What Deleuze Gets From Nietzsche
Deleuze has written several pieces on Nietzsche in
his collection of essays here, and in
another collection here).
There are sections in each of the main books too
-- Logic of Sense and
Difference and
Repetition. There is even an entire book. When I took
notes on that book, the main problem I had was
reconciling the usual view of Nietzsche as a proto
fascist with Deleuze's admiration. I
understand that there was a context for the
rehabilitation of Nietzsche in French thought,
part of the turn away from Hegel that also saw
interest in Spinoza, and it might just be that
Deleuze did what philosophers do in rehabilitating
formerly unpopular philosophers. Even so,
there are some substantive issues as well.
The first arguments that I
encountered were in Difference and Repetition
(2004)
Deleuze needs to supplement his general argument
in favor of difference rather than repetition by
considering what looks like a celebration of
repetition in Nietzsche's eternal return.
Deleuze insists that the eternal return will not
be a simple repetition of existing arrangements,
but some sort of qualitative change, not a
contradiction in the classic Hegelian sense but
the assertion of difference. Repetition is opposed to the laws
of nature, in Nietzsche’s eternal return, which is
not just a banal cyclical event, but ‘the
universal and the singular reunited, which
dethrones every general law, dissolves the
mediations and annihilates the particulars’ (2004:
8). Stressing difference in the eternal return
supports the equally important notion of
becoming: 'the being of becoming… The
becoming identical of becoming itself' (50-- 51).
The assertion of
difference as an inherent quality of Being helps
us stave off philosophical notions of some
univocal identity explaining being (as in
essentialism), and the dubious generalizations of
science.
The return justifies and demonstrates other
aspects of Deleuzian ontology. It is intensive, driven by
difference.
It is being, ‘the only Same which is said
of this world...[ which] excludes any prior
identity’ (304).
Deleuze says that Nietzsche was
interested in the contemporary notions of energy
in the science of the time, hoping ‘to make
chaos an object of affirmation’, and he saw this
sort of thinking which breaks the laws of nature
as the highest thought. At its most
obscure, possibly, the argument is that the
eternal return also features pure difference, has
series which return in a coexisting kind of way,
with no obvious origin except in difference. It
features 'the for- itself of difference' (153). This
notion of univocity is superior to that of
analogy. Analogy
does operate with fixed elements which remain
the same, and variable elements. Univocity,
however argues that although being operates in a
single sense, this still produces difference,
which is ‘mobile and displaced within
being’(377).
This connection is outside of
representation.
Being is univocal, while actualizations
[?] are equivocal.
Categories are a poor substitute for the
notion of the unity of all forms in being. It
also misunderstands how difference works to
distribute beings in a space produced by
univocal being, with no assumptions about fixed
and variable elements, as in analogy. Univocity
is open. It
features nomadic distributions, crowned anarchy
as opposed or sedentary distributions in
analogy. In
univocal being everything is equal and
everything returns, but only when difference is
allowed full play.
‘A single and same voice for the whole
thousand – voiced multiple, a single and same
Ocean for all the drops, a single clamor of
Being for all beings: on condition that each
being, each drop and each voice has reached the
state of excess—…
that difference which displaces and
disguises them and in turning upon its mobile
cusp, causes them to return’ (378).
Nietzsche's eternal return
serves as a general model of the production of
apparent repetition. As above, repetition seems
external again, or confined to the first
occurrence, seen as a ‘once and for all’, or
repeated in cycles—all this 'depends entirely upon
the reflection of an observer', making judgements
about resemblances through analogies managing
empirical circumstances (367). These
observations are directed at empirical objects,
but these are themselves 'simulacra' or signs of
some deeper processes. The eternal return lets us
see that,although again it looks as if it
presupposes resemblance and identity. Is it
not the One that returns? (asks Deleuze). Nietzsche
suggests that would be impossible because the One
cannot leave itself or lose its identity in the
first place [definitional quibbling?]. It is the
different that returns not the similar, and all
other forms have been destroyed which attempt to
limit it, including conventional systems of
representation.
