Notes on:
Bourdieu, P. (2001) Masculine Domination,
translated by Richard Nice. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Dave Harris
[Quick notes only.] This book is really
important part of Bourdieu's work in my
view. He says he is interested in masculine
domination because it is the most widespread form
and he has persisted across a number of societies
and centuries. So it offers a particular
case study for anyone interested in how domination
manages to reproduce itself. It is also the
one that is perhaps the most misunderstood, seen
as internal or based on something
biological. For Bourdieu, it is an arbitrary
symbolic system that produces dispositions and
practices that produces male domination. For
example, the biological differences between the
sexes have to be symbolically ordered to make the
female ones inferior. Psychoanalytic emphasis on
the phallus ignores the other social dimensions of
domination. Virginia Woolf's To the Lighthouse
gives a detailed account of male perspectives on a
range of things.Loads of footnotes support the
arguments and there are the customary asides in
smaller tyypeface.
Chapter 1
The analysis itself is quite ingenious that the
whole symbolic order supports male domination, and
not just the most obvious ones to do with sex or
childbearing. This is going to make it the
most ambitious excavation of the system of
dispositions yet.We can see this best if we look
at Kabylia. Here, everything is coded in
terms of male domination - the layout of the home,
public spaces, market activities [and possibly
even the nouns and verbs are gendered]. As
with Durkheim on primitive classifications, these
codes developed from basic terms developed into
whole systems and semiologies - things like nature
and culture as in Levi Strauss, but also wet and
dry, up and down, action and inaction, honor and
dishonour. As usual, it is not just ideas
but practices themselves that embody these codes,
which is a possible source of departure from Levi
Strauss, and it is a matter of domination not just
communication. We see this for example in the
agoraphobia of Kabylian women -- fear of entering
a public space which is a male domain, or in
characteristic ways of standing or walking. If we
want to understand male domination we have to see
it as it is displayed and spread throughout
society - it is not just a matter of
consciousness, and so strategies to awaken female
consciousness are limited. It is a matter of
the logic of practice (to which there are links).
Kabylian practice is ingenious as ever -- if there
is no male heir, for example, a man has to be
acquired to marry a daughter but he becomes almost
an honorary woman, living with the bride's family,
a kept man: everyone conspires to conceal this
unorthodox beginning to the marriage to save the
honour of the family.
Bourdieu gets quite pessimistic here, confirming
almost everything Rancière
says about him - social reproduction seems so
effective that it's almost impossible to conceive
of anything that would ever bring about radical
enough change ( so a great excuse to do nothing
would be Rancière's take -- but is optimism better
than actual knowledge of the problem, however
pessimistic?) . Indeed some of B's asides
indicate the stubborn persistence of the symbolic
order of male domination, such as taking for
granted that bodies should be sexed, that female
bodies are distasteful, that women prefer male
partners who are taller (supported by survey
data). Kabylian society has loads more examples --
ploughing and impregnation are more important than
tending to growing crops and foetuses. There
is no account of how all this started of course,
so maybe 'radical feminism' canbelet back in -- it
all starts with the vulnerability of women at
childbirth -- but this would still be some
imaginary starting point, inconsequential compared
to ongoing reproduction which requires no
originating myth.
Males also get trapped though -- they are bound by
codes of honour which include having to be potent
all the time (hence massive demand for
aphrodisiacs and Viagra), and to defend their
honour with violence (persisting in cults of
violence in modern society, including violent
sports and degradation ceremonies). They
have to always stand up straight and look other
men in the eye. Women have power as exercisers of
the irrational -- magic or cunning -- which also
demeans them of course.
While discussing this topic, Bourdieu also refines
his understanding of other terms. The
habitus is still a matter of the system of
dispositions and visions, supported by practices
in the form of illusio, but
differentiations according to gender seem to start
with the very formation of the habitus
itself. The system depends on symbolic
violence, discussed at some length in the first
chapter, and Bourdieu is at pains to say that
symbolic violence includes physical violence,
which only has an effect because it carries a
symbolic charge. One consequence of symbolic
violence is a sense of shame, and Bourdieu argues
that this is prior to all the passions (38), and
emotions such as guilt, humiliation, anxiety, or
even the nicer sentiments like love, admiration
and respect - shame, of course is an anticipated
reaction from 'society', an acceptance of dominant
values.
