Notes on: Deleuze, G. (2006) [1962]. Nietzsche
and Philosophy. Trans. Hugh
Tomlinson. London: Bloomsbury publishing PLC
Dave Harris
[I was prompted to go back and reread some
Nietzsche before considering this book by Deleuze
and I made some notes.
I was already aware that Deleuze's reading of
Nietzsche was quite different from the one with
which I had grown up, and I wanted to see how
Deleuze had managed to transform Nietzsche into
such a positive figure. I am no scholar of
Nietzsche, but it was possible to see this book as
a kind of redemptive essay, sympathetically
reading Nietzsche in order to rescue him from the
usual charges of elitism, patriarchy, and
incipient Nazism, largely by ignoring those bits
as irrelevant. I have only been able to spot
one or two examples of this redemptive
reading. One occurs with a discussion of one
of Deleuze's favourite concepts, the eternal
return. I was already aware after reading Difference and
Repetition that Deleuze sees the
eternal return as a kind of dynamic return of a
system for generating possibilities, or, in one of
the metaphors he uses a lot as a return of the
whole game of dice, not a repetition of one result
of the cast of the dice. The argument is
made in two essays {notes here and here}.
Imagine my surprise when on reading one of the
sources of this discussion in Nietzsche, his very
peculiar book Zarathustra,
there seems to be a clear statement that the
eternal return does produce an identical reality,
not even a similar one. Compare this with
what Deleuze says about Zarathustra in the
first chapter below -- the opposite.
Not even the combined resources of the Facebook
discussion group on Deleuze and Guattari could
resolve this apparent contradiction: one or two
thought it was an example of what used to be known
in the trade as a 'symptomatic reading', where
some deeper meaning is identified despite the
specific forms of the words. In this way,
Deleuze seems to be arguing that Nietzsche really
meant to say the opposite of what he actually
said, which gives you quite a licence for
interpretation!
The actual argument, in Chapter 2,seems to be
first that the clockwork science of its day could
not deal with qualitative differences, but focused
on models featuring quantitative ones, and
qualitative changes in the eternal return could
not be dealt with by scientific models of the day
which installed mechanical reproduction,
equilibrium, or entropy. One obvious conclusion
would be, therefore, that the eternal return is a
lot of non-scientific bullshit of little value. Of
course, Nietzsche and Deleuze much prefer the
other option -- that science is limited in its
ability to grasp philosophical concepts and thus
we should disqualify it from the debate, the
'wise' resort of all sorts of homeopaths,
spiritualists, astrologers, faith healers and
snake-oil salesmen. What superior argument can
philosophy offer for its conception instead? A
combination of philosophical and political
implications and commitments and preferences as
below. Sometimes these are even pseduo-scientific
as in 'since there has been infinite time, and the
universe is not in a state of stability yet,
there can be no long-term trend to equilibrium,
because if there were, we would have reached it by
now'. You don't have to be too critical to spot
the terms and conditions smuggled in there --
'infinite time', 'no equilibrium', the mutual
support of 'infinite time' and 'not yet' -- and so
on.
One or two little tropes like this are apparent as
we shall see as we go along. As usual, they
are deployed in the service of the peculiar
arguments of philosophers which often take the
form of arguing that A must really be seen as B
because if we accept the consequences of literally
reading A as A, this will cause some embarrassment
elsewhere in the text, either in the stirring
conclusions we wish to draw, or in having to
accept that an earlier discussion omitted a
possibility. I suppose it is a form of
abduction. One similar classic example is that if
the eternal return produced exactly the same
world, there would be no becoming, which takes for
granted that there is becoming, which must be
qualitative: so the argument is that if there are
no qualitative changes, we would not be able to
argue that there are qualitative changes, and that
this would be sad; since we do not wish to be sad,
it follows that the eternal return cannot produce
the same world.]
Preface to the English translation
Deleuze begins by confronting head on with the
argument that Nietzsche was a protofascist, and
suggests instead we can see his thought as a kind
of 'over violent poetry, made up of capricious
aphorisms and pathological fragments'(viii).