Any similarities are only effects, they are
‘”simulated”: they are the products of systems
which relate different to different by means of
difference' (154), they are fictions, but this is
a necessary illusion. Apparently,
the eternal return maintains these illusions 'in
order to rejoice in [them]’ (154). : ‘The negative,
the similar and the analogous are repetitions, but
they do not return, forever driven away by the
wheel of eternal return’ (370). However, there are
additional repetitions. In pure time
each determination or stage is already repetition
in itself. The
perspectives of the external observer are no
longer relevant. However,
it is clear that there must be a third time which
produces these analogous relations, among other
possibilities. There is no
conventional representation in the eternal return,
so difference is liberated, ironically, by a
repetition in the eternal return. Representation
is needed only once, in the early stages, and it
is not reproduced in the eternal return. Yet there
is a unity of the play of difference, or
similarity between the series when they resonate
and return. The
similar, repetition and the identical in the
eternal return are products of difference. I am not sure if
Deleuze feels himself vindicated, or if he is out
to vindicate Nietzsche.
There is something that might
appear as a kind of preliminary ethics or even
politics. Repetition
points towards the future, escaping reminiscence
and habitus.
‘Forgetting becomes a positive power’ (9),
which is important since the obsessional man of
bad conscience or the paranoid man of ressentiment
can never forget anything. We also find a
useful critique of Hegelian
dialectic which also preserves all the past
moments in some ‘gigantic Memory’ (64). By
contrast, in stressing difference (not negation)
extremes represents difference
itself, ‘the univocity of the different… The
eternal formlessness of the eternal return
itself’. Everything
which can be denied is denied, we must pursue an
active forgetting, and that includes weak
affirmations resulting only from negatives. Of
course, the 'we' here does not refer to the
normal notion of a human subject. Deleuze tells
us that Nietzsche suggested that beneath
the I and the Self is an abyss. This
would mean that it is the I and the Self which
become abstract universals, and the terms must
be replaced by a proper understanding of
individuation, to produce more fluid
conceptions.
We need to go back to the pre-individual
singularities.
The nearest image is the ‘fractured I and
the dissolved Self’ (322). The
two are correlated. Ideas,
as problems, ‘swarm around the edges of the
fracture’, appearing as multiplicities, and
expressing themselves as individuating factors
producing ‘the universal concrete individuality
of the thinker or the system of the dissolved
Self’ (322)
Finally, Nietzsche offers a model for the ideal
philosopher to pursue. Any idiot can reproduce
similarities through 'recognising' them in every
new event, and the community will reward you if
you do: Deleuze tells us that Nietzsche
insisted that the latter was not what he meant
by the will to power, and derided Kant and Hegel
as ‘”philosophical
labourers”’ because they did not want to break
with recognition (172). philosophy
actually requires an individual ‘full of ill
will who
does not manage to think, either naturally or
conceptually’ (166), someone who sees subjective
presuppositions as prejudices, refusing to go
along with appearing as a wise idiot, not
partaking in current culture. ‘Such
a one is the Untimely, neither temporal nor
eternal’ (166). This echoes Nietzsche's rather
self-pitying view of himself, of course,
especially in Zarathustra,
and the idea is pursued in Nietzsche's work on education.
In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze
tells us that cruelties and
violence are necessary, Nietzsche said,
precisely in order to train “a nation of
‘thinkers’” or to “provide a training for the
mind”’ (205).
The second set, in Logic of Sense
People like Nietzsche are still
misunderstood as an advocate of transcendence—but
he only used the term the death of god to explain
the bad faith and ressentiment which emerged (71).
Transcendentalism involves a false choice
between chaos, ‘an abyss’ without differences and
without properties’, and ‘a supremely individuated
Being and intensely personalized Form’ (106). It
follows that such a being would have to possess
all the characteristics of reality within itself. The
being can be either god or man. In both options
‘we are faced with the alternative between
undifferentiated groundlessness and imprisoned
singularities’ (106). Nietzsche came
close to discovering a world of pre-individual
singularities, driven by a free energy, ‘the will
to power’ (107).
‘Being…
leaps from one singularity to another,
casting always the dice belonging to the same
cast, always fragmented and formed again in each
throw’ (107 [Deleuze’s own position?]. For
Nietzsche, this is the philosophy of the ‘pure
unformed’, and ‘the subject is this free,
anonymous, and nomadic singularity which traverses
men as well as plants and animals independently of
the matter of their individuation and the forms of
their personality.