Chapter 2
The project is aimed at an amnesis (opposite of
amnesia) an is to proceed as does proper ethnology
-- acquire knowledge at the ordinary level then
systematise it eg as a series of oppositions
[theoretical reconstruction not generalization in
the usual sense -- Levi Strauss again]. These are
both collective and individual. Sexual
differentiation is an immense labour, focused on
the body, producing sexed habituses, developed in
'ideal' conditions in Kabylia but present in our
societies too. This differentiation is performed
constantly in lots of little ways, often without
deliberate intentions -- and include conventions
of dress and behaviour, occupational structures
like little harems at work, conformity of
vocations and opportunities as always.
Double standards exist even where work is similar
--eg chefs and mere cooks: these are the same
processes as in conferring nobility discussed
elsewhere. Self-fulling expectations mean people
treated as women become women --eg too weak to
lift heavy weights etc --a 'reverse or negative
Pygmalion effect' (61) [body-focused stuff again].
Male definitions become seen as universal [I think
of a colleague's definition of the teacher
professional -- someone neat, well-dressed, on top
of his subject etc , or, in other words, a married
man who has someone to clean his clothes, look
after the household etc]. Because so much of it is
unconscious -- like bodily hexis -- women can
never succeed in performing credibly. Ther is no
universal 'human' condition to aspire to.
Emphasising 'female' virtues like being able to
relate to people still reproduces these
differences -- it is still a 'product of the
historical relation of differentiation'
(63). [All negative again then].
For women, perceptions and self perceptions of the
body become crucial in the exercise of symbolic
power. Bourdieu goes on to describe a number
of ways in which the body becomes important in
social interactions, pointing out again ndeed it
is not just our ideas of the body found in
discourses like those of fashion or beauty, but a
deeper set of codes. Binaries such as
big/small valorize male bodies, leading, among
others, to female anxieties about being too big,
and male ones about being too small. In
turn, these lead to metaphors such as overlooking
things, in folding things, exerting authority and
the rest. The thing is that these codes and
metaphors don't look as if they are sexed.
The ideal male body is self sufficient as an
object requiring no attribution of subjectivity
[justified by examining the respect and deference
accorded to male statues!]. For women, there
is almost no way to escape constant comparisons
between their real and the ideal female body,
including bodily behaviour. It is not just a
matter of the gaze [attributed to Sartre here
(65)], but the underlying schemes of perception
and the wielding of symbolic power
Bodily hexis is crucial and it refers both to the
shape of the body or physique and the way it is
carried, deportment, and bodies are supposed to
offer clues as to the real nature of the person
[so fat people lack moral self control]. It
also takes on connotations of social class as we
know from Bourdieu 1986. The petty bourgeois
are particularly prone to anxiety and
embarrassment. Classic emotions affect women such
as shame, timidity, alienation and embarrassment,
and they also experience characteristic female
behaviour, such as being friendly and attentive,
smiling, being demure or coquettish and so on, a
kind of domesticated and pleasing heteronomy
(66). Female interest in romantic love is a
way of canceling out the importance of the
body. There is also an interesting aside on
sport for women (67), which can lead them to
realise that they have 'the body for one's
self... an active and acting body'.
But of course women then have to pay the price of
being seen as not proper women.
When considering female visions of males, Bourdieu
turns to Woolf, especially To the Lighthouse
[I have never read this novel so I can't comment
on his accuracy, not that that is an issue.The
discussion provoked in me several moments of
guilty recognition]. The author comments on
the central male character, Mr. Ramsay, whom we
encounter reciting poetry aloud, which turns out
to be The Charge of the Light Brigade.
He evidently pursues military metaphors as a guide
to conducting himself as a proper man, and this
makes him both an imposing character and a
child. The key scene arises when he attempts
to disillusion his son by adopting a kind of
aggressive realist position about the inevitable
failure of plans [in this case because the weather
will prevent a visit to the light house].
This is a kind of male prophecy, 'a forecast of
science'(70), the statement of unanswerable
wisdom: symbolic violence. Underneath lies
the reality principle asserted against the
pleasure principle, as a kind of vocation for men,
to align themselves with necessity.
Asserting reality is a kind of 'pitiless
solicitude', 'kill-joy realism, complicit with the
order of the world' (71), and it leads his son to
hate him, because he detects the arbitrary nature,
and the weak conformity of it all. Male
realism disillusions children and ridicules women.