He says that English readers understand Nietzsche
least because they are not aware of the underlying
struggles with French rationalism and German
dialectics. As a results, in England,
Nietzsche was only admired as a stylist
[really?]. He is a great philosopher and has
had considerable influence. There are two
main arguments. First we have to see the
importance of forces and the way in which they
produce events that must be read as signs or
symptoms of forces, as a 'general semeiology'
(ix). There are active and reactive forces
in different combinations. Language
represents a propositional form of symptoms,
indicating an underlying mode of existence [yet
neither Nietzsche and nor Deleuze see any mileage
in sociological investigation of these
links. In the case of Nietzsche, it seems to
be approached through some kind of wacky
'physiology']. The reactive forces are ressentiment
and bad conscience, both of which enslave
human beings, and their masters. We also
find the first defence of Nietzsche's antisemitism
-- it is really a critique of 'the original
priestly type'. The second argument turns on
power and its connections with ethics and
ontology. Nietzsche's will to power is not
just a matter of political agents seeking power,
but is a product of the state of forces at work
and represents the dynamic qualities of
activities. Rather than individual wills
wanting power, it is more a matter of 'the one
that wants in the will' (x) [really a kind of weak
naturalism for me]. It is really a search
for forms of power, especially Dionysian
forms.
The eternal return has also been
misunderstood. It is not the return of the
identical or the same. In Zarathustra,
there are two intervening processes, first willing
or thought which constitute ethical interventions
[by the ruling order that realises its
responsibilities to kill the weak?], so that we
can will only those things that we would be
willing to live all over again; second, being
itself is understood as becoming, and only that
that is capable of becoming is 'fit to
return'. It has to be something active and
affirmative, not anything negative or
reactive, which both prevent becoming. The
eternal return is therefore 'a transmutation',
something active and affirmative [but the context
always suggests activity to press on with human
adventure and heroism, and being affirmative about
your strong and aggressive nature?]. This
book is all about Nietzsche on becoming.
However, it is difficult to read the kind of
emotional dispositions in the work, which
Nietzsche has always maintained are connected to
concepts. We have to place ourselves in
Nietzsche's 'atmosphere' to avoid
misunderstandings like the ones above, this time
including seeing the Overman in terms of a master
race. Nietzsche was aware that he would
often be misunderstood, as in his discussion of
the ape or buffoon in Zarathustra.
Nietzsche is a nihilist in one sense, in making us
aware of the dangers of reactive forces and the
negative, and transmutation or becoming was
deliberately established to overcome
nihilism. The Overman was not a superhuman
being, but the focal point to oppose the reactive
forces, pointing to the future. Nihilist
forces could be overcome.
We can see the difficulty of the context in the
use of the aphorism, 'which only makes sense in
relation to the state of forces that it expresses,
and which changes sense... according to the
new forces which it is 'capable'... of attracting'
(xii). We must change our image of
thought. It is not concerned with truth and
falsity, but interpretation and evaluation,
focused on forces and power. It is deeply
connected to movement, with different speeds and
slowness, and this connects thoughts to the arts
in particular. Zarathustra is really an
opera, designed to 'directly express thought as
experience and movement'. His admiration for
fascist figures should really be seen as an
example of a theatre director showing how the
Overman should be played. Thinking and
creating is what emerges overall, thinking as
casting the dice.
Chapter one. The Tragic
Genealogy. This is N
reintroducing sense and value back into
philosophy, in the form of a critique. Kant
neglected values, and as a result, conventional
values have been reasserted, even in
phenomenology. However we need thorough
critique focused on the notion of value and
evaluation. Values underpin all
appraisals. The core of evaluation is
uncovering differences in corresponding values,
seen as differences in 'ways of being, modes of
existence of those who judge and evaluate' (2)
[before sociology, of course]. The key
differences, between 'high and low, noble and
base' [Bourdieu would have a field day here]
represent different elements in ways of being.
Being critical means referring everything back to
values and to the origin of values. Too much
philosophy has either ignored values, as in the
'"high" idea of foundation', simply listed
existing values, or adopted conventional
values. Some have derived values from simple
facts, like utilitarianism or scholasticism,
assuming some notion of 'the valuable for
all'. Instead we must do genealogy, focusing
on different elements rather than universal
ones. There are no absolute values or
universal ones. Values are divided in their
very origin. Focusing on this difference is
something active not reactive, nothing to do with
ressentiment or revenge. The latter is for
'apes'. Critique is more active and
affirmative, down to the 'natural aggression of a
way of being' (3). It is something noble of
course, designed to bring about the values of the
future.
Sense. The sense of something is
provided once we know the forces at work in it,
once we treat phenomena as signs or
symptoms. Philosophy becomes symptomatology
or semeiology [sic -- about things as well as
words]. The distinction between phenomena
and sense replaces the old idea of appearance and
essence, or the scientific notion of cause and
effect . Force involves the domination 'of
the quantity of reality' and even perception is
the expression of such forces. A succession
of forces can take possession of a thing, and can
coexist, which changes the sense of the phenomenon
or object, and this is the proper topic of
history, especially the development of '"mutually
independent processes of subduing"'.
