picking up on the critique of Hegel above].
Differentiation is important, but there is
something more profound, 'an action, an
actualization'[with a lovely philosophical
argument—otherwise 'there would be no reason to
speak of a concept of difference'] (43).
There is a first [primary?] differentiation in
that the virtual splits. As a result, the
objects that are subsequently produced can be
explained in terms of causes or reasons relating
back to this primary process or concept of
differentiation. Bergson develops a helpful
analogy here based on the concept of colour.
We can take actual colours and then abstract from
them a general idea or concept of colour.
Here, the concept is more general than the
objects, and those objects are subsumed under the
concept. In Bergsonian terms, we are talking
about spatial distinctions, external differences
to the objects themselves. What we should do
instead is make the colours converge [the reverse
of splitting up white light with a prism] and we
can then arrive at pure white light that is
responsible for the different colours, where they
are nuances or degrees of the concept. Here
we have the relation of participation. White
light is 'still a universal, but the concrete
universal, which gives us an understanding of the
particular because it is the far end of the
particular' (43). The concept itself has
been actualised in its nuances—'the concept itself
has become a thing… A universal thing…
A concrete thing, not a genus or a
generality'. We have arrived at the concept
not by examining the resemblance of objects, but
rather the difference between them, the thing that
explains their relation, internal
difference. This is a 'superior
philosophical goal', and we had to abandon
empirical thinking, in particular 'Spatial
differences had to be replaced by temporal
differences'. We have here a process whereby
concepts become concrete things, which are nuances
present within the concept.
We have also now seen how difference is connected
to time. What consciousness does is fairly
'modest', connecting successive moments, and
thereby making 'contact with matter' (44).
'The distinctions between subject and object, body
and mind, are temporal and so a matter of
degree'. We can now understand what the
virtual is, a pure concept of difference
containing coexisting degrees and nuances.
Bergson says that the virtual is the most profound
concept, and it has three aspects—'duration,
memory, and elan vital'. Duration is
'difference from itself', memory grasps the
coexistence of degrees of difference, elan vital
is the process of subsequent
differentiation of these nuances. Memory
plays an important part in constructing objective
consistencies, and these enable actualization, the
virtual actualizes itself through life 'in a vital
form', but only to the extent that degrees of
difference already coexisted inside it.
Again we see that concrete differentiation is
'less profound than the theory of nuances or
degrees'[which justifies the move from specific
discussions of consciousness, say, to a general
ontology].
We have a positive mode of existence in that
duration differentiates itself. It is not
psychological as such, but represented in the
psychological. The virtual itself provides
what is, and it is something that must 'act only
by differentiating itself, by ceasing to be in
itself, even as it keeps something of its
origin'. We must operate at the pure level
rather than the actualised, and we can develop
pure recollection not confined to what has been
actualised. Again it is not just a
psychological process being described here,
something that follows perception, since the past
and present coexist for Bergson. What pure
recollection aims at is pure difference, while
normal recollections develop resemblances between
actualised objects. We can gain this pure
recollection through dreams [seriously?—'It is
enough to dream to gain access to this world where
nothing resembles anything else', (45)].
In the present, we seek resemblances, but
philosophical recollection preserves the past and
its role, and shows us the inadequacy of ordinary
thought, since we can see that subsequent moments
always contain something else, previous moments
and the recollection which they leave behind
[again all this is perfectly understandable if
we're just talking about the workings of human
consciousness]. Memory constantly prolongs
the past into the present, sometimes in the form
of 'the increasingly heavy baggage one drags along
as one grows older'. It is memory that makes
the will to change possible, since we can decide
not to reproduce the past, so there is a sense in
which difference is responsible for the present
and 'the new that is coming about' (45).
This process often produces 'a strange impression:
that of acting and being acted on the same time'.
Another way of thinking of this process is to say
that the present moments are joined to previous
moments in the form of a contraction [Schutz would call it a
synthesis]. Contraction means something
special connected to duration. It is a
process that is not just repetition, something
self sufficient. Contraction makes simple
repetition impossible. Can this be
generalised? Bergson discusses Hume and the
problem of induction. In order to perform in
induction, you have to generate an expectation of
something new arising from a sequence of similar
cases. Hume saw this as a form of
habit. Bergson also sees this something new
is being produced in the mind, a form of mental
fusion, 'a contraction that occurs in the
mind'. This is a double process, though
because something distinct also remains in the
understanding, and this also helps minds grasp the
concept of space.