“Overman” means nothing other than this—the
superior type of everything that is’ (107). However,
Nietzsche also returned to explore the ‘bottomless
abyss’ (108).
We see here (and in Difference and Repetition),
Deleuze's interest in this dice-throw metaphor.
Obviously, this does justice to the elements of
chance and contingency in the unfolding of Being
(although Nietzsche was entirely [?]
anthropomorphic here, seeing the dice throw as the
mechanism determing the fate of free individuals,
and admiring the acceptance of chance among the
strong). Deleuze also sees it as extending the
affirmative nature of the eternal return since (in
a mere sentence or two in Zarathustra) since the
dice throw has itself to be affirmed,not just the
results of one particular throw. This is the
meaning of the double throw metaphor once in
Heaven and once on earth. It links to the figure
of Dionysus, enjoying the results of chance,
whatever they may be. Incidentally, the whole
thing about Dionysus becomes clear only if you
have read Nietzsche on Greek
tragedy, in my view -- it's also the only
bit of Nietzsche I enjoyed!
The common image of a philosopher is the platonic
one, where the philosopher ascends above reality
to get to the world of ideas. Nietzsche
advocated going in the opposite direction,
penetrating beneath biographies to get to the
workings of life itself. (127) .Difference here is
a topological term relating to distance on
surfaces rather than depths. It is not just a
matter of suggesting ‘some unknown identity of
contraries (as in commonplace in spiritualist and
dolorist philosophy)’ (173). An
example is Nietzsche arguing that health and
sickness can both inform each other, act as points
of view, remembering that ‘things, beings, are
themselves points of view’ (173). [And
then there is a very curious bit about how
Nietzsche perished—ostensibly from sickness and
death, but from a 'quasi cause' [Deleuze waffle to
avoid causality] ‘which represents the state
of organization or disorganization of the
incorporeal surface’, something to do with his
entire oeuvre and style [his {absurd}
'physiological determinism?] . ‘We see
no other way of raising the question of relations
between an oeuvre and illness except by means of
this double causality’ (108)
Modernity shows the power of the simulacrum (so we
are on familiar ground here) . Nietzsche
attempted to critique it by extracting from it
‘the untimely, which pertains to modernity, but
which must also be turned against it’ (265). It
involves going back to the past, in this case
Platonism, to reverse it; seeing current simulacra
as critiques of modernity [sorting out the
artificial?]; seeing the future as dominated by
the phantasm of the eternal return [which is at
least a belief in the future]. The
simulacrum opposes itself to mere artificiality,
copies of copies, and preserves at least the
constructive aspects of chaos [which include ‘the
destruction of Platonism’ (266)].
Turning to the essays, first
the two in Essays:
Critical and Clinical (1997)
The first one compares Nietzsche's take on
Christinaity with that of DH Lawrence ( a major
author for Mrs Deleuze who teanslated him into
French). Most of it is about Lawrence on the
Apocalypse, and it's rather clever in suggesting
that the Apocalypse is the proletarian vengeful
take on the second coming of Christ, where the
masses will triumph over the Roman Empire Deleuze
notes the stress on the important pagan symbolism
in the Apocalypse, another device to make the
terms graspable by the masses. By contrast,
Nietzsche focuses on the work of St Paul in
modifying Christianity into a universal religion,
making it abstract and cementing the links with
ressentiment and the bad conscience. Lawrence is
the major focus though.
The second essay deals with the
poem about the myth of Ariadne, which we are
told elsewhere is crucial although this is never
spelled out very well. In the book, Deleuze even
uses the stuff on Ariadne to reject the charges of
misogyny against Nietzsche, but her main role is
to complement, support and affirm Dionysus ( the
second affirmation -- since Dionysus is himself
affirmative). Ariadne was first connected to
Theseus,who can be compared to the Higher Man in Zarathustra, the
man of modernity, overcoming nature, but seeing it
in heroic terms, as a massive burden to be borne.
Theseus is not a happy playful person, and is even
adversely compared (by Deleuze) to the playful
bull which he subdues in the labyrinth. Ariadne is
abandoned by Theseus, is mystified, self-doubting
and lamenting, but is transformed by her
relationship with Dionysus into a support for the
playful. Deleuze says we can see this in the
actual (bloody awful) poem: again he is pretty
selective though and focuses mostly on the last
verse, where Ariadne meets Dionysus. Before that
we have lots of lines of lament, turning on
perceived injury from an unknown and spiteful god,
who nevertheless is missed by Ariadne when he
leaves her. Within the 5 lines of thatthat
selected last verse, Deleuze goes further, picking
out a remark in one line about Ariadne's
ears,which he rends as Dionysus saying they are
small, round and labyrinthine. In the book,
Deleuze tells us that Nietzsche was proud of his
own small ears which he thought women found
attractive, but there is also an implicit
comparison with the large and long ears of the
ass, the beast of burden, a reference to Theseus
and the higher man. Ears are a labyrinth, Dionysus
is a labyrinth, life itself is a labyrinth, but
this is not something to be feared and overcome,
domesticated by a modernist device -- Ariadne's
thread
Smith's very useful Introduction to the Essays
says Deleuze saw Nietzsche as an exemplary
diagnostician (of nihilism) by ‘isolating its
symptoms (ressentiment, the bad conscience, the
ascetic ideal), by tracing its aetiology to a
certain relation of active and reactive forces
(the genealogical method), and by setting forth
both a prognosis (nihilism defeated by itself),
and a treatment (the revaluation of values)’
(xix), and that this is the basis for Deleuze's
own 'clinical', method in this collection and
elsewhere. Deleuze's discussion
of this own use of the 'method of dramatization'
is also explained in the book on Nietzsche -- to
avoid charges of anthropocentrism, Deleuze says
Nietzsche makes the clash of forces into a play of
human wills.
These
theme is spelled out in more detail in the book
on Nietzsche, but it's also a controversial
reading. Deleuze tells us explicitly that
Nietzsche denies that's the eternal return will
be a repetition of the similar or identical, but
it is clear that in one of the areas where
Nietzsche discusses the term, in Zarathustra, he
says exactly the opposite. Nietzsche also
discusses the eternal return in several other
places, with slight modifications, suggesting,
for example, in Will to Power, that if the
strong can come back to their former dominance,
they will be able to insist that their values
persist in the eternal return, but this is still
rather hypothetical.This leaves still
owes with quite a bit of work to do, and I have
added in my notes on the book, some comments about
how he does this. The first stage is, as
we've seen, to read what Nietzsche actually said
in zarathustra to mean the exact opposite of what
might be seen as normal reading. This is
part of the 'symptomatic reading' strategy that
Dedleuze pursues on encountering a number of
controversial pieces in Nietzsche. Another
example arises with discussing the will to power,
which Deleuze assures us does not mean the coming
to power of a particular group, although the
discussion of the role of the strong seems to
suggest quite the opposite. The strong have
a very important role in preventing decadence, in
reconnecting with human projects that have been
subverted by ressentiment and bad conscience: they
might even have a role in selecting the best
element saw the eternal return, as we saw.
There is it also admiration for particularly
strong dominant individuals, especially
Napoleon. Finally, Nietzsche does
indeed excuse if not glorify war, part of the
inevitable cruelty of the strong, almost a leisure
pursuit for them. Deleuze tries to gloss
this by ignoring it, but also arguing that it is
'warlike play' that Nietzsche is advocating, which
looks a bit like a possible endorsement for male
invasion games, or possibly return to chivalric
jousting.
Deleuze then attempts a reconstruction of
Nietzsche's context, one of those occasional
interludes where philosophers get quite close to
the sociology of knowledge, but then back rapidly
away. Deleuze explains that the eternal
return has to be properly cyclic and selective,
because Nietzsche wanted to oppose the particular
models that were dominant in the science of his
day, those relating to a clockwork universe.
Those notions predicted eternal equilibrium,
evolution... One of the objections that
Nietzsche had was that these sciences worked with
excessive metrication and quantification.
There is quite a heavy handed section in the book
where this rather familiar argument is made in
terms of the qualities of forces which are not
just reducible to the quantitative. Since
Nietzsche opposed these conceptions, Deleuze wants
to argue that his notion of the eternal return
must also oppose them, and that therefore
qualitative change is being predicted, as the only
available alternative at the time. I have
suggested that is possible to detect in this
argument and number of flaws, like smuggling in
the conclusion in the definition. In
particular, in this specific case, there is no
real discussion of how the qualitative can indeed
be reduced to the quantitative, and how positive
[sic] benefits can ensue.
We can see some of these operational and
beneficial procedures in Nietzsche's own work, and
the sections where Deleuze is trying to complement
Nietzsche as a systematic thinker, especially with
the development of typologies like those of
different sorts of 'man'(ugliest man, last man,
higher man and so on). For sociologists,
more familiar with Weberian ideal types,
Nietzsche's types are sadly lacking in terms of
their 'adequacy': there's no way of using them to
do actual research or indeed to test them.
It would involve a long and laborious study of the
bizarre writings of Nietzsche, but my guess would
be that there are also incoherences in the way in
which he uses these types, but I'm not the one to
test out this suggestion with close reading.
Perhaps the most dubious exercise an apology
follows the compliments on these typologies.
Deleuze tells us that they depend on a topology,
some attempt to rank factors such as forces, to
assign them some moral force. This brings
back morals into philosophy, Deleuze tells us
early in the book, meaning that they are really
inseparable from more abstract exercises like the
development of typology. No doubt this is
true, but Deleuze never really goes on to explain
what Nietzsche's values actually are and offers a
sanitized and abstracted view of them. Thus
the paeans of praise to the strong, to their
carefree stance towards people's lives and their
own, their pleasure in cruelty and suffering,
their refusal to be constrained by pity, which is
condemned as weakness throughout, the scorn
directed at socialism or equality including the
equality of women, and the dark suspicions leveled
against ethnic groups such as the Jews, and, to be
evenhanded, the Germans of the period. All
these are rendered as abstract admiration for the
creative and active forces in human life.
The times, this is clearly a celebration of male
heroics—adventure, risk taking, laughing at fate,
staking everything on the role of the dice and so
on.
The same goes for the notorious examples which
have attracted a great deal of commentary already
in Nietzsche. The anti Semitism, for example
is 'balanced'by citing Nietzsche's criticisms of
antiSemites, including some of his
correspondents. I've already argued in my
notes on Nietzsche, that this is rather flimsy
defence, because it's perfectly possible to admire
individual Jews, and to detest individual
antiSemites while holding a more general anti
Semitism. If we're looking for selective
reading, incidentally, even Kaufmann finds an
example of pretty explicit anti Semitism in
Nietzsche's work but obviously much is going to
depend on how we read many of the comments.
The Jews are admired for completing their mission
in developing Christianity as a more universal
form, for example, but then Nietzsche detests
Christianity as the triumph of the weak and the
resentful. It is true that the priestly
type, are represented initially by Jewish priests
has a positive role, but mostly, priests collude
in developing a system that binds the weak, the
bad conscience. As for being anti female, examples
proliferate in the actual Nietzsche, and again
apologists tried to argue that Nietzsche was
really saying that women would not be happy if
they simply tried to copy male roles.
However this is also saying that they should stay
in their appointed place. Nietzsche had no
doubt about where that was, that by nature they
were fitted to be the support of man, the domestic
partner of man, or the erotic object of man, at
least in the version of courtly love.
Suggesting that women should receive full equality
was a clear sign of decadence, as was any kind of
equality. No doubt again, at Nietzsche
admired particular women, but then that is a
different proposition from advancing the cause of
women in general. The issue of race is also
apparent, of course, with the same sort of
ambivalence. In Genealogy, Nietzsche clearly
admires the 'Aryans', the mythological 'blond
beasts', and Kaufmann takes pains to explain that
these admirable creatures on not to be identified
with the current German 'race'. Indeed,
Nietzsche tends to dismiss current Germans as
vulgar and drunken but then, HItler didn't like
actual Germans much).
Other problems include Nietzsche's
anthropomorphism. The whole thing is about
culture, history and human politics, with someone
discussed notion of 'nature'or a bizarre
'physiology' as the only material forces.
Anthopomorphic? Feeblexcuses. Egocentgric --
discussed in Essays -- typically back to front
What hefets -- activity (butno id of active
forces), politics agin consv trends but mythical
Dionysian polcs and eternal return as post-capist
utopia. HGardlynmentioned MArx escept via GI and
Stirner. Wilful to choose NIetzsche instead!
|
|