Woolf uses 'indirect free speech' to represent
both the child's point of view and the fathers, to
show the fragility of his high self esteem.
It is all based on insisting on the truth,
including the truth that life is difficult and
'facts uncompromising' so we need courage and
endurance. This is in effect a 'free
affirmation of a choice', to opt for the masculine
role and therefore to stand on the side of
aggression, against indulgence. There is
more than a hint of a self fulfilling prophecy in
this view of the world.
Almost inevitably, it is accompanied by acting
like a child, indulging in fantasies, including
one that sees the academic game as like war, with
the same 'soldierly valour'(73). Life is a
struggle for recognition accepting that it is
rare. Thinking these thoughts, Mr. Ramsey's
body stands upright, and he squares his
shoulders. What links the military and the
intellectual, and makes one a metaphor for the
other is 'the ludic illusio' (74). Luckily,
this makes the academic illusio as glamorous as
the military one, but much less risky. No
wonder males exhibit so much 'visceral investment,
the expression of which is essentially postural',
evoking statues, memorials, uprightness,
rectitude.
This is the 'original illusio, which is
constitutive of masculinity', and it is found in
all specific forms of the urge to dominate.
Men willingly let themselves be instructed in
games that are socially assigned to them, 'of
which the form par excellence is war' (74).
Men like to enter into 'collective collusion'(75)
to preserve this illusio, to represent what they
do as serious [and heroic, and also
pathetic]. They rapidly come to see the
nature of the social game 'in which the stake is
some form of domination', and they are socially
initiated, 'and thereby endowed with the libido
dominandi'.
Women are not taken in by these games of fighting
for privilege and treat them with 'amused
indulgence'. This can make them look
frivolous, unable to take an interest in serious
things. However, they are also expected to
display 'affective solidarity with the player',
which often means unconditional support because
they do not know the reality of the game.
[The footnote says this also explains why young
working class women share the sporting passions of
their men, which inevitably looks frivolous and
absurd, as does the opposite reaction of 'jealous
hostility']. They do show some concern and
sympathy for the childishness to which men are
reduced by their symbolic disasters [including
excessive macho displays to their kids which
backfire and make them feel guilty]. Men are
harsh on themselves because they are also victims
'of the inexorable verdicts of the real' (77), and
therefore require pity themselves. Sometimes
this is another male strategy, however. These
implications and meanings are represented in the
novel by what looks like a really ordinary
conversation about visiting lighthouses and being
able to predict the weather, or the fury of men
when contradicted by irrational women, for
example.
Women can clearly indicate that they have seen
through the game played by men and their
'pointlessly serious debates'(78), seeing that
passionate advocacy is really about putting
oneself forward, or a desperate need to constantly
talk about themselves to make an impression and to
reassure themselves. However, this is
'somewhat condescending pity for the male illusio'
is rare, and many women have to enter the game
'vicariously', to support their men in indirect
participation in the games.
'Affective dispositions' like this reflect a
division of labour of domination. Kant has
argued that women need representatives in civil
affairs because of their female nature [so another
dig at him, and, in a footnote, at subsequent
kantians who seem to have the same views about the
masses '(traditionally regarded as feminine)',
(79)]. It is of course the habitus, a second
nature, realized in 'the socially instituted
libido' which then energizes particular libidos
including love of games of power by men, and the
love of powerful men by women. This is also
another example of the effects on the body, and of
misrecognition of the origin of dominant
categories [really arising from 'the very
relationship of domination' (80)]. This
misrecognition leads to 'that extreme form of amor
fati' , a love of the dominant and of
domination, desire for the dominant, even at the
expense of the personal exercise of the desire to
dominate.
Chapter three Permanence and Change.
That it takes the skill of a novelist like Woolf
to penetrate every day practice like this shows
the power of misrecognition. Masculine
domination seems to have persisted across nearly
every known society at whatever stage of economic
or political development they might be, from
Kabylia to Bloomsbury. The condition looks
as if it is eternal or natural, but it really
shows the persistence of practices, and also their
systematic concealment or denial.
We need to look at the operation of particular
'objective and subjective structures' (83),
especially the work of the church, the family, the
state and the education system. These
structures operate in different combinations or
patterns [so a good example of dynamic
reproduction], and explain both objective
hierarchies and 'hierarchical dispositions', which
affect even women themselves. There are
'transhistorical invariants' despite differences
in say the requirement of women to work in one era
and stay at home in another, and they affect even
the notions of normal sexual practice [a
fascinating footnote on 84 says that casual sex by
men with other men was very common until quite
recently, and 'perhaps only after the Second World
War [did] heterosexuality or homosexuality become
an either - or choice'. Proust lives!].
The agencies actually had invariants in common,
and all acted powerfully on the unconscious [and
each are briefly described, 85, 86, with a
reference to his own early work on education -
maybe this in
particular]. The church added a cosmological
dimension, including affecting the structure of
the farming year, the education system presents
gendered academic disciplines and structures, and
offers a particular combination between 'social
destinies' and 'self images' (86) [another
fascinating footnote on 86 shows how Simone De
Beauvoir had to operate with unhelpful academic
classifications imposed by Sartre!]. The
state has supported private patriarchy with 'a
public' patriarchy, emphasizing manly virtues in
definitions of the citizen, say. The split
between welfare and finance is also a reproduction
of 'the archetypal division between male and
female' (88).
There have however been substantial changes.
Masculine domination is not as explicit as it was,
partly thanks to the growth of feminism.
Access to positions in hierarchies for women has
also increased, and family burdens reduced.
Education has been decisive, although it is
autonomous enough not to have affected other areas
drastically - the family, for example.
Nevertheless women now appear much more frequently
in the 'intellectual professions, in
administration and in the various forms of sale of
symbolic services' (90), although 'they remain
practically excluded' from authority positions in
industry, finance and politics. [There is a
hint of a difference between absolute and relative
mobility chances here]. What we have is
'permanence in and through change'(91) [there is
some counterbalance here as well, so that those
professions that become feminised also become
devalued]. [And a buffer zone thesis - women
are represented, but in frequently insecure
occupations, often in welfare and caring. ] Even
when they achieve dominant positions, say in the
area of symbolic goods, they remain as
'"discriminated-against elites"' (92), expected to
pay back by meeting increasing demands, and
sometimes having to act and behave as men.
As a result, women always have 'a negative
symbolic coefficient'(93), like skin colour for
black people or any other visible stigma.
This provides a certain element in common between
women whatever their social position, but they
always remain separated from each other as well,
'by economic and cultural differences', which can
turn on different ways of experiencing masculine
domination [optimism is immediately replaced with
pessimism] . The main general distinction
that remains is the allocation of men to public
and women to private spaces, which is seemingly
based on 'three practical principles' (94):
private domestic functions appropriate to women
extend to their occupations; women can never have
authority over men; men are the ones who handle
'technical objects and machines'. [an aside
refers to the ways in which schools direct women
into particular areas].
Constantly experiencing a gendered social order,
with explicit and implicit reminders, means that
girls internalise masculine domination 'in the
form of schemes of perception and appreciation not
readily accessible to consciousness' (95),
producing a consistent habitus, often transmitted
at the bodily level, and thus resistant
transformation. There may be somewhere a
fear that feminisation threatens the value of
social positions and the sexual identity of its
occupants, and this can produce a violent
emotional reaction, especially if the occupation
is central to manliness.
Differences are actually perpetuated by the
autonomy of the area of symbolic goods and the
sphere of [civil society]. Even if families
are weakened, the reproduction of symbolic capital
is still required, through inheritance [which
seems to be endowing male heirs with particular
masculine forms of cultural capital?]. Women
are still confined to domestic work and the
reproduction of kinship networks and family
integration, and this is the real value of unpaid
domestic labour [it includes keeping the family
together on the telephone or through
anniversaries, and, as women's work, it is usually
denounced as frivolous]. There is a
connection between domestic work and voluntary
work. Women still reproduce and produce
symbolic capital, by maintaining appearances, for
example, or by appearing as attractive partners,
upholding feminine virtues, including a
potentially sexualized body, or managing the every
day aesthetics of decor.
