NOTES
ON: Ranciere, J. (2003) Politics and
Aesthetics an interview, Trans Forbes Morlock,
Angelaki 8(2) 191--21.
notes by Dave Harris
Hallward P Introduction
Ranciere retired in 2002 from University of Paris
VIII. His overall project is to overturn
existing forms of classification and distinction
and 'to subvert all norms of representation that
might allow for the stable differentiation of one
class of person or experience from another'.
Moments of crisis which reveal these
representations are particularly useful.
As a student at Ecole Normale Superieure (ENS) ,
he encountered Althusser and wrote a section of Reading
Capital which preserved the distinction
between experience and the authority of
theory. He split with Althusser and others
over 1968, and published a critique.
Inspired by Foucault he founded a new journal
'dedicated to recasting the relation between work
and philosophy, or proletarians and intellectuals
in such a way is to block any prescriptive
appropriation or representation of the former by
the latter'(191). Like Foucault this has been
applied to a number of different areas as such is
philosophy, pedagogy, and aesthetic areas.
His general argument is developed best in Philosophy
and its Poor, where he disagrees with the
fundamental argument that there are some people
capable of genuine thought while others are
incapable largely because of their economic and
social conditions, lacking 'the ability, time and
leisure required for thought'(192). It all
stems from Plato and dividing society into
functional orders so that slaves can never be
philosophers and anyone who tries to cross a
functional division is excluded.
In The
Ignorant Schoolmaster, attempts to
generally classify children in the name of
emancipation are rejected in favour of the
view that '"all people are virtually capable of
understanding what others have done and
understood"'. We must simply assert equality
and maintain it. 'Everyone has the same
intelligence; what varies is the will and
opportunity to exercise it'[what's the problem so
far then? Who is denying this?].
Teachers have no right to claim superior knowledge
or to spend their time explicating in a way that
sees children as inferior, making differential
progress and so on.
Historians have also presented this picture of
appropriate places for individuals, allowing
individuals to appear only as spokespersons, and
arguing that environments affect social relations
and therefore legitimate speech. Heresy is
denied, and democracy suspected, to the extent
that it turns on 'a popular voice that refuses any
clear assignation of place, the voice of the
masses of people who both labour and think'.
This leads the position of politics. The
'police' classify and regulate speech, and
distribute it. The democratic voice is one
that rejects the social distribution and tries to
support '"floating subjects that deregulate all
representations of places and portions"'
It leads to an equal reservation about attempts by
Marxists to simplify workers' experience into
'theory - certified simplicity'. He is also
opposed to 'nostalgic attempts to preserve a
"traditional" working class identity'. The
latter usually leads to nostalgia for the demise
of the authentic working class instead of
celebrating 'unauthorized combinations and
inventions'. His historical studies show
opposition to social hierarchy rather than to
economic exploitation, and the most dangerous were
the migrants who refused to keep their allotted
place.
This clearly informs the aesthetic revolution, a
move away from attempts to impose rules on art, or
to define art. There is a celebration of
'the endless confusion of arts and non - art',
with particular admiration for those efforts which
use aristocratic conceptions to describe banal
every day life and celebrate the ordinary (193).
The Interview ( with Hallward)
How did you get involved in
teaching, given that you don't support
academic mastery?
He is a perpetual student, and like most of those,
found himself teaching others. He saw
himself as a teacher-researcher which 'implies the
idea of the teacher adapting a position of
institutional mastery to one of mastery based on
knowledge'(194). Commitment to Althusser was
disrupted by 1968, and the way it connected
mastery and knowledge. As a researcher he
was able to resist student divisions into levels,
and at Paris VIII, there were no levels in the
philosophy department—he offers material to
students at all levels.
Was his background important in
channeling him into research and teaching?
He wanted to go to ENS to be an archaeologist, but
lost that interest and was left with having to
choose between Arts & Sciences. He
wanted to go to the best in the field for arts,
the ENS. 'That, rather than any vocation to
teach' explained how he got there.
Why the initial interest in Althusser?
He had been interested in Marxism, not at all
familiar at the time. Religious and humanist
Marxism had been the way in in those days, and not
a communist tradition or membership of the
Party. Althusser's novelty was much admired
at the time....
Althusser's texts were influential rather than his
actual teaching. His insistence on new
projects opening up was seductive, 'the sense of
going off on adventure' (195). He had an
early seminar on Capital, and felt like a
pioneer and also an authority: adventurism was
combined with dogmatism.
Why did you break with Althusser after 68?
He watched the events of May '68 'from a certain
distance'(195). [!] The creation of The
University of Paris VIII provided the challenge,
and also revealed the power of professors and
their distance from student and other social
movements. 'It was almost laughable'. In
particular Balibar designed a program 'to teach
people theoretical practice as it should be
taught', and that led him to protest, and then to
think about the relation between theory and
dogmatism. So it was the aftershock, and the
choice of what to do in a new institution.
How did you manage egalitarian teaching with
the business of granting degrees and
qualifications?
He had more or less given up academic philosophy
for political practice. The diploma in
philosophy was soon invalidated anyway, and this
gave the staff a certain freedom. As a
result 'for good while, then, I was absolutely
uninterested in rethinking pedagogy', and research
and militant practice seemed more important.
'For years my main activity was consulting
archives and going to the Bibliotheque
Nationale'...
There were lectures but there were also
'courses which took the form of conversations and
interventions'(196).
[So -- he has never actually tried to teach like
this?]
Did you turn to historical proletarian thinking
because philosophy seems to have been defeated?
It was more a naive approach to try and find out
what class consciousness or workers' thought
actually meant, to get 'the reality of forms
of struggle and forms of consciousness' which was
different from Marxist accounts…
The focus was the difference between Marxism and
alternative political traditions, which turned
into a search for a genuine workers' thinking and
politics. However, there was no simple
unified identity as a worker reflected in forms of
consciousness or action, but rather a set of
statements or enunciations.
But you did not reject the usual connection
between Marxism, the proletarian movements and
repression as in the USSR? You still
thought in terms of a universal singularity,
even if a deferred and differentiated one?
There was a double movement between
singularization and its opposite. A
dissociation with the usual identity of the
worker, which itself 'created forms of
universalization' which were positive.
Disidentification showed the relation between
negativity and positivity. The struggles of
the 1830s were about attempting to become a
speaking and thinking being, and this became
shared, but at the same time always threatened by
new forms of positivization. There was no
authentic workers' movement that had escaped
altogether. The danger of positivization
threatened to install both the notion of an
authentic community and an orthodox Marxist
proletariat.
Don't you overdo the creativity of political
practice without adequately considering its
conditions of possibility? Sometimes,
democratic institutions that you call 'the
police' also opened a public space.
Writers like Habermas insist on a quality of
linguistic competencies which leads to sharing
the symbolic domain
Citizenship follows only because a movement has
insisted on it [Always? It MUST do?]. Human
beings are assumed already to have freedom and
equality which underpins legal inscriptions.
However, 'equality or legal freedom produces
nothing in itself. It exists only insofar as
it defines a possibility, insofar as there is an
effective movement which can grasp it and bring it
into existence retroactively' (197). The
question of origins is not really important,
whether it is transcendental or historical, but
transcendental conditions seem particularly
dubious.
But you insist on an equality once people
speak? Doesn't this also imply an
inequality according to how well or often people
speak? Abstract equality is not the same
as real equality? Aren't you suggesting
simply a formal similarity between participants
in a game?
Some minimal equality of competence is necessary
in any game. Even slaves have to understand,
Aristotle knew. But Aristotle also insisted
that it was necessary to possess language,
although he never clarified the point. There
is no need to specify some abstract equality,
simply to 'presume a minimal equality of
competence in order that inequality itself can
operate', and the point is to show how equality is
only ever polemical.
[Let off the hook here I thought Easy to just
dismiss this important question? Merely
empirical?]
But aren't you dealing in transcendentalism
when you say that a political role is always
played by those who have been excluded and have
no particular identity, and can thus pose as 'in
the incarnation of the universal
interest'? Does this applied to modern
politics, for example in the USA, where the
struggle is between abstract consumerist
identity, and various 'communitarian and
identitarian movements'? (198)
It is necessary to define the political, as
opposition to any whole that claims to be more
than the sum of its parts, especially in the form
of organic conceptions or general
assemblies. In the USA, the notion of a
whole dominates, even though there are conflicts,
and this whole community 'authorizes forms of
subjectivation for the uncounted'. It is not
a matter of an excluded group trying to identify
itself with the community, which would make it an
ethical issue not a political one. It is a
particular symbolization of community that
produces inequality.
Is such politics realistic today? It is
'always possible'. But we have to be
pessimistic about its actual imminence.
What about anti colonial struggles? They
might have a universal moment, but this rarely
lasts, and often a choice has to be made,
between 'militant particularism' and effective
struggle? (199).
There is always ambiguity and risk of being
'coercively pinned down'. Nevertheless,
politics must refuse the choice mentioned and push
the universal, whether held by you or the enemy,
to its own particularity 'to the point where each
comes to contradict itself', where symbolic
violence of separation leads to reclaiming
universality. The risk still remains though
– submit to a disciplining universal, or stay
within an identarian perspective, and no movement
has succeeded in avoiding both risks.
[So always a good reason to do stuff all?]
Your idea of democracy really presupposes
conventional notions where there is no central
authority and therefore a space for new figures
to claim universality?
Democracy is really a form of symbolizing
political power, not leaving it open. 'It
turns on the very existence of the political'
(199). It is a practice which has democratic
institutions, but not necessarily a democratic
life: the institutions can 'operate simply as
instruments for the reproduction of an oligarchic
power'
[so Bourdieu might be right? Do we not need
empirical research to find out which possibility
is operating add any particular time?]
Zizek in The Ticklish Subject
says you offer impossibly ideal notions of
political practice, which means you can just
keep your hands clean. Do we not really
need power, parties authorities and so on?
This is not asserting spontaneity as against
organizations. There is a personal dislike
for particular practices of power and the forms of
thought that accompany them [God forbid we should
ever have to overcome our personal dislikes!] The
real issue is theoretical [! LOTS of interest
here...theoretician do have a role then? They can
perceive things that ordinary plonkers
cannot?]—Politics and power may not be the same
thing. Politics is more than just the
organization of the community, or the occupation
of a particular government. It is an
alternative to the police order, regardless of
forms of power and organisation.
But how can political authority be
organized? Do we need a party or not?
There are no simple rules. What is important
is 'forms of perception, forms of
utterance'(199). How these are taken up by
organizations is another matter. 'I must
admit that I had never been able to endure any one
of them for very long, but I know I have nothing
better to propose'. {Says it all]
You have commented favourably on French
politics at the end of the Algerian war, which
extended beyond just sympathy. Do you see
this in modern anti American and anti
globalization thinking?
Political movements defining themselves against
international capitalism are inspiring, but so
far, none has yet managed it beyond national
frameworks or arguments about particular states
and peoples. Indeed, in cases like Algeria,
national interests 'allowed the uncounted to be
accounted for' (200). Taking on capital is
different. Negri and
Hardt show how there are no simple points
which might lead to political
subjectification. Their politics depends on
the forces of production somehow breaking through
the relations of production. Recent
demonstrations have tried to show how capital is
politicized, at least through particular
instruments. Yet there is no easy connection
between multitude and anticapitalist
politics. It is unlikely that there will
never be a specifically anticapitalist struggle,
without national relations 'bringing into play an
inside and an outside'. The rules of the
game are no longer clear, as with the reaction to
9/11. The Vietnam war was simpler because it
was clear who was being attacked, and the
contradictions between democratic discourse and
aggression were clear. However, there is no
simplicity now. Global affairs seem to be
supported by some moral vision of political life,
wars of good against evil, and it is difficult to
regain the ground for politics...
As a result, the national domain remains
important, for example in openly excluding
immigrants without papers, an obvious
contradiction.
If politics is about configuring space and
exposing processes of constructing subjects, and
this is completely opposite to the domain of the
police, are we not disconnecting ourselves from
the politics of inequality and how it is
structured?
This is really Badiou. It is possible to
define what specific to politics, and to separate
practice and the ideas of community from other
forms of negotiations between social groups.
'The political isn't the social'. Neither is
it the social and empirical mixture of local and
state controlled as Badiou thinks. Instead,
the social arises when policing logic is designed
to share out or distribute meet 'the various ways
of configuring the common space which throw the
same distributions into question'(201).
Social benefits are not just shares of the
national income, but what is seen to be shareable,
common, and who distributes common spaces and
permits people to occupy them. It is always
a matter of 'distribution of places and roles' and
who is qualified to say. So politics really
emerges from the social, which is why it runs
through labour movements and educational
questions, social questions about universities,
the status of the unemployed and so on.
Running throughout all these disputes is 'the
configuring of what is shared or common', whether
it is a matter of university selection, or
pensions and social benefits—all these engage with
notions of the common sphere and how it is
configured, and this includes disputes about state
vs. private provision.
Reminds me of the endless deferrals of
Derridavians who always wanted to discuss the
philosophical meaning ofpolitics rather than
actually doing any politics -- see Fraser]
How do you relate to Arendt?
There is some agreement and also strong
disagreement, which extends to current
interpretations of her work. It is agreed
that politics is a matter of appearance, a common
stage, acting out common scenes not just governing
common interests, but Arendt argues that the
political is sometimes confused by social claims,
such as compassion for victims. This
preserves the idea that the social is about
reproducing life, while politics is mere
appearance. This turns on the old opposition
between 'men of leisure and men of necessity'
(202), and how having to work only on the basis of
necessity excludes people from politics and from
'the domain of appearance'. Instead, 'the
misfortune of the poor lies in their being
unseen', and they do not even realize this.
However, workers already have made a claim for
visibility. It is an example of where those
who apparently cannot do something actually do
it. Some followers of Arendt have also
recuperated her to say that the government is
above mere social pettiness and narrow conflict.
What about Michelet on history?{I do not
know this work so I'm going to summarise
drastically}]
Michelet's view of history turns on the gradual
emergence of speech from below, although he never
takes revolutionary assemblies seriously, but
instead sees it in terms of some discourse of the
earth, or truth opposed to the actual words of
speakers, silent masses, anonymous and unconscious
thought. This is quite different from
Jacotot's affirmation of the capacity to
speak. It is not the same as believing that
people are equal in principle and have an
anonymous voice, that speech is everywhere,
implicitly, as in Victor Hugo. Rather, the
capacity to speak pertains to anybody and can be
verified. We often find the two mixed, so
that emancipatory discourse combines active
speeches with 'the silent power of the collective'
(203).
Why did you shift to aesthetics?
There is no programme of work, rather an interest
in blurring boundaries. Political and social
movements are also intellectual and aesthetic
ones, 'reconfiguring the frameworks of the visible
and the thinkable'. Personal interests have
led to literature and the cinema rather than to
less interesting questions of political
science. Even the work on workers' history
was also about literary references, and how
workers' texts might be seen in terms of 'models
offered by literature', as well as a chance to
experiment with writing and composition, rather
than seeing workers speech 'as the expression of
the condition': instead, the intention was to
practice 'a certain poetics'. Actual books,
like the one on Mallarme were initially
interesting because of the poems about the
proletariat, but also because they commented on
matters like the relation between day and
night: workers did not accept the simple
division between work and rest. A seminar on
the politics of writing, on what is political in
writing had been led 'over several years' (204),
turning on how writing translates properties and
transmits knowledge, or itself configures and
divides 'the shared domain of the sensible'.
This is not just the issue of representation,
which is how politics and aesthetics are normally
linked. Instead, writing cuts up 'the
universal singular'. Flaubert, for example
announces a notion of literary equality, of topic
[apparently he said he was as much interested in
the lice that feed on the poor]. Literature
can introduce dissensus, and break with political
conventions. This is more interesting than
the debate about bias.
Then some 'people in the arts' asked him to
reflect on the cinema, which he has always been
interested in. A further invitation helped
him think about contemporary art, where he had 'no
real competence', but saw a need to respond to the
challenge.
[Reminds me of what Althusser
says about the difference between professional
bourgeois philosophers and marxist ones -- nothing
drives the former except the agreeable need to
enjoy university life and its interests]
Is there a parallel between literature the
claims to be systematic and encyclopaedic, and a
literature of nothing, self referential, and
politics?
There might be a similar kernel of meaning, in the
idea of a work that comes from a 'profusion of
things and signs' or from 'the rarifaction of
events and senses'. The literature or after
the Revolution focuses on interpreting society and
the place of speech, an idea of speech that
exceeds the speaker and the speaker's intention,
that there is speech everywhere. Social life
can be seen as 'a vast poem'(205).
Alternatively, the book about nothing replaces
this totality, as an inverse. This can take
the form, as in Flaubert, of 'an aesthetic of
equal intensities'[apparently one of the tensions
in Madame Bovary, who is rebuked for
confusing art and life but also permitted to be an
equal subject]. In this way 'Literature invents
itself is another way of talking about the things
politicians talk about'.
Why are you more interested in romanticism than
modernism?
There has been an aesthetic revolution, opposing
the notion of art as systematic with clear rules,
focusing on dignified subjects and offering other
kinds of hierarchy, such as tragedy over
comedy. Now, art is no longer governed by
these rules or subjects, and can speak of
everything. 'It is the affirmation that
poems are everywhere, the paintings are
everywhere'. The important thing is what art
speaks of: the beautiful is everywhere, and
anonymous, and this is 'the idea of equality and
anonymity'. This idea is found in fiction
and poetry, and also in attempts to mix genres.
Modernism wanted to assert the autonomy of the
different parts, based around one simple notion—'a
great anti-representational rupture'and the
development of autonomous processes and
forms. It is an ideology of art, and it is
always retrospective. It is also deeply
affected by preoccupations about architecture,
social religious and political life, despite its
preoccupation for purer art.
Oddly, modern art as autonomy was a Marxist idea,
something that had become autonomous that promised
emancipation, as in Adorno (or Greenberg).
This led to seeing modern art as the art of
autonomy, which soon collapsed.
So for you, the contradictions of the aesthetic
regime should be maintained? The relations
between wholes and nothing, generalized speech,
universal speech and silent discourses? No
interest in the postmodern?
It is hard to point to the break between the
modern and the postmodern, or to identify
definitively postmodern art. Is it the
return of figuration? The mixing of
genre? Rather than breaks, we should grasp
continuities. There was no simple break with
realism—realism helped develop new perceptions
like 'indifference to subject, close-ups, the
primacy of detail and tone'(206). Painting
was already seen as abstracting from
subjects. Installation is not new either,
and markets like Les Halles were being seen as
installations in 1874 [by Zola]; butchers' windows
were seen as art, so were modern department
stores.
What about Rothko and his interest in
blackness?
This is still not just 'an idea of pure painting',
since Rothko was already becoming mystical
(207). Greenberg actually defined modernism
as a particular type of art done at a particular
time. Modern movements like surrealism
already have roots in romantic thinking about art
and life. Modernism is [a snapshot].
What about Freud and Lacan? The latter in
particular stresses equality and anonymity of
speech?
'I still don't know what to think about
Lacan'. His work was once about the primacy
of the signifier and structuralism, and later 'the
surrealist legacy of Bataille and all those other
movements in the 1930s which wanted in their own
way to rethink relations between aesthetics and
politics'(207), which led him to rethink the
rationality of thought other than as a series of
symptoms. He became interested in silence
and nonsense, both as 'emblems of an absolute
freedom (a la Breton) or… the accursed
share, the opaque residue impenetrable to sense (a
la Bataille)'.
When Freud bases everything on the figure of
Oedipus, a struggle between desire and
enlightenment rationality, Lacan emphasizes
Antigone, who wants to be faithful to the powers
below, and wants only death, and linked this to
the Baader-Meinhof Gang [!]. This is somehow
closer to the notion of aesthetic reason, a notion
of 'classical causalities'.
Will your idea of silent speech simply lead to
silence? What about the mystical tendency
in Bataille 'and to some extent in the writings
of Blanchot, Foucault and Deleuze?']
There is no particular interest in that
generation. 'It all struck me as very
opaque'. It is much more interesting to
think about the notion of the will in the 19th
century, through literature, and the accompanying
problem of how to write, 'untying the
representative knot connecting action, will and
meaning' (208). There is this idea that the
will is maximized when it seeks abdication, a race
towards nothingness, self destruction. Freud
can be seen as commenting on this tradition.
There is no mysticism of silence, but there is a
link between the regime of writing, 'the desertion
of a certain idea of meaning', and the tension
between silent speech and 'self annihilating will'
[pass].
Your own writing is ironic, indignant and
suffused with movement
This is not so much resistance to the death drive
as 'a strategy of writing which tries to put
uncertainty back into statements', challenging
dogmatic statements, by reworking the way that
dogmatism constructs otherness, the one who is
ignorant or naive. Studies of workers
shatter 'the image of the naive believer', since
it always knows that its utopian discourse is
illusory and ironic. It is necessary to make
one's own assertions probabilistic as well, to
avoid affirmative and categorical styles, unlike
philosophy normally.
How do you line up, with Derrida on the
deferral of certainty, and Badiou on axiomatic
equality?
Derrida is interesting but out of kilter, and he
downplays the politics of writing. Foucault
is the closest thinker, his archaeological
project, his discussion of the conditions of
possibility of statements. There are some
similarities with Badiou, a common history, seeing
politics as not state practice. But Badiou
is too affirmative about history, and he sees
events as completely separated from situations,
and exaggerates the effects of statements about
events [those that say it's now impossible to
carry on as before].
What of the future?
There is no great project. The politics of
literature is of interest, so is the aesthetic
regime of arts, but there is no interest in
writing massive volumes about these topics, rather
attempts to focus on 'significant objects and
angles' that 'allow me to say as much as possible
in as little space as possible. I suppose my
idea of research is indissociable from the
invention of a way of writing'(209).
more social theory here
|