Interpretation and subjugation are the same thing.
Nietzsche is a pluralist and in this sense an
empiricist [we cannot assume things simply express
single essences but must investigate them] .
We see this in the rejection of the notion of a
single dominant god. Even the death of god
is plural, having multiple sense, just like every
other 'phenomenon, word or thought' (4).
Hegel saw pluralism as naive, but for N it is a
great achievement, requiring mature concepts,
estimation of forces and interrelations.
Essences remain, but as something more variable,
and related to the thing and those characteristics
which persist despite the forces attempting to
subdue it: an affinity between force and things
produces essence.
Forces appropriate objects indirectly first,
imitating matter initially, in order to
survive. This explains the initial
similarity between the philosopher and earlier
variants such as ascetics and religious people
[this is the site of another objection to
Deleuze's interpretation of Nietzsche for
me. Nearly all Nietzsche's examples relate
to the human sphere, but Deleuze seems to want to
generalize to the non human as well, a kind of
reverse anthropocentrism]. It explains why
the religious forces were able to take hold at
particular times. At the same time, it is
absurd to remain with this image, and philosophy
must eventually come out from behind its mask and
acquire a new sense. This indirect
interpretation is actually frequently necessary,
because we do not perceive original differences
very easily - we need a friend, some third person
who can guide us but then be overcome [reminds me
of the role of the philosopher's apprentice in Future of Educational
Organisations]. Only when
philosophy has thrown off its mask can we grasp
its genealogy, which can be generalized [almost
like the owl of Minerva flying only at
dusk]. Reservations the common people often
have about philosophers are well grounded if they
go on to suggest dangerous ideas [male heroicism].
The philosophy of the Will. Objects
themselves are forces, or express forces [same
thing for Deleuze?], and all objects are
signs. The forces are plural, and are
related to each other but at different
distances. It would be wrong to see matter
alone as plural and interrelated, and this is why
Nietzsche opposes the idea of 'atomism' [assuming
fundamental primitive objects?]. Simple
atoms would have no concept of relation, because
the concept would not contain the necessary
differences. The will and the will to power
is an element of force fully embracing difference,
and is often exercised on another will: the big
split is between wills that command and wills that
obey. Only will can dominate or obey.
Schopenhauer saw the will as something essentially
unitary, based on some common links between those
who command and those who obey. He also saw
the need to constrain the will and suppress it in
order to develop morality, to become
ascetic. Nietzsche has to reject this
unity as a mystification [so there is no general
will then {sic}, only the wills of groups like the
elite and the mass? This would be too sociological
for Deleuze?].
The critique of atomism turns on psychic objects
such as soul or ego. These make more sense
in terms of discussing command and obedience, and
egoism can help us to throw off
disinterestedness. However, the will is not
just egoism and again we have to look at
origins. The origin lies in hierarchy again,
an internal difference between dominant and
dominated. This difference is central to the
genealogy. [So hierarchy is just an example of the
universal process of difference for Deleuze?
Instead of a narrow and racist elitism, Nietzsche
is really offering us general philosophy but
behind his own back?]
Against the Dialect [and the chance to take
on some unspecified critics and rehearse Deleuze's
own critiques in Difference
and Repetition]. For Nietzsche,
all sorts of plural relations are possible between
forces, not just dialectical ones. The
Overman replaces the dialectical concept of man,
and transvaluation replaces dialectical
appropriation and alienation. The whole
approach is profoundly opposed to Hegel.
When forces are related, for example difference is
affirmed and even enjoyed. Difference
emerges from activity not essence, often from 'the
aggression of an affirmation'(8). This
aggression is inherent in activity itself [again
an apologetic generalization,combining
philosophical activity with actual attempts to
grind the faces of the poor and kill those who
object]. Hegelian negatives by contrast look
feeble and artificial [yes --but what about Marx's
ones?]
There is an empirical kind of enquiry involved,
when Nietzsche asks what does the will actually
want: the answer is 'to affirm its
difference'. [Again there are human
examples], the pleasure of thinking that we are
different. This is to be seen as affirmative
and 'constitutive of existence' (9). It is
positive because it 'denies all that it is
not'. This positivity is the basis of noble
morality, while slave morality attempts to deny
any difference or any alternative. Slave
denials are the root of the negative elements of
the dialectic [ridiculous speculative
determinism], and lead to the desire for revenge
and ressentiment as impoverished versions of
affirmation. There is no dialectic between
master and slave: this is a form of slave
thinking. There may be opposed notions of
representation of power or superiority, struggles
over recognition, the desire to represent power,
but this is not the same as the will to power, but
only how it looks to slaves and those with
ressentiment [I suppose the best example these
days would be the ludicrous symbolic struggles
over 'respect'?]. Slaves cannot conceive of
power except in this symbolic way, as the stake in
the competition, and this actually reinforces
established values. The slave wins in Hegel
because the power of the master is misunderstood,
and already implies the struggle of slaves to
become successful and recognized.
The Problem of Tragedy. Nietzsche on
the tragic has been misunderstood by using
dialectic, but the domestication of the tragic is
actually accomplished by Socratic rationalism and
dialectic, and, more recently, by turning it into
a display of spectacular emotions [I think this is
really interesting discussion, and I have notes here]. We
should not see the tragic as linked dialectically
to life [as is common, apparently].
Nietzsche's first attempts, still influenced by
Schopenhauer, might still have borrowed from Hegel
with its emphasis on contradiction and resolution
in tragedy, but there are other
contradictions. These include the
contradiction between primitive unity and
individuation, between life and suffering, with
suffering needing to be redeemed: here, Nietzsche
is still influenced by Christian notions of
redemption and reconciliation. However, the
contradiction is then rendered in terms of the
struggle between Dionysus and Apollo, with Apollo
representing the value of beautiful
appearances, glimpses of eternity, and the
dream as redemptive, something individuated
[rendered at the individual level, available to
individuals], while Dionysus offers a different
resolution by pointing to the underlying
reality. Tragedy does unite these two
antitheses, and reconciles them, although it is
dominated by Dionysus, who is the only proper
tragic subject. Apollo helps represent the
tragic in drama, but the dionysian chorus always
offers something deeper and more primal beneath
apollonian forms.
N's Evolution. Tragedy is some
original contradiction which finds solution and
expression, and this theme runs through modern
tragic culture as well. In the end, wisdom
prevails over anything more empirical or
scientific, something more comprehensive.
Despite the dialectical elements, however,
Dionysus appears as something affirmative who does
not just resolve pain, but affirms it as
necessary, even pleasurable. Dionysus also
transforms himself or grows, rather than simply
appearing as the individuation of the
primal. There is even an anticipation of the
eternal return in the myth, when Dionysus is
reborn, although the argument is directed against
individuation. Nietzsche is still influenced
by Schopenhauer and Wagner and still sees the goal
as the resolution of suffering, but at the price
of transcending normal individuation.
Nietzsche himself revised his approach later and
stressed the novel elements—the affirmative nature
of Dionysus, the affirmation of life itself rather
than any higher resolution, and the discovery of
the real opposition between Dionysus and Socrates
with his instinctive criticism and his stress on
rational consciousness as creative, his judgement
of life against rational ideas. The real
opposition is no longer between Dionysus and
Apollo, and even Socrates is still too close to
Greek thought to become a proper 'theoretical
man'. The Dionysus figure is used not in
contrast to Apollo but as a complement to Ariadne,
since 'a woman, or fiancée, is necessary
where affirming is concerned' (13), and the real
opposition to Dionysus is now seen as the
crucified god, Christianity, something negative
and ascetic.
Dionysus and Christ. There are many
similarities in terms of martyrdom and passion,
but the difference is whether life is to be
affirmed or suffering, with the latter therefore
requiring redemption. The Christian view has
led to the bad conscience, the internal torments
of guilt and pain, and a nihilist stance towards
life. Christians appear to praise love, but
it is a cruel love. The relation with judaic
thought is not a simple dialectical one, because
there are continuities, and continuites between
love and hate—both examples show the limits of the
dialectic and the way in which it selects elements
to be related 'in an entirely fictitious
manner'. Thus Jewish hatred triumphs in
Christian love. All this is quite different
from Dionysus, where pain is resolved by a joyful
recognition of the unity of life, requiring no
external justification. The two approaches
can then be contrasted point for point, the
ascetic versus the affirmative, the life force
versus the need for a saviour. This is what
is Zarathustra is aiming at, something more than
just redemption, transvaluation, the reemergence
of Dionysus. A fundamental opposition to
dialectic is clearly implied.
The Essence of the Tragic. Dionysian
tragedy offers us 'multiple and pluralist
affirmation', (16) but how can we affirm
everything, even that which produces
disgust? We need of course to interpret and
transform such things first, so we can affirm it
in a special way. It's not a matter of
regaining lost unity, but rather heading for
multiplicity, 'affirmation as such'. The
tragic is a particular aesthetic form of joy,
arousing only fear and pity in the moralist or
scholastic, and requiring a new kind of 'artistic
listener' [detached and financially secure members
of an elite]. Multiple affirmation is the
key, and with it, even the tragic hero can be
joyful. Nietzsche was to go on to reject
this early argument as still excessively
Christian, just as Wagner was to be rebuked for
declining into emotionalism. Tragedy is to
be undergone by heroes who remain 'joyful,
graceful, dancing and gambling' (17). This
is seen better in the later celebration of Ariadne
who appears as 'the bursting constellation of a
famous dice throw' (17). Dialectic offers an
over theoretical account of the tragic vision,
still informed by Christianity in the case of
Hegel.
Christian theology asks the right question about
the meaning of existence, but Nietzsche insists
that this requires much more interpretation and
evaluation, to aim at the notion of the just
existence, not something which can be seen as a
fault requiring divine rectification. This
is the bad conscience, the unhappy consciousness,
that affected even Schopenhauer despite his
atheism [apparently, Schopenhauer could see no
point in existence having rejected god, so he
compromised] .The 'truly tragic way' [assuming
this is 'good'] is to see all existence as
justified and affirmative including suffering.
The Problem of Existence. This
has been long discussed, usually in terms of the
injustice of existence and of divine justification
for it. For the Greeks, the Titans helped
provide a first sense [Prometheus necessarily
committed crime and incurred divine judgement and
punishment]. [Anaximander's specific account
is discussed on page 19]. Deleuze notes that
the myth is hostile to any sort of becoming, which
is seen only as some original fall from
grace. At least this is not a Christian
interpretation, though,so it does not lead to bad
conscience and guilt. Nietzsche sees the
notion of Christian original sin as '"preeminently
feminine"', but this is 'not Nietzschean
misogyny', because the powers attributed to
Ariadne are seen as inseparable to Dionysus
[hmmm! Looks like the familiar dualism of
the idealized asexual good and the suspected,
sexualised and feared bad woman here].
Nietzsche thinks that we should not be appealing
to women, who make us feel guilty in the guise of
mothers and sisters [there is a particular
diatribe in Will to Power, apparently],
who peddle ressentiment. It is this notion
of revenge that haunts modern philosophy and
moralism, one of the 'fundamental categories of
Semitic and Christian thought'(20).
Nietzsche wants to free us from this abiding sense
of responsibility, make ourselves independent of
praise and blame: 'Irresponsibility—Nietzsche's
most noble and beautiful secret' [and obviously
self-justifying]
Christian nihilism is more developed than Greek
versions, since they saw the gods themselves as
responsible for the faults in existence, a result
of divine folly, not the sins of men.
However, this is developed, following the
introduction of a sexual connotation, where Eve is
responsible, and where human beings crucify their
god. Even so, the issue is whether existence
is blameworthy in itself, whatever caused these
faults. Dionysus offers a radical innocence,
'the innocence of plurality, the innocence of
becoming and all that is'(21)
Existence and Innocence. It is
'deplorable' to seek people responsible for
[natural] injustice. There is no one outside
the whole, indeed, '"there is no whole"' (21), no
unified universe but multiplicity, things affected
by different combinations of forces, and the focus
instead on what forces are able to do
affirmatively. Those who do not pursue these
investigations will only be controlled by another
will or force. Most of us prefer to
interpret the world in a way which corresponds to
the forces we possess, and to deny anything
else. We congratulate ourselves for the
former, and blame herself for the latter, so the
will is split, and some neutral subject is assumed
to possess free will to act or refrain. This
is a poor understanding of the forces at work, the
will which we can develop. We develop
negative interpretations, and one interpretation
tends to serve—the one that says existence has no
meaning. We are simply 'bad players' at this
game.
Heraclitus was the first to realize the importance
of play as something affirmative, to do with
becoming. There is only becoming, no being
as such. Thought must affirm becoming and
also see the becoming in being. There is no
other being, 'nothing beyond multiplicity'
(22). Multiplicity and becoming support each
other. Any single individual [people, but
also objects] is a form of unified multiplicity:
'unity is actually affirmed in
multiