NOTES ON: Rancière, J. (1991) The Ignorant
Schoolmaster: Five Lessons in Intellectual
Emancipation, trans and with an intro by Kristin
Ross, Stanford: Stanford University Press. by Dave Harris Translator’s Introduction [Locates Rancière in French soc of ed – pass on if not particularly interested] When this book first appeared, in 1987, it appeared only marginal to the radical interests of sociologists of education. The hero, Jacotot, was working in France in the 1830s. Rancière was also a maverick, originally an Althusserian, then a major critic. His research interests turned on 19th century workers’ archives, and he wrote about their desire for emancipation. This book could be seen as a curiosity piece, but it is best seen as a fable ‘that enacts an extraordinary philosophical meditation on equality’ (ix). The French context is important: May ’68 and the aftermath, the decline of the left and the emergence of Bourdieu (and Foucault). Bourdieu always seemed to offer the best explanation of the events, developing a critique of education, but also explaining the conservative nature of social structure as reproduction and distinction. Bourdieu's and Passeron’s The Inheritors suggested that the main role of university was reproduction of inequality, and this was followed by Reproduction and Distinction, which showed how class division was ‘minutely catalogued in the tiniest details of posture or daily behaviour’, a welcome diversion from conventional Marxist politics. Rancière attacked the project on the grounds that it assumed that the excluded were unaware of the mechanisms of their exclusion. Oddly enough, social critics gain status by showing how democracy is unlikely especially in the guise of a science. In practice, it all turned on a tautology— ‘1. Working class youth are excluded from the university because they are unaware of the true reasons which they are excluded (The Inheritors). 2. Their ignorance of the true reasons for is a structural effect produced by the very existence of the system that excludes them (Reproduction).’ (xi), [the quote derived from Rancière, L’Empire du Sociologie] Another way of putting this tautology is to argue that the system is able to reproduce because it is unrecognized, and it is unrecognized because it deliberately produces misrecognition [what is tautological about this? Depressingly 'eternal', certainly]. It is convenient, that the system can forever hide itself, and it implies that only sociologists can see through the system, not teachers or students. The real point was to produce sociology as a science ‘through a naturalizing objectification of the other’ (xii). [As an aside, try Magri’s mild and largely implicit criticism of Deleuze (in Negotiations) as a permanent aporia. Deleuze cannot make up his mind politically – first of all it is radical desire that will break through repression, then it is advanced schema of repression that will control us all; we all need to become revolutionaries and experiment with becomings, but we also have to be very cautious and not end up in micro-fascism or self-destruction. As soon as he analyses one pole, he wants to reopen it all and rethink it, and often come to opposite conclusions. Deleuzians can pose as revolutionaries, knowing there are always good reasons in the master’s work why they should not actually be revolutionaries because it is far too risky.] Bourdieu’s was a popular project too by offering the pleasures of demystification and the unveiling of the structuralist mechanism, and the justification for progressive practice [it was apparently incorporated by the socialist administration of Mitterrand]. One minister of education, Savary, set out to establish a new radical educational community, an egalitarian atmosphere in schools focusing on the “whole personality” of the child, and compensatory education in priority zones, which included ‘specially designed curricula’ (xiii). His successor, Milner, abandoned these reforms and focused instead on ’”republican elitism”’, back to basics, a restoration of grammar, rigid examinations and selection (xiii). The debate got mixed up with a more general one about French identity. The transition to republican elitism was facilitated by a polemic by Milner, who talked of a plot against knowledge, and who attacked pedagogy as an empty science. Advocating the rigours of the Third Republic, he argued that teachers should just focus on transmitting knowledge, and the inequality between teacher and student was necessary and helpful. Rancière agreed with Milner that it would be wrong to cut back on formerly transmitted knowledge, and provide a special curriculum for working class kids, and immigrants. Maternalism in education was -- infantalizing. But the past regime was tainted by ‘the hygienic project of moral formulation’ (xv), and the debate was couched in the wrong terms – the old education was never fully involving, and scholarly passion always reflected the interests of the elite. Both Milner and Rancière had been disciples of Althusser, and belong to that of circle that included Balibar and Debray—but both have moved on considerably since, in an era characterized by the defeat of European worker movements in Europe, May ’68 which demolished orthodox Marxism, the recuperation and turn to the free market, and the development of the New Philosophy and post structuralism. Nevertheless, Althusser had also argued that teaching should be about transmitting determinate knowledges and was thus inevitably inegalitarian. Rancière’s approach was different in
his Lesson of Althusser. He read Althusser
predominantly as an educational theorist, pointing out
that his only political intervention was to deal with
student discontent expressed in the French Communist
Party. Students
themselves had already begun to criticize pedagogical
relations and the reproductive function of education, the
arbitrariness of exams, and ‘the ideology of individual
research’ (xvi). Althusser
said that students should first learn about marxism and
then conduct proper scientific analyses; then focus on the
quality of knowledge rather than pedagogy; then focus on
the ideology in the content of teaching. [You can see what
Althusser said about French students in my notes here] Rancière argued that the science/ideology distinction was simply to justify pure knowledge and the privilege of those who possessed it. It left becoming an academic as the only option for students. The general illusions can only be dispelled following ‘a kind of muscular theoretical heroism on the part of the lone theorist’ (xvii) [shades of Deleuze here too]. This is why Althusser had to denounce May ’68, only to pretend to discover its potential later following solitary research—the result was the notion of the school as an ideological apparatus. May ’68 was not the proper moment for the all-knowing philosopher: this ‘is to eternalize the division of labour that grants [philosophy] its place’ (xviii). Does philosophy have any other authority than its privileged place? How did it speak for those in assumes to be ignorant? This is where the project of conducting archival research becomes important, since it shows a number of figures who have emancipated themselves from necessity, and who have openly claimed the right to contemplation and thought. [British authors who have done something similar are a superb and encouraging read – Thompson, E. (1968) The Making of The English Working Class, Harmondsworth: Pelican Books, and Rose, J. (2002) The Intellectual Life of the British Working Classes, London: Yale University Press.] Rancière apparently describes this as an irruption of negativity, in a good sense, of the rejection of the necessity of constantly doing something, and a rejection of positivism. The archival research has been paralleled with a critique of bourgeois intellectuals and their claims to speak for ‘the privileged other of political modernity, the worker’ (xix), and this leads to a critique of explication. The educational theories of Bourdieu, Milner and Althusser are all founded on the notion of inequality—they begin with it, and then prove it, and then are obliged to rediscover it over and over. This extends even to those who want to do progressive reforms of schools. As a result, the future reconciliation is always distant, ‘a distance discursively invented and reinvented so that it may never be abolished. The poor stay in their place’ (xix), and pedagogues remain superior to their students. The answers to make equality a presupposition instead, the centre of practice in the present. And this is what provided by Jacotot’s story, his experiments and his subsequent experience. The assumption is that everyone is equally intelligent, and it follows that prior knowledge is not necessary, nor is explication of. Explication in fact creates incapacity, supports the equality of the wider society, and infantilises students. It uses metaphors based in terms of velocity, speed or slowness. In our own time, pedagogy and its fictions have been globalised, so that the developing nations will never catch up. Rancière develops his argument further to critique the idea of progress as additive, of conventional history as additive. Historians need to create an alternative, to capture the unique experience of the past, to serve as an episode of the present [compare with Foucault’s archaeology], to be interrogated politically. Rancière seems to offer a simple narrative structure, a recounting, one of the exercises seen as crucial in the book, and one which assumes equality with the reader. But there is also a moment where the identity of the narrator becomes unclear— Rancière’s voice merges with Jacotot’s, and his commentary extends and dramatizes, continues Jacotot’s account[cf 'indirect free discourse' in Deleuze] This links the past with the present, and there is one basis for this in that both writers are experiencing post revolutionary politics. The uncertainty helps the reader locate the account in the present, and evokes questions such as the connections between the commentators of the 18th century and the sociologists of the 20th. It raises satirical possibilities, the strange irruption or untimeliness of the piece is an opposition to the seamless tautologies of modern sociology and structuralist linguistics. The book returns the notion of equality to the centre, ‘against the seamless science of the hidden’ (xxii) that says it is impossible. Promoting equality means celebrating a number of small concrete acts and actual moments, that resist institutionalization –hence the final irony of the title, because Jacotot had no school. [And now some quick notes on the book itself] This is an admiring commentary on the work of an early pedagogue (Jacotot) who discovered that he could teach people even though he knew nothing about the subject. It works if we assume a fundamental equality of ability between all concerned – if people can learn to speak their entire language, they can learn anything else that is human. The big pedagogic mistake is to do explication – this assumes that learners must have expert mediators, and that they can never match the expertise of those mediators. [It also gives that ‘stage managed’ tone to questions in seminars, where the pedagogue already knows the answer and the learner just has to guess it, to the boredom of both. Much better to ask genuine questions, but that involves choosing topics at least where you really do not know the answer – about modern club culture or leisure activities, or actual practice which you do not do yourself, for example] However, this gives no credence to the modern fashion for teaching languages by only speaking them. This pedagogy is based on books or other texts (like prayers) which serve as the neutral ground between learner and teacher. And the pedagogy is very unfashionable – students learn by heart the whole book, in the original language of the book in some cases, and are tested frequently on their knowledge of it [I don’t know who corrects the pronunciation – but spoken facility is not the point? However, it raises a point which Deleuze would be critical about – doesn’t all this community learning lead to consensus and ‘common sense’? Or does the pedagogue have a hidden role here in keeping it all open, dragging the readers onwards – to elite culture? Can the pedagogue really abandon his elite culture in general? It reminds me of those awful school English lessons I used to have where there were apparently no right answers when it came to poetry appreciation – but it was clear there were wrong ones, and nasty proles like me tended to offer them, as a sign of our irredeemable vulgarity]. Quite high powered books were used too – Télémaque (a classic text about Telemachus, the son of Ulysses) . Memorising gives a sense of mastery, and all good learners have done it including famous philosophers [ and certainly loads of famous social theorists have been translators first]. Quite a few of us do it in a sort of implicit and shamed way, thinking it is not ‘the right way’ – I spent a lot of time memorizing my best bits for my PhD oral exam, but contrived to make it look spontaneous [see below],and have done the same for presentations since. Once you have learned the book you can proceed to other operations. Reading, for example, can be pursued by asking people to look at the first words in the text which will be the same ones that they have memorized. They can be asked to look for those words elsewhere, asked to write the words, to focus on the letters in them and so on. Learners are also tested for understanding: it is not enough to parrot back the words, they have to think about them and comment on them. Rancière claims a fundamental equality persists because it is all new to the pedagogue too. His hero deliberately set out to teach painting or the piano even though he could not paint or read music. He helped someone learning Greek, although he did not know it himself, by asking the learner to isolate and write down some Greek words then point to them in the text -- mistakes were a sign of insufficient attention at least. The book is full of examples of how Jacotot argued his case against sceptics. The bourgeoisie, including senior academics, were invited to examine student work (the tests were things like asking them to write something which commented upon and extended the texts they had read, making reference to them – or they were given short texts to read by the visitors and then asked to extemporize). Most visitors agreed this was quality work -- although one professor found a minor error (a missing accent). The conclusion is that it is perfectly possible to go from a narrow base to think about and comment upon anything: ‘everything is in everything’. I also liked the way Jacotot/Rancière addressed scepticism from the students too. He would brook no excuses. When they said they ‘can’t’ do anything he argued this meant that they could but did not want to. When they dismissed academic learning as elitist tosh, he pointed out that their own pride in their common sense or their practical expertise was also elitist, and, very often, their contempt for ‘ordinary people’ was strong. [I am reading this at the same time as reading Hume, in bed at night, for fun, and I wish they would get together. Hume says there is nothing dishonourable in sceptical philosophy even if it seems absurd from the point of view of common sense – everyone has their specialisms. What’s wrong with inquiring about the foundations (sic) of common sense perceptions? etc] I am also starting to worry that this
is getting very French and that an educated mind is being
seen in elitist terms—the ability to spout on about
anything at short notice that Bourdieu sees as the
required oral style at least.
The argument was pursued through various 19th century philosophical disputes about will and intelligence, and picks up en route early claims that the physiological study of brains will solve all these problems (brain science in those days was phrenology). The ultimate conclusion is that human beings have will, they act, and they use their intelligence to do so. Here is a nice bit: Intelligence’s act is to see and to compare what has been seen. It must seek to repeat, to create the conditions to re –see what it has seen, in order to see similar facts, in order to see facts that could be the cause of what it has seen. It must also form words, sentences, and figures, in order to tell others what it has seen. In short, the most frequent mode of exercising intelligence, much to the dissatisfaction of geniuses, is repetition. And repetition is boring. The first vice is laziness. It is easier to absent oneself… “I can’t” is one of these absence sentences. “I can’t” is not the name of any fact. Nothing happens in the mind that corresponds to that assertion (55). Lots of goodies are tucked up in that quote including the view that language is an arbitrary expression of intelligence (early opponents were French linguistic colonizers denying the human subject etc – we recognize them still in structuralism,and not just Althusserian stuff). Language does not form communities, but collections of people struggling to understand each other. The willed struggle to understand the somewhat arbitrary utterances of others is really what lies at the basis of the teaching efforts based on books that neither the teacher nor the student know. [Note that this attempt to understand others, to learn from others is precisely what Deleuze seems to be against in his dislike for conversation and discussion – he alone can pursue the truth and mixing with intellectual inferiors would only be distracting]. Gaining knowledge is therefore improvising, doing, a kind of poetry, artisanal. It can be guided and introduced gradually so as not to frighten people. [One example is to teach painting by first asking kids to talk about pictures, train their attention etc. Rancière admits this will not produce excellent painters, but says it is more important that people do not feel they cannot paint – another section which will be cited in support by progressives. Would you like surgeons trained on the same basis? One clear and radical implication emerges for me though – intelligence cannot be assessed, even progressively. If we have to have assessment, it ought to measure different things, like technical competence, and be far more modest]. Effective writing and speech is a craft
and should be learned eg by studying poets. Their goal is
to translate thoughts into words AND allow people to
countertranslate, investing each word with an ‘aura’ (69)
[the ‘writerly‘ text in Barthes – the danger is that this
becomes the incomprehensible blathering or delirious text
like Deleuze. Be fair though –maybe Deleuze really is
writing writerly texts? This is what he claims] [This is
the very opposite of rationalized ,definitional ‘effective
teaching’ as she is currently known in official quality
stuff, of course]. This implies that the reader/listener
is of equal intelligence, capable of adding meanings that
the poet cannot – intelligence is equality.
However, the actual societies and communities that the individual learners form are quite another matter. Chapter 4 starts with Jacotot being visited by an indignant and pompously critical Belgian minister of education! The tendency is to meet people who will preserve their own self esteem by expressing nothing but contempt for the learning of others. Very often, debate is about which form of superiority is really superior—‘preponderance’! This is a typical form of distraction and it leads to intellectual laziness [This used to be called comp kid culture, before that became politically incorrect, and of course it’s not confined to comprehensive schools. Any bright kid will know what this means, as their achievements are routinely belittled, denied, and rendered inferior to more routine achievements, like being popular or knowing about football. As a result, bright kids hide their achievements, do not participate in lessons, give up their own ambitions in order to show they belong. This is the downside of any community education, and it is never discussed. I knew this only too well as a kid. In my own modest recent experience, I have had a colleague tell me off for using long words at a planning meeting—one long word was ‘validation’—and this was followed by a plea to recognize his views as superior because he had lots of experience ‘in the real world’] Rancière quotes Jacotot and Bentham on the ways in which dominant groups to do this so effectively, using political rhetoric [and it reminded me an awful lot of managerial rhetoric as well. And academic language in Bourdieu’s study of professorial discourse while we are here!] One technique is to express false modesty, denying that one has any expertise to discuss proposals put forward: what is really being said is that even a talented person such as myself cannot see anything to discuss in this proposal, so what is its real worth? There is some marvellous stuff on managerial and political rhetoric which seeks out vague and florid language deliberately to evade—apparently Bentham refers to this [actually legal language] as a perverted kind of poetry, and that includes using metaphors like the ones about the body politic. It is intended to produce silence and submission. Rhetorical contests between speakers do this, by trying to silence others with appropriate words or sentences, regardless of the actual case, in a game of verbal trumps. In order to be good at it, you have to be a sophist, and submit to your own irrationality. As a result, the masses come to see themselves as stupid. [Rancière gets close to what Adorno has called ‘malicious egalitarianism’, or the fascist personality, which operates as do cyclists in the German proverb ‘above they bow, they kick below’—see the work on authoritarianism]. Mass stupidity is contagious unfortunately, and equality comes to look impossible. All this is necessary because ‘there is no natural reason for domination’ (87). It is only a dangerously apparent and always about to surface equality, with its dangers of equal rights, that produces all this effort put into justifying inequality. Philosophers who create ideal social orders do not realize that social orders cannot be rational—social life itself imposes some material deadweight on intelligence. This goes for the idea of an open democratic society, as well as the one hoping that a Philosopher King would emerge. People are alienated from their leaders, changing their humanity for the notion of a citizenship. ‘Truth settles no conflict in the public place’ (90)—it travels alone. Social forces cannot be made subject to rationality. Duties can never be made to imply rights. Most citizens are prepared to trade their reason for a bit of social order. Reason can remain personal and individual, and often gets channelled into the idea of leading a virtuous life, remaining as ‘an impenetrable stronghold in the middle of irrationality’ (92). But ‘the battlefield is the true portrait of society’ (92), and tolerance of others gives way when there are radically unequal powers. All individuals can do is try to preserve themselves as living beings, while obeying orders as citizens. Often, reason has to be suspended. Nevertheless, opportunity should always be taken to intervene using reason—but the reasonable person is in for a fight and has to use weapons such as rhetoric and inside knowledge. The creative learner can do this, just as they can expand their knowledge from one book [so academic literacy approaches are best!] Nevertheless, the main function of rhetoric is not persuasion but distraction. Does this mean that teaching must embrace political cynicism? Opportunities must be tested and activity verified, just as in the process of learning we began with. Sophistry can be undone by a knowledge of sophistry, passion can be matched by will. ‘He who knows how to remain true to himself in the middle of irrationality will triumph over the passions of others exactly as he triumphs over his own’ (95). Again, there is this assumption of equality of intelligence—it’s not just our leaders who lie. We must not think ourselves superior to bullshitters! We must analyze and dissect their techniques, and use them ourselves [especially some of the more populist techniques, I think he is implying]. At least we will preserve ‘the miracle
of reasonable moments’ inside social order (96) [here and
elsewhere in this section, the main examples seem to be
the discussions of the classic philosophers in ancient
Greece]. Self
knowledge is emerging [this sounds quite like Deleuze on
the subversive power of minority languages]. This may be a
daydream, but we can always resist ‘inegalitarian madness’
at least (98). It
is important to emancipate individuals if not whole
classes. [Not much of an actual programme here then? Isn't
this going from optimism to pessimism in exactly the same
way as Bourdieu?]
The last chapter details the principles
and their sad fate when various groups and bodies tried to
institutionalize them in various schools, learned
societies and journals. Strangely,
some of these enthusiasts also flirted with the Lancaster method, which they
saw as a form of self instruction. Jacotot did get a lot
of attention and support, especially in post-1830 France,
and his disciples sent out to spread the word, but later,
his particular views about radical equality of
intelligence were seen as a mere personal opinion,
something to be detached from his actual methods.
Basically, it all got routinized again, mixed with the old
pedagogic practices, and Jacotot was left isolated as a
lone voice. He
did have a good way of sorting out potential disciples
though—anyone who wanted to explicate was shown the door.
However, even
the notion of emancipation got recuperated, and became the
name of a journal run by the Society for the Propagation
of Universal Teaching, ‘a society whose vice president
pleaded eloquently for the necessity of qualified masters’
(135). Rancière
thinks the message will survive though, as a kind of faith
in the everyday etc. [So what does this sad recuperation
tell us about the difference between an abstract right to
speak and an actual struggle to retain a voice? The mere
assumption of equality does not seem very helpful? This is
only a way to preserve the critical and lofty status of
philosophy as above vulgar politics? It is an intellectual
refuge after the failure of activism?] Meanwhile, here are some nice quotes: ‘Use all possible means of convincing the ignorant one of his power’ (101). [I do worry about this because it looks like liberal empowerment approaches, but that empowerment means encouraging people to feel they can manage official curricula]. ‘There are 100 ways to instruct, and learning also takes place [even] at the stultifiers’ school; a professor is a thing… He can be learned observed, imitated, dissected, put back together’ (102) ‘Let’s affirm then, the universal
teaching will not take, it will not be established in
society. But
it will not perish, because it is the natural method of
the human mind’ (105). [naturalism!] ‘Stultification is not an inveterate superstition; it is fear in the face of liberty. Routine is not ignorant; it is the cowardice and pride of people who renounced their own power for the unique pleasure of affirming their neighbour’s incapacity’ (108). ‘In fact, only an emancipated person is untroubled by the idea that the social order is entirely conventional; only he can scrupulously obey superiors that he knows are his equals’ (109). ‘in order to be concerned with these abstractions, these ontologies [progress, educating the people], other abstractions—corporations—were necessary’ (116). ‘A man of progress is something else as well: a man whose thinking takes the opinion of progress as its point of departure, who erects that opinion to the level of the dominant explication of the social order’ (117). ‘Whoever says order says distribution into ranks’ (117) ‘With these four terms, good and evil, before and after, we have the matrix of all explications’ (117). ‘Progress is the new way of saying inequality… pedagogy is spontaneously progressive… And this disorder within stultification left some space open for emancipation. [However] progress is the pedagogical fiction built into the fiction of the society as a whole… Before, steps were taken gropingly, blindly… Things were guessed at. Now a new age is beginning… Methods are necessary. The century of Progress is that of the triumphant explicators, of humanity pedagogicized’ (119 – 20). ‘This is the progressives’ circle. They want to tear minds away from the old routine, from the control of priests and obscurantist of any kind. And for that, more rational explications and methods are necessary...for this a system of public instruction is necessary (121). ‘The permanent pedagogical revolution becomes the normal regime… It was a tether… Less for what it could furnish in the way of instruction than for what it could make people believe about the inegalitarian fiction’ (122). ‘instruction would no longer be a privilege; rather the lack of instruction wold be an incapacity. To oblige the people to get educated, any man of 20 who could not read in 1840 should be declared an incapable civilian’ (125). ‘And so universal teaching, and even the words intellectual emancipation could be put in the service of progressives’ (127) [by producing a simplified explication—maybe a bit like Bentham here?. Rancière notes that the old privileged schools and institutions did not actually disappear in this sort of educational reform]. ‘A progressive explicator is first of all an explicator, that is to say, a defender of inequality’ (128). ‘with the system of perfected explications came the installation of the system of perfected examinations... The unbendable power of the inequality of intelligence over the path of whoever might wish to move through society at his own pace’ (130). ‘If this principle [the inequality of intelligence] is granted, then one consequence alone can logically be deduced from it: the intelligent caste’s management of the stupid multitude’ (131). ‘[is difficult to get people to believe this] Even Joseph Jacotot himself would never have understood it without the chance event that had turned him into the ignorant schoolmaster. Only chance is strong enough to overturn the instituted and incarnated belief in inequality’ (133). ‘One must choose to attribute reason to
real individuals or to their fictive unity. One must choose
between making an unequal society out of equal men and
making an equal society out of unequal men... whoever takes
this [second] position has only one way of carrying it
through to the end, and that is the integral
pedagogicization of society—the general infantilization of
the individuals that make it up. Later on this
will be called continuing education, that is to say, the
coextension of the explicatory institution with society’
(133). [What would
developing the first option look like?] ‘social progress was first of all progress in the social order’s ability to be recognized as a rational order. This belief could only develop to the detriment of the emancipatory efforts of reasonable individuals… An enormous machine was revving up to promote equality through instruction. This was equality represented, socialized, made unequal, good for being perfected—that is to say deferred from commission to commission, from report to report, from reform to reform, until the end of time’ (134). ‘The panecastician [the name given to the approach by Jacotot himself, referring back to the idea that everything is in everything]... doesn’t recognize any hierarchy among orators or discourses… [but] is interested in all discourses, in every intellectual manifestation, to a unique end: to verify that they had put the same intelligence to work, to verify, by translating the one into the other, the equality of intelligence’ (136) [and apparently, the Jacotot journal analysed a number of competing philosophical discourses to expose the art they used to express their views, including showing some of the literary works that were alluded to. Each was rendered as a story. This apparently led to a rather strange relativism, where proletarians had to recognize the equal weight of defenders of freedom of the press as well as adversaries—both would show the rather abstract notion of the intelligence of antagonistic positions. This apparently empowered proletarians. Jacotot apparently believed that that was the point, rather than searching for the truth, page 138] [But this does get back to the translator’s intro and the problems Rancière identified with Bourdieu and the endless circularity stuff. He has an endlessly circular argument too! It’s the old stuff about hope versus a realization that societies are about order. He even admits people want order themselves, they are afraid of liberty etc. He spends a lot of time trying to show how privilege reproduces itself through fancy discourses,but not as well as Bourdieu. About the only differences are that Rancière has more hope, he opts for the alternative of liberty as counterfactual etc – but that maybe because his analysis of social repro is not as good as Bourdieu’s {it seems to turn on potential and rising expectations etc}. It does seem a bit decisionistic, although there maybe some human anthropology in there [Man is a Liberty-Seeking individual etc] He does run the risk of somehow eternalizing the struggle between hope and repression, partly by discussing this historical example not modern cases. There is something too of the eternal and endless hesitation between the options of hope and order, characteristic of Deleuze and his followers.] back to ed studs |