This too gets transferred into paid work as
receptionists and hostesses and so on [the main
example is the Japanese hostess club which
provides businessmen not with sex as much as
personal services, personal attention, simulated
seduction, so that the clients do not even see
themselves as clients, 100]. Women produce
'signs of distinction'[in the sense of class
closure] (101) to help convert economic capital
into symbolic capital: the fashion industry is the
classic female occupation here, with its
'perpetual movement of overtaking and
outflanking'. This spreads down to lower
levels producing both 'aesthetic and
linguistic hypercorrection', and [keeping up with
the Joneses], or by relying on women's
magazines. The market for symbolic goods is
therefore a classic example of [the paradox of the
subject] where women voluntarily submit to
something that dominates them.
The analysis shows the power of the relational
approach, the need to uncover 'the whole set of
social spaces and sub spaces' (102), and not
to work just in separate areas like family or
education. It also shows that dualisms are
still 'deeply rooted in things (structures) and in
bodies' (103), and cannot be wished away by
renaming categories, as post modernists like to
do, or by acts of 'performative magic' [and a
footnote suggests that Butler has now rejected the
voluntaristic view of gender performativity], or
'subversive voluntarism'. It follows
Foucault in attempting to show the historical
dimensions of sexuality, the way in which people
are produced as subjects of desire. It
emphasizes the way in which unconscious
relations between the sexes have developed over
history. However, unlike Foucault, there is
no attempt to contrast modern and ancient visions
of sexuality to display the current features,
since sexuality is developed progressively, as a
result of the interaction between various fields
and their objects. It might have begun as a
source of opposition to mythical reason [rather
obscure here 104], and sexual difference also
energised the development of religious legal and
bureaucratic fields.
There is no attempt to argue that sexual
characteristics are fundamental structuring
alternatives, as in Goffman. They are highly
differentiated historical developments 'arising
from a social space' that is itself highly
differentiated' (104), learned through exposure to
experience in those different fields and their
characteristic oppositions. As we saw,
opposition such as strong/week, hard/soft and so
on are always seen as homologous with the division
between males and females. These oppositions
also support cognitive structures, 'practical
taxonomies' (105), such as the ways in which the
disciplines are divided up in the academic field,
with hard and soft sciences, or more public and
private distinctions. There are also
relations between economic agents and academic
ones in the form of seeing intellectuals is
particularly demonstrating female qualities such
as 'lack of realism, otherworldliness,
irresponsibility' (105-106). This is how the
sexual unconscious gets 'logically extended' (106)
into apparently objective divisions between social
positions, especially in symbolic production [now
apparently including academic activities as well].
But we have to grasp the totality here to see the
constants and the processes of reproduction,
'invisible structures, which can only be brought
to light by relational thinking'. The
relation show the phenomena discussed above, such
as successful women having to pay for their
success, perhaps with unhappy domestic lives, or
how the specialism of women in the domestic
produces the 'representation of the necessary,
unavoidable, or acceptable gap between the
husband's position and the wife's' (107).
Connections like this also explain the persistence
of male domination across different sectors of
society, so masculine domination 'is the ultimate
principle of these countless singular
relationships of domination/submission' (108).
Postscript on domination and love
We might see in this is what Woolf called '"the
pleasure of disillusioning"' (109), which might be
one of the pleasures provided by sociological
analysis [a footnote says that Bourdieu discusses
the pleasures of lucid vision available to
sociological analysis, apparently at the end of Distinction.
It also explains 'some of the most violently
negative reactions aroused by sociology'].
Woolf would also want to emphasize the autonomy of
love - is it autonomous, the only exception to
masculine domination, or is it a supreme example
of symbolic violence after all? Arranged
marriages of various kinds used to show that love
is domination, but also that domination could be
accepted. At the same time, women have
always had the power to fascinate, and bind men,
getting them to forget their social obligations
[and have met with suspicion as a result?].
Can power relations be suspended altogether in
love or friendship? Male conceptions of
hunting or warfare seem to be replaced, domination
gives way to 'anxieties, uncertainties,
expectations, frustrations, wounds and
humiliations' (110). However, any escape is
only accomplished by endless labour, relations
based on full reciprocity and mutual recognition,
even disinterestedness [in the sense of suspending
calculations of interest and instrumental
relations]. In the full economy of symbolic
exchanges, the gift of the self and one's body can
take place, and these can be seen to diametrically
oppose exchanges in the commercial world.
However, pure love is a relatively recent
development, connected to other pure loves of
autonomous objects, like art. It is
'extremely fragile' because it can be seen as
excessive, requiring constant investment, and
continually threatened by a crisis, whether the
'egoistic calculation of the simple effect of
routinization' (111). However, it exists 'as
a practical ideal', especially among women.
It is often seen as a mysterious activity which
alone can escape from the continuous struggles for
symbolic power, or recognition and domination,
leading beyond the usual oppositions between ego
and other, 'and even beyond the distinction
between subject and object', seemingly ending in
some mystical union or fusion where people become
lost in each other. It seems to escape
rivalry, and domination gives way to mutual
recognition, a form of a 'free
alienation'(112). People experience
themselves as capable of creating their beloved,
through activities such as naming each other, and
then to accept themselves as 'the creature of his
creature'. Love becomes an area of supreme
consecration, more important than all those
offered by other institutions and social groups.
Conclusion
Analyzing domination is risky, because it can
confirm the inevitability of domination as well as
mobilizing the victims. Hoping for the best
is not enough, nor can we assume that activism
will prevail. Threats arise whenever a
scientific project pursues some external object:
'"good causes" are no substitute for
epistemological justifications' (113), and good
intentions can sometimes include more calculative
interests anyway. Although we can never get
to value free science, 'the fact remains that the
best of political movements will inevitably
produce bad science, and, in the long run, bad
politics' (114), if it is not prepared to be
critical of itself. We must not simply support
what seems to be real.
There is a danger of trying too hard to avoid
being seen to blame the victims. This can
sometimes lead to a partisan or euphemistic
attempt to use terms such as 'popular culture' or
'culture of poverty' to describe the [criminal?]
situation of [some?] black people in the USA, or
to avoid describing the willing submission of
women in domination. We can sometimes get
'an idealized representation of the oppressed'
arising from an interest in solidarity, ignoring
apparently negative aspects like the collusion of
women in their own domination instead of
explaining them [a footnote warns us of the
reverse tendency as well, to excuse men by arguing
that it is the habitus which produces their
domination. In both cases, we need to study
'objective and embodied dispositions' and attempt
to free both men and women from their
effects]. There is always the risk of
seeming to justify the established order by
describing the properties of the dominated.
'Appearances... always support appearance'
(115), while sociological unveiling produces
condemnation both from conservatives and
revolutionaries. Mckinnon has complained
about the reaction she gets that she is
condescending to women [by portraying them as
victims?], whereas in fact 'she is simply showing
"how women are condescended to"'. The male
analyst is particularly likely to be unable to
conceptualize the effects of masculine domination
without suitable experience [but a footnote
challenges this view that a particularly
privileged analysis must arise 'by the mere fact
of being both subject and object', while insisting
on first person experience offers 'the political
defence of particularisms which justifies a priori
suspicion' and questions universalism which is
central to science].
We must admit that men writing about sexual
difference do face particular problems, perhaps
'unwittingly following justificatory intentions'
and appearing to present presuppositions as
revelations. After all, the argument has
been that there is a particularly deep rooted
opposition between male and female in all
cognitive structures. Even the best of
analysts '(Kant's, Sartre, Freud, even
Lacan…)' can allow the unconscious
categories to intrude into the instruments of
thought that they used to think of the
unconscious.
His own stance can be described as one of
'sympathetic externality' (116), and the intention
is to support 'the immense body of work' produced
by feminists with findings of his own research on
symbolic domination. This might produce a
new orientation, a relational one, 'aimed at
changing those relations'. For example, we
might see that although the domestic unit is a
major site, the symbolic power relations you find
there are situated outside in other agencies like
church, school or state. The current
political controversies about the notion of a
civil contract for homosexual couples shows this
wider context. Feminists have widened the
area of analysis themselves, beyond the private
domain, but they tend to omit more conventional
struggles over agencies even though they
contribute to masculine domination. Feminism
has done good work in exposing 'theoretical
universalism flaunted by constitutional law'(117),
but it tends to operate with 'another form of
fictitious universalism' often favouring women who
are themselves in the spaces occupied by dominant
men.
Political action needs to consider 'all the
effects of domination', the structures relating to
men and women, and the structures of major
institutions which produce the whole social order
itself, perhaps starting with the state.
This sort of analysis will be effective 'no doubt
in the long-term and with the aid of the
contradictions inherent in the various mechanisms
or institutions concerned' [left very much as an
afterthought an unspecified - maybe we are
supposed to look for the sorts of contradictions
of legitimacy exposed in State Nobility?].
Appendix
[Difficult to get this -- particularly cautious
and elusive prose, and maybe some indirect free
speech?] Gay and lesbian movements raises some
important issues. Methodologically, it is
difficult to generalize from what is a very
complex set of 'groups, collectives and
associations'. Homosexuals are not marked
with visible stigma, but are the victims of
'collective acts of categorization'.
(118). They can initially be denied a public
visible existence, as with other groups, with
demands to become public greeted with the
invitation[!] to remain discreet.
Again, the dominated partake of the system of
domination, 'through the destiny affect'.
This takes the form of applying straight
categories of perception to themselves, even
adopting insults, and becoming ashamed. It
is sexual practice here that is subject to
symbolic domination, again reflecting masculine
principles of activity over female principles of
passivity: homosexuals are resented for feminizing
the masculine. Some gays even apply these
principles to themselves even if they are victims
of them, as when they form conventional sorts of
couples after all, or adopt exaggerated
manliness. Conventional perceptions of the
body and the sexual division of labour can be
found, reproducing the conventional links between
sexuality, power and politics, perhaps even
accepting that passive homosexuality is
unnatural.
Analyzing homosexuality can also make us aware of
the politics of sexuality, radically separating
conventional sexual relations from power.
But such 'radical subversion' would have to
involve all the victims of sexual
discrimination. Further paradoxes await in
that to mobilize effectively, means to belong to
one of the classic categories, which can reinforce
the very classification that people are trying to
resist [the Weber paradox of radical
politics].
The alternative might be to aim at a new sexual
order in which the distinction between the
statuses is indifferent, that sexual categories
are constructions, that making these constructions
visible might offer serious challenges -'symbolic
revolution' (120). [Could be Rancière here -- see
Valentine] This
has been adopted by those who want to invert the
stigma and make it a source of pride.
However, acknowledging the social construction
involved can lead to political weakness and
difficulties in organizing, especially if the
logic is followed to acknowledge the large
diversity of sexual identities.
Is the way forward to ask for state
recognition? This would offer progress
from more limited forms of 'symbolic
breaks... provocations' (121).
However, internalized categories and schemes of
thought would also have to be transformed, to
challenge the way in which they produce some 'self
evident, necessary, undisputed natural
reality'. There are still contradictions as
well, in arguing for a particular status, since
this risks being included within dominant norms [I
think. A footnote says that all movements
arising from stigmatise groups oscillate 'between
invisibilization and exhibition, between the
suppression and the celebration of difference',
and also oscillate between the strategies they
adopt according to their circumstances].
Take the problem arising from the notion of a
civil contract - will this institutionalise one of
the members of a homosexual couple as head of
household, making such couples 'invisible'[which
means, I think not special or particular,
normal]. The advantages may not outweigh the
'concessions to the symbolic order'required (122)
[an aside notes that civil contracts have been
common in Nordic countries, and partners sometimes
decide to appear as 'couples of quasi twins'
instead of openly challenging the symbolic order].
Dominant law or orthodoxy already offers
particularistic categories, which it presents as
embodied and natural. To occupy them almost
inevitably will 'imply a form of tacit acceptance
of those constraints'. Members seem either
to have to accept that they are invisible because
natural, or that they are different in a
justifiable way. This is how 'the
universalist hypocrisy' of orthodoxy operates, and
it is able to oppose any particular identities as
a threat to universalism. Symbolic
minorities are always prone to be 'recalled to the
order of the universal' (123), as when gay and
lesbian communitarianism is condemned in the name
of the common law [what does this refer to?].
Particularism is useful to expose 'hypocritical
universalism', but runs the risk of being
universalized itself, for example 'as a form of
ghettoization'. The gay and lesbian movement
often brings together relatively privileged
individuals, 'in terms of cultural capital', which
is useful in symbolic struggle and in the
construction of new categories of perception and
appreciation. It still faces the 'problem of
delegation', however, finding some spokesperson to
embody and express the group. It also tends
to 'atomise into sects'. A successful
struggle seems to involve using the specific
capacities of ' strong subversive dispositions,
linked to a stigmatised status, and strong
cultural capital' in unity with 'the social
movement as a whole', acting as some kind of
avant-garde in terms of theoretical and symbolic
activity.
back to social theory page
( includes more Bourdieu)
|
|