Notes on: Maton,
K & Moore, R. (2010) (Eds) Social Realism,
Knowledge and the Sociology of Education.
Coalitions of the Mind. London: Continuum.
Dave Harris
Introduction
This is about social realism and its implications
for the sociology of education. Social
realism intervenes in debates that formerly
included constructivism, post structuralism and
postmodernism, but these are relativist.
They also help address knowledge itself, and deny
the assumption that the only choice is between
positivism and relativism. There is also a
false dichotomy between objective and socially
constructed notions of knowledge. Sociology
of education is spent a lot of time trying to
criticize knowledge claims rather than 'exploring
the social grounds for objectivity in knowledge or
the autonomy of knowledge - producing fields'
(2). Social realism attempts to bridge these
polar opposites. Knowledge is 'inescapably
social' but this does not entail relativism.
There is objective knowledge but it is a social
phenomenon produced by people in actual contexts
and it is 'fallible rather than absolute or merely
relative'[not really social realism in the Bhaskar
tradition of the transcendent reality then?
Looks like Popper again]. This knowledge has
a power in itself, it does not reflect
essential truth or social power.
Education produces and teaches knowledge, but it
has not focused on knowledge as an object in the
sociology of education. We need to
understand what knowledge is. Social realism
makes it central. We need to investigate her
own knowledge is created and developed in the form
which it takes.
There is a distinction between truth and
truthfulness, for Williams. Truth involves
claims to epistemological power, not that there is
'unchanging, eternal Truth' (3), but that we can
choose rationally between different sorts of
knowledge 'in terms of their explanatory
power'. Truthfulness involves looking
through appearances to '"the real structures and
motives that lie behind them"', but this can
obscure the true nature of knowledge.
Sociology of education has focused on critical
deconstructive analyses of the curriculum, to show
underlying 'interests and experiences of a
dominant social group'. Truthfulness has
replaced truth, although it still implies some
deeper truth. However, constructivism,
feminism, multiculturalism and post structuralism
all obscure knowledge as a study in its own right.
Social realism embraces both truth and
truthfulness, trying to add to the structures
beneath the appearances, but arguing that these
'are more than the play of social power and vested
interests'(4). It embraces ontological
realism, epistemological relativism, and
judgmental rationality' [citing Archer et al
1998]. Ontological realism recognizes 'that
knowledge is about something other than itself:
there exists a reality beyond our symbolic realm',
'independently existing realities, both natural
and social', which limit what we can know,
checking our collective beliefs [confused again,
is there an external reality or a collective
belief in one?]. Epistemological relativism
accepts that knowledge is socially produced rather
than being invariant Truths, but it does not imply
judgmental relativism: we can choose between
competing knowledge claims, on a 'rational,
intersubjective bases'[enshrines rationality and
assumes some legislating institution - no doubt
the university]. This escapes the priority
that positivism gives to the logical properties of
knowledge claims. Instead we are looking at
collective procedures producing judgments 'against
the background constraints of the real' (5).
In education, we are more interested in the
substance, how fields of social practice produce
knowledge and particular procedures for rational
objectivity. Again we don't have to choose
positivism or relativism, and nor do we have to
choose transmitting knowledge or valorising the
learner. Knowledge producing fields have
both 'relational structures of concepts and
methods… And actors positioned in
institutions within specific social and historical
contexts' [epistemic and social dimensions].
Knowledge emerges from practices and contexts and
cannot be reduced to them: it can transcend its
own conditions [presumably relying on Popper
again].
In this way, social realism goes beyond
constructivism, for Young [it is all horribly self
referential, and rather parochial -- London
University]. Nor can we construct the world
free of consequences, since the world reacts
back. Fields of practice are only
'relatively autonomous'(6), but there are 'both
arbitrary and non arbitrary bases' for
practice. Knowledge itself shapes the world
[followed by '("realism")']. Knowledge is
not certain, but it 'is an object in its own right
but as real effects'[further definition].
Social realism helps us to understand these
different forms and their effects, including the
capacity to build powerful knowledge, and to
affect education, to discuss access and
professionalism - lots of nice 'practical issues
in educational theory and practice'[and this is
what subsequent chapters in this book do,
apparently].
For example, teacher training has recently
emphasised learning rather than knowledge.
This is produced 'a radical skepticism towards
knowledge' seeing it as a mere power play.
Knowledge is insufficiently differentiated and the
construction of the curriculum seems
arbitrary. Similarly, pedagogy is seen as
focused on process not the form of knowledge, and
the authority of teachers becomes personal.
Curricula and pedagogy are conventional, and there
is no rational sequence on offer. The same
views underpin arguments to replace conventional
teaching with ICT. It is argued that there
are no differences between every day and
educational knowledge. This attacks teaching
as a profession and disempowers learners.
Social realism does better and accepts such
differentiation of knowledge. Knowledge is
real and differentiated and emergent, and teaching
should be structured accordingly. There are
differences between production and educational
contextualization, but they are still
related. There are 'may be good reasons for
why [SIC] some subjects are typically organised in
curricula and taught differently to others'(7)
[come back Hirst and Peters], but these are not
absolute differences, nor are they
arbitrary. Future research should sort out
the arbitrary from the non arbitrary [the latter
here is defined as 'the affects of an ontological
imperative']. It also follows that if there
is non arbitrary knowledge, some forms of
knowledge are more epistemologically powerful than
others, and this should affect pedagogy by taking
account of hierarchies of knowledge. There
are even implications for assessment which should
evaluate 'the content knowledge of learners'.
In democracies all citizens should get equal
access to powerful knowledge. We should not
just 'celebrate the experiences of students' (8),
and risk relativism. The social backgrounds
of students are one variable, but so is the form
of knowledge involved. Overall, both
intellectual and educational practices
'necessarily involve hierarchies', but these are
not always and everywhere arbitrary. Popper
argued that progress is indicated by the problems
created by intellectual fields, and that these
problems must be engaged with both truth and
truthfulness [pretty odd summary. Nothing on
falsification? Also, knower mode throughout - we
should believe this because Popper said it].
There is also a political dimension. Seeing
knowledge as value free is associated with
conservatism, and critical relativism is seen as
radical. For the latter, arguing that
knowledge is an object worth studying can be seen
as reactionary. Social realism is both non
relativistic and socially progressive.
Others have complained about relativism, including
Furedi and Wheen [his piece on mumbo jumbo].
Furedi has argued that the role of intellectuals
is crucial to a democratic ethos and this is been
undermined by cynicism.
We need to reclaim the association between Reason
and Truth and social progressiveness:
postmodernism is not the last word. Events
like September 11 show that objective reality
exists and has consequences [common sense
definitions of social reality here] we have to
avoid what Gellner called 'the suicide of
reason'(9). The consequences have also been
endless fragmentation 'political toothlessness and
deleterious educational outcomes' (10) as seen in
the sociology of education [professional reasons
for realism here]
Social realism is not just another school but
should be describe better 'as a coalition of
minds', with differences among social realists, or
although there is a sense of collaboration and
constructive engagement. This produces an
ongoing dialogue, as Durkheim once said about
collective representations. This means the
social dimension is central and the intellectual
field is shared: it is not just a matter of
competitions over power. This diminishes the
full social nature of knowledge.
Intellectual activity is collective and about
symbolic membership and coalition, extending over
time and space. There is no radical break
with the past [not what Popper says here] .
Examples of such coalitions include intellectual
traditions in sociology, such as the one inspired
by Durkheim; critical realism in philosophy that
bring together Bhaskar, Gellner and Williams;
linguistics through Halliday and his associates.
However, Bernstein has had 'the most immediate
influence'[restoring Bernstein to the canon is
another reason for adopting this perspective], and
his ideas produce a central thread for the book.
Coalitions of social realists have also developed
through associations and discussions, including a
series of publications [with Maton and Moore
prominent]. Attention was given first to the
structural features of knowledge, and this had
further applications, above all Maton's.
This resurrected Young. International
conferences and publications leads to more waves
and chains of participants. The chapters in
this book illustrate progress [some of them
Maton's papers]. Further participation is
required.
return to ed studs
|
|