We are now or in a position to return to the
initial arguments about differences of degrees and
differences of nature. We now know that
differences of nature arise from two tendencies,
one of which is dominant or privileged, and which
differentiates itself in the form of [primary]
differentiations. These primary ones are
also differences of nature, although there are
also external ones in nature. Bergson agrees
that science has made great progress in studying
these external differences, in a form of
'infinitesimal analysis' (46). However,
there is also pure recollection, where dreamers
[!] immerse themselves in particulars so as to
arrive at pure differences,
and this is somehow unifying with matter
itself. It is not just studying empirical
repetitions that lead us to generalities.
Empirical repetitions are abstractions, also forms
of 'contraction of the mind' (47), and they only
focus on aspects of particularity, the repeated
bits. In this way, we can get all witty and
philosophical, and say the repetition is itself a
kind of difference, one which is actually
'indifferent to itself', that is disinterested in
general properties, including nuances, and general
ideas.
In the same witty spirit, we saw that managing
difference is an act of contraction anyway.
Going back to memory, we can see that recollection
identifies both differences, in its pure form, and
similarities in its mundane recollections.
This shows [to the philosopher anyway] that the
mind operates with degrees of contraction,
operating at different levels, and with different
notions of difference and repetition. These
levels and processes are interconnected, in that
contractions that produce relations of identity
themselves go on to present something new, or
difference. The same processes and acts of
mind operate at different levels, in other words,
as in the famous example of the sections of a
cone.
Subjective memory, or psychic repetition, is a
virtual kind, achieving consistency only through
mental forms of repetition, having no independent
existence. Duration also has a real
coexistence, real successions, operating with
matter, and offering 'the simple material of the
simultaneity: real coexistence,
juxtaposition'. Deleuze thinks that despite
these differences, the underlying model of changes
in tension and energy can offer an entire
'cosmology' (48). The differences between
mind and matter can simply be seen as aspects of
duration, and it is our task as philosophers to
grasp this 'infinite diversity of relaxations and
contractions'. [And this upside
down notion of particularity being seen as
relaxation—again I can see how this works in the
form of memory where personal memories relax,
expand and ramify. Deleuze wants to say that
where these memories are contracted, we end with
banality]. After all, sections of the cone
have a common basis. We manage the present
by denying particularity and seeking resemblance
or even universality. But this is still only
one extreme.
We can therefore see matter and duration in terms
of extreme levels of both relaxation and
contraction. Duration also has different
levels of relaxation and contraction, in the form
of 'pure past and present... memory and
perception'. Between the extremes there are
intermediate degrees, of generality, for example
between the particular and the pure.
Empirical generalisations focus on resemblance and
are therefore a contraction, while general ideas
[philosophical ones], operate with 'a dynamic
whole, an oscillation [between action and
memory]'. These degrees of generality can be
connected [in a form of transcendental deduction],
so that noticing and opposition between two
generalisations or memories can lead to the
identification of tendencies or movements which
are seen as genuinely different. We see this
when we consider the relation between the present
and the past, which are distinct, but also part of
a whole. This explains the famous phrase
about duration splitting 'into two symmetrical
streams', one falling back towards the past and
the other projected to the future, with the
present as 'the most contracted degree of the
past… [And thus also]… an imminent
future' (49). [As in the production of the
new]
Thus we see how difference produces something new,
but we need to think this further [sigh].
New thinking of the kind above [what I have called
transcendental deduction] leads us to the general
idea of the hole and its differentiations.
At the level of consciousness, this sort of
general thinking joins recollections and actions,
improves the images of the past in order to make
them active in the present. We're talking
here about particulars being emphasised in
universals, as leaving 'room for voluntary and
free action'[in the interests of dereification,
the breaking of habit]. [This seems to be
the basis for human potential for free action,
because a human being 'simultaneously comes and
goes from the universal to the particular, opposes
them, and puts the particular in the
universal… simultaneously thinks, desires,
recollects'.
Overall Bergson can look vague and incoherent,
because difference is unforeseeable and
indeterminate, and some notions seem to be
condemned only to be rescued, such as the idea of
degrees of difference [rejected, surely if they
are seen a self sufficient rather than leading to
some purer thought?]. He is against the
notion of intensity in your relaxation and
contraction seem to be similar. He opposes
the negative, but still uses the idea, even if
only as an interruption to positive flows, and
when discussing the opposition of science and
philosophy. However, he can still be rescued
[that old philosophical goal of reinstating people
to the canon]. Bergson insists on
translating differences of degree into degrees of
[some more fundamental] difference [witty chiasm
now?]. We need to separate these rather than
take them as red and generalize about them.
Differences of degree are the lowest forms of
difference, resulting ultimately from duration, a
difference of and in nature itself. We
should see these differences as expressing
extremes [close to dialect again?] [Relaxation and
contraction?]. Differences between
relaxation and contraction are not exactly the
same as differences of intensity, but are better
seen as the inverse of each other, not both kinds
of the same force of intensity, itself arising
from some eternal underlying Being. For
Bergson there is only duration which is relaxed or
contracted, and this explains the differences of
intensity. Overall, philosophy must begin
with difference, and with the major difference of
nature—duration, which eventually produces
matter. 'Difference is the genuine
beginning'(50). We must not begin with some
stable Being which is indifferent. However,
inversion looks like negativity and
opposition. Bergson wants to overcome this
by suggesting that there is a virtuality that
contains both apparently opposing terms: these
terms become apparent in actualization.
Actualization itself produces intermediate degrees
of generality, such as the different forms of
recollection. Overall, Bergson can be
rescued from incoherence by this insistence on
fundamental difference. Even his apparent
indetermination should not be seen as something
vague, but rather something that permits a number
of contingent results from processes like the elan
vital. He does not support indetermination
in the sense of refusing to explain actualizations
in the name of some belief in pure
possibility. We need to work from duration
right down to particularity, not stopping at the
level of general causality.
Chapter six Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Precursor of
Kafka, Celine and Ponge
We underestimate great writers by failing to see
how apparent in coherences result from a deeper
logic, and by failing to see the humour in the
writing. This applies to Rousseau.
Rousseau's argument that humans are naturally good
is part of his general logical argument that
qualities of meanness are not natural. In
the natural state, human beings relate to things
as well as with each other, and lived largely in
isolation from each other, even although we have
to engage in sexuality [and apparently, Rousseau
writes about this with humour]. As a result,
we also had limited needs, and thus acquired 'a
kind of self sufficiency'(52) and
equilibrium. Meanness only arises with
society and the notion of profits or compensation,
social interests, and relations of
oppression. Rousseau foreshadowed Engels
here in arguing that violence and oppression
presupposes a civil state and economic and social
relations. Even Robinson only enslaved
Friday by drawing upon his small stock of capital
and his notions of the means of production.
In social relations, it is often in our interests
to be mean, and this is sometimes misunderstood as
natural. However, meanness is usually
imposed upon us—if we know we are someone's error,
we often unconsciously wish for their deaths, and
circumstances often makers depart from
virtue. Even beautiful souls often encounter
ambiguity as its 'destiny' (53). This is a
kind of black comedy, and this produces Rousseau's
gusto and joy. We often dream of fulfilling
human relationships, but these are rarely
realisable. Rousseau apparently sought some
Trinity—a loved woman loves another man who can be
a father or brother, or there are two women who
are loved, one being a strict and the other a
gentle mother. Actual situations, however,
always turn out badly. Rousseau displays that
combination of 'manias and bizarre behaviours'
which enables him to combine ideas and feelings
(54), typical of poets and philosophers [and
examples of philosophers' eccentricities include
Kant who apparently invented an elaborate shoe
holder, or Rousseau's Armenian outfit].
We can avoid situations which push us into
meanness, through acts of will, such as refusing
to become an heir, or refusing compensation if
one's partner dies. But this is difficult to
do, and Rousseau was probably too weak
himself. He was forced to use other 'subtle
devices', to play on bad health, say, in a
humourous way [one anecdote turns on him claiming
bladder trouble which would prevent his attendance
on the king, where he might be offered a pension
in exchange for some service]. Above all
though, we must remember the past that has
produced a tempting situation, and even to repeat
it in order to make it profane and not sacred and
compelling. This also helps us set our
priorities instead of giving ways to passion in
the present.
In Emile and the Social Contract,
we find the two poles of Rousseau's work.
The root of evil is that we have become 'motivated
by profit' (55), and thus have acquired an
interest in being mean, and have been propelled
interrelationships of oppression. In Emile,
we have a private individual who has withdrawn,
and in the Social Contract, a renewed
citizen. Both restore the natural
relationship with things, and therefore preserve
human relationships not nasty ones of
oppression. 'True pedagogical rectification
consists in subordinating human relations to the
relation of human beings to things' (55)—as in the
'famous rule from Emile which demands only muscle:
Never bring things to the child, bring the child
to the things'. This will avoid 'the [usual]
infantile situation that gives him a stake in
being mean'. The citizen by contrast has a
definite interest in being virtuous, aiming at the
reconciliation of justice and self interest, 'the
proper task of politics'. The citizen is
determined by the public, and the main power of
the Republic is legislative.
Chapter seven The Idea of Genesis in Kant's
Esthetics
Kant's third critique raises the problem of
different points of view, with the spectator
having a different aesthetics compared to the
creator, within aesthetics of the beautiful in
nature, and a different one in art, sometimes
classically inspired, sometimes
romantically. The problem is then to
establish some systematic unity by tracing the
relations between these different points of view.
Judgments of beauty require the use of both the
imagination and the understanding in the
spectator. They are not just preferences,
because there is a claim of 'a certain a priori
universality' (56), which links such judgment to
understanding and its procedures [its
'legality']. However, it is not a matter of
developing agreed concepts, but rather matters of
pleasure, and of singular objects which have no
concept. The imagination has 'free reign',
unlimited by the need to develop rigorous
concepts. The judgement of taste means
uniting 'a free judgment… With an
indeterminate understanding' (56-7). Such an
agreement or unity arises from judgement of
taste—'the pleasure is the agreement of the
faculties themselves, in so much as this agreement
is achieved without concepts and so can only be
felt'[judgment precedes pleasure].
Agreement among the faculties is central to
Kant. They are different and yet they can
function together. In the Critique of
Pure Reason, 'understanding, imagination and
reason enter into a harmonious relationship, in
accordance with a speculative purpose'(57).
In the Critique of Practical Reason, it is
reason and understanding that relate primarily for
practical purposes. However, one faculty
always predominates, in terms of the aim, the
objects, and the other faculties. In the
first critique, understanding produces a
priori concepts which are then applied to
objects which are necessarily subject or it, while
the other faculties function to secure the aim of
understanding and in relation to its
objects. In the second critique reason and
freedom are determined by the moral law, reason
then goes on to describe 'suprasensible objects
which are necessarily subject to [the law]', and
then ties understanding to a particular function
with a practical purpose. In other words,
understanding either for speculation or as reason
for a practical purpose dominates. Kant sees a
role of the imagination as being able to
'schematize', but only to serve understanding, for
a speculative purpose according to concepts of the
understanding, in the first critique.
Schematizing like this, and indeed reasoning like
this. could do other things, were they not
limited, and this is emphasised in the second
critique. Here, reason determines
understanding and its function—to develop general
laws from natural law, for practical
purposes.
It is quite possible that different combinations
or permutations between the activities of the
faculties could arise. That they take the
relationships they do presupposes that they must
be capable of developing 'the free harmony,
without any fixed proportion' (58). No other
form of inducement of one faculty on the others
would be possible. Is this argument
developed in the first two critiques that grounds
the argument in the third one, beginning with 'a
free agreement of the faculties'. Aesthetic
judgement makes this grounding of free agreement
particularly clear, since here, the imagination is
not immediately dominated by understanding or
reason, and aesthetic pleasure is 'disinterested
pleasure', not tied to any speculative or
practical purposes. There are no specific
aesthetic objects to define ['legislate'], only
those already in the domains of pure and practical
reason [ 'phenomena and things-in-themselves'
respectively (59)]. This makes aesthetic
judgement 'heautonomous (it legislates only
itself)'.
In the first two critique, there is 'the idea of
the necessary submission to certain types of
objects in relation to a dominant or determinative
faculty', but no such objects or dominant
faculties' in aesthetic judgement. The
agreement between beautiful objects in nature and
our aesthetic judgments is only 'contingent'[there
is no necessity that this be so]. It is
therefore a mistake to think that the third
critique does for imagination what the other to
critics do for the other faculties.
Imagination does not legislate 'in turn',
but demands that the other faculties become
'capable of free play'. Aesthetic judgment
therefore suggests contingent agreements between
objects and 'all our faculties together', as well
as 'a free indeterminate harmony of the faculties
among themselves'(59).
The imagination in aesthetic judgement can
schematize without concepts. In effect this
means liberating the imagination in the form of
reflection. The imagination 'reflects the
form of the object', but not its form that appears
in sensibility, through intuition, which still
belongs to understanding. Aesthetic forms
themselves merge 'with the reflection of the
object in the imagination', in a disinterested way
[it is even a disinterested about whether the
reflected object actually exists]. Kant
actually suggests that some objects cannot be
beautiful because they are too material, too
rooted in senses to be properly reflected in the
imagination [the examples are colours and
sounds]. Only the design or composition can
be reflected in imagination, the constitutive
elements of objects, not their mere adjuncts
[which would include colours and sounds].
For Kant, common sense is not just an empirical
faculty, but rather one which shows the agreement
of all the faculties together. There is a
logical common sense, found in pure reason, and a
moral common sense, in practical reason.
Aesthetic common sense is what generates communal,
even universal, feelings of pleasure.
However, it cannot be grounded in experience
alone, since there will be some who will not
accept judgment. Sometimes that does not
matter, but there are some aesthetic judgments
that must be accepted by everyone, by right [these
will be the elite judgments, about Bach or Mozart
in the example]. How can this claim be
justified? It is no good appealing to agreed
concepts, that deal only with logical or practical
aspects. We can presume or presuppose such
universality, but this would be to contradict a
free indeterminate agreement of the faculties in
the first place. We have to suggest that the
development of harmonious universal relations
between the faculties are spontaneous, and this
can not be presumed. Instead 'We must engender it
in the soul' (60), to show how it has been
generated.
We have to analyze the beautiful by examining
aesthetic judgments of spectators, uncovering the
free agreement of the faculties as a ground, and
then presupposing that this is the 'ground of the
soul'(60). This presumption is argued to be
necessary, to see taste is a natural
faculty, not fully graspable by analysis. We
can only deduce aesthetic judgement. The
first two critiques show how objects are
'necessarily subject' to speculative and practical
purposes, but now we have to argue that the
relation between the faculties themselves must be
deduced.
Some critics of Kant said that [grounding all
this] was neglected, and that Kant simply assumed
the existence of things like facts and faculties,
smuggling in a presupposition that they could be
analyzed or were capable of harmony
respectively. However, this [tautological]
argument is developed in the third critique, in
the search for an ultimate ground which would
affect the first two critiques as well. This
ground is going to involve us in 'a transcendental
Education, transcendental Culture, a
transcendental Genesis' (61).
We can make progress by thinking about the
difference between the beautiful and the sublime
[the latter involves not only understanding and
imagination, but reason agreeing with
imagination]. However, this is a paradoxical
agreeing, actually 'a discordant concord, a
harmony in pain' (62). The imagination has
to lose some of its freedom and undergo violence,
as when it is confronted by the immensity or power
of nature. However, the imagination is
capable both of 'successive apprehension, and
simultaneous comprehension'. The former is
infinite, but the latter are 'always has a
maximum', and this can force a limit on the
imagination. It is not the impact of the
sublime itself, or rather its appearance, but
reason which 'forces the imagination to confront
its limit', and acknowledge the superiority of
rational ideas. This is initially
discordant, yet it yields an agreement, and Kant
almost develops a
dialectic here. Reason confronts the
imagination with its limits, but this helps
imagination takes this limit itself as an object,
and thereby surpass its limits, even if initially
in the form of the negative realization of
inaccessibility to reason's grasp. In this
way, limits disappear, and imagination can
confront the infinite in a way which '"expands the
soul"'. [To cut a long story short,
imagination leaves the constraints of the
empirical and agrees with reason that there must
be some suprasensible level of reality, a
transcendental origin]. This eventual
agreement only arises from initial discordant
pain, but in the end, reason and imagination both
benefit: both come to realise that there is
'the suprasensible unity of all the faculties',
deep in the soul. Only the analysis of the
sublime provides this discovery of the
transcendental as genesis. And only the
'cultured' individual can see beyond the discord
and pain presented by nature itself. As a
result, the analysis of the sublime can be a model
to help us grasp the beautiful—maybe the agreement
between imagination and the understanding is also
produced by a transcendental genesis.
In the first critique, Kant argues that the
categories are 'a priori representations of the
understanding' (63), but then has to show why
these categories are able to grasp objects, how
they can speculate or legislate. However,
when judging the sublime, there is no such
problem: we relate to objects ' only by projecting
our moods'[possibly because the sublime is
formless?]. It might be the same when
judging beauty or taste—we have a disinterested
pleasure, disinterested even to the extent of
being able to disregard the object. In this
sense, 'the judgement of taste is only
subjective'. However, a sense of the
beautiful arises from the form of an objects,
unlike the sublime, so with the beautiful, there
must be some aspect of the object which leads us
to 'experience the free harmony of our
understanding and our imagination'. Somehow,
nature produces objects that take on positive
properties which help us develop judgments through
relating our faculties—the internal relation of
the faculties 'implies an external agreement
between nature and the same faculties'(64).
This is more than just our faculties 'legislating'
objects, subjecting them to our categories,
because in that case, the judgement of taste would
become subject to autonomous agreement and
legislation, [just as the concepts of the
understanding]. However, if nature itself
dominated the agreement without faculties', then
'the judgement of taste would no longer be
heautonomous', but subject to empirical tests [of
the correspondence with nature]. Thus this
agreement between our faculties and nature is
unmotivated ["presents itself without a goal"]—we
must just be 'organized in such a way that we can
favourably receive nature'.
So to recap, we do have some common sense of the
beautiful, because aesthetic pleasure is
supposedly universal. This pleasure results
from the agreement of the imagination and the
understanding, a free agreement which 'can only be
felt'. However, this cannot just be
presupposed butt must be grounded a priori.
We have to explain why these feelings are
universal, even appearing '"like a duty"'.
Is there something objective after all that
generates the agreement of the faculties in
judgment? We might get there by shifting
from the analysis of the beautiful to the analysis
of the sublime, because the latter analysis helps
us understand the genesis of judgments, the
conditions under which free agreement between
understanding and imagination can appear. We
do not need this analysis to understand judgments
of the sublime themselves [because they are just
felt], but we can use it to understand agreements
of the faculties elsewhere.
The agreement between nature and faculties when we
judge what is beautiful 'defines a purpose for
reason'. This is not a purpose that
legislates beauty, because it is totally
disinterested, and arrived at 'without the
intervention of reason' (65). We can see
that what is important is that nature has an
aptitude to produce beauty, an external factor
affecting the agreement of the faculties
within. This can be the genetic
principle—although our actual judgments are
disinterested, we can experience a rational
purpose underneath [this seems to turn into a
classically circular argument—we need to find some
role for reason even in aesthetic judgement, and
we can discover this by presupposing one in the
actions of nature, or as Kant apparently put it '"
it is in the interest of reason that Ideas have an
objective reality… That nature at least
indicates by a trace or a sign that it contains a
principle allowing a legitimate agreement between
its productions and our satisfaction independent
of any purpose... Reason is necessarily
interested in any natural manifestation of such an
agreement"'(65).
So there are determinations of the beautiful, 'for
which the sense of the beautiful remains
indifferent', and imagination can only reflect the
form. Thus nature provides aspects like the
connection of the beautiful with sounds and
colours, as a material purpose: Kant even thinks
of nature as producing primal matter, some 'fluid
matter, a part of which is separated out or
evaporates, and the rest of which suddenly
solidifies (crystal formation)', but some of these
aspects cannot be reflected in the imagination, as
we saw with sounds and colours. There is
therefore something beyond the imagination, still
connected with the judgement of beauty—'described
as meta-aesthetic'.
It is this that generates the agreement between
the understanding and the imagination when we
judge beauty. We reason about the
presentations of the idea 'in sound, colour, and
free matter'. We do this by not just
subsuming colours or whatever under concepts, but
relating these aspects to another concept, the
Idea of natural reason [with a capital I in the
original], and how this determines objects.
Natural reason has no object that can be grasped
by intuition, but we can see it as analogous to
objects that are grasped by intuition—we transpose
the reflection engendered by these mundane objects
on to the concept of natural reason. [The
example is that the white lily is no longer seen
just in terms of concepts of colour and flower,
but 'awakens the Idea of pure innocence, whose
object, which is never given, is a reflexive
analogue of white in the fleur de lis'
(65-66)]. What this sort of analogy
does is extend the concepts in our
understanding, infinitely, and it frees the
imagination from being over schematized,
constrained under the conventional concepts of
understanding [in other words, once we allow
metaphor and analogy, we can move sideways out
from formal logic]. What we are arriving at,
says Deleuze, is 'the principle of a
transcendental genesis', arrived at through
reason, and this is the point of the analysis of
the sublime in Kant [although we have been talking
about beauty and its meta-aesthetic just now?]
The Idea of reason in nature presents itself in
several ways. In the sublime, we get 'a
direct presentation accomplished by projection',
but it appears only as an negative
inaccessibility. When rational purpose is
connected with the beautiful, we get an indirect
but more positive presentation, through symbols as
we saw. There is apparently a third
model—'Genius… Accomplished through the
creation of an "other" nature' (66), [and a]...
fourth mode which is teleological… Achieved
in the concepts of end and final agreement'.
These are positive and direct.
If we explore the notion of the rational purpose
of nature, which leads to this a priori
agreement of faculties, we have to agree that it
was nature that produced beauty. However,
this causes a problem because we now have a split
between the beautiful in nature and the beautiful
in art [which we're going to heal by a
transcendental deduction? Well-- a convergence of
transcendental deductions really, as we see right
at the end]. We can see the purpose of nature if
we consider only natural beauty—why a work of art
produces a similar agreement of the faculties is
so far ungrounded, 'without a principle', and Kant
has to discover this principle. The
principle is Genius, 'the subjective disposition
by which nature provides art with
rules'(67). It is Genius that provides the
arts with materials. It is also a
meta-aesthetic principle, 'the same as rational
purpose'. It provides aesthetic ideas,
unlike the ideas of reason which take the form of
concepts without any intuition—aesthetic ideas are
the opposite, it seems. However, just as the
ideas of reason help us to go beyond limited
concepts to discover transcendental principles, so
do aesthetic ideas: they lead to 'the
intuition of another nature than the nature given
to us… In which the phenomena are events of
the spirit, in an unmediated way, and the events
of the spirit of phenomena of nature'. This
helps us grasp these invisible beings in a way
which is adequate to them. Aesthetic ideas
therefore provide the intuitions behind reason,
achieving a kind of unity between intuition and
reason. Aesthetic judgement helps us to
present these ideas, just as we got to them
through analogies and symbolism—it makes us think
and extend our concept of understanding, while
freeing our imagination as above. It
vitalizes, and enables the different faculties to
come together an agreement. It also helps us
cover the splits between natural and artistic
beauty, since genius agrees with the idea of
natural purpose [both are genetic].
However, 'Genius entails a far more complex
genesis'—it does not just generate agreement of
the faculties in the spectator, but 'is the gift
of the artistic creator' (68). So how can it
take on universal implications? The answer
lies not in 'a universal subjectivity, but at most
an exceptional intersubjectivity', where the
genius of one somehow stimulates the emergence of
the other geniuses, by setting an example.
This is rare or often unwelcome. However,
geniuses both produce the matter of art, 'by
inventing another nature adequate to Ideas', which
liberates the imagination, and give this
imagination form, adjusting the imagination.
This form is that 'of an object of taste'—that is,
'the free agreement of the imagination and the
understanding', which is engendered 'everywhere'
in spectators [taste is a matter of popular
appeal? Hang on though, spectators can only
be 'men and women of taste, students, and
aficionados'].
Overall then, there are 'three parallel geneses in
Kant's aesthetics': in the sublime, we see a
genesis of the agreement between reason and
imagination; in the beautiful we see the purpose
of nature generating an agreement in us between
the understanding and imagination; in Genius, we
see understanding and imagination agreeing in
beautiful arts [Deleuze has deliberately left out
the fourth genesis, teleology]. In each
case, the agreement follows from an original free
state. Thus aesthetic judgement is not like
the other forms in the first two critiques, where
we have 'ready made faculties [which] enter
determinate relations and take on organized tasks
under the direction of one legislative faculty'
(68-9), aiming at speculative or practical
purposes. The third critique is
different. Initially, Kant argued that it
showed the subordination of speculative to
practical purposes, in the form of moral
development—'(the beautiful in arts, no less than
the beautiful in nature, is in the end declared "a
"symbol of morality")'(69). However, the
critique led on to a discussion of the ground of
judgment, even the ground for the other two
critiques. This ground lies not in nature
nor [imaginative?] liberty, beauty has a purpose
that is not just moral or speculative, and our
tendencies to become moral are grounded in
something suprasensible [presumably, developing
some transcendental idea of nature and the arts as
spiritual]. Judgment shows that the basis of
the development of the faculties is 'free
agreement, indeterminate and unconditional', and
that the more limited operations of the other two
activities depend on this as well—'No determinate
relation of the faculties, or relation conditioned
by one of them, would ever be possible if it were
not first made possible by this free unconditioned
agreement'(69) [clear parallels between original
difference establishing subsequent mundane
differences and repetitions?].
The three geneses of judgment 'converge on the
same discovery: what Kant calls the Soul, that is,
the suprasensible unity of our faculties…
The life giving principle that "animates" each
faculty... A primeval free imagination that
cannot be satisfied with schematizing… That
does not yet bend under the speculative weight of
its determinate concepts… That has not yet
developed a taste for commanding' (69-70).
We can reconstitute the argument:
- In the 'Analytic of the
Beautiful', we see the development of formal
aesthetics [ an aesthetics related to actual
forms] from the spectator's point of view,
involving a free agreement of the
understanding and imagination. This free
agreement constitutes the judgment of
taste. Spectators here are reflecting
the form of the object [in their
imaginations]. 'Free indeterminate
agreement must be a priori', and
whenever this happens, we discover 'what is
most profound in the soul', the possibility of
harmony. It is this that provides the
ground of the other two critiques, and means
we can't just rely on the understanding or the
imagination. We require a transcendental
genesis, but this can only be presupposed in
discussions of the beautiful.
- In the 'Analytic of the
Sublime', we moved to a formless aesthetics,
but still from the point of view of the
spectator. Here, we have to aim at 'the
free agreement of reason and imagination', but
this is often accompanied with 'pain,
opposition, constraint and discord'—it is very
challenging to encounter the sublime in the
'formless or deformed', even though we also
experience freedom and spontaneity. This
analysis does point to a generic principle for
the agreement of the faculties, however.
- In the analytic of the
beautiful again, we can deduce a material
meta-aesthetics in nature, still from the
spectator's point of view. We have to
pursue 'a particular deduction', based in some
way at least on some forms of the object [Kant
tells us which are to be considered as
important]. We also have to grasp how
understanding and imagination can agree.
The analysis of the sublime provides us with
this, pursuing the equivalent deduction for
the beautiful. Here we are trying to
ground in a rule the 'universality of
aesthetic pleasure' (71), and not as a
presupposition but a priori. We
know from analysis of the beautiful that there
must be some rational purpose in nature which
produces beautiful things from its materials,
some meta-aesthetic purpose. This
particular purpose requires us to develop
reason itself, expand the understanding and
liberate the imagination, and once we've done
this, we can start to see the basis of a new
free indeterminate agreement between the two
[some sort of mutual benefit in expansion,
given some spiritual purpose]. So we now
have an objective dimension of the
transcendental in nature, and a subjective one
in the human spiritual benefits of expanding
understandings and liberating imaginations.
- We also have a notion of
the beautiful from the point of view of the
creative artist—the theory of Genius. So
far, we have seen a purpose only for natural
beauty. We need another meta-aesthetic
principle to explain artistic beauty, and
Genius does this. Like purpose in
nature, it produces a matter, 'it incarnates
Ideas', developing reason through liberation
and expansion. All this is done 'from
the vantage point of the creation of a work of
art', but genius must also proceed to 'give a
universal value to the agreement which it
engenders, and it must communicate to the
faculties of the spectator something of its
own life and force'.
Taken together, these stages of the argument form
of 'a systematic whole, in which the three geneses
are unified'
[now try Bourdieu's
critique of Kantian aesthetics]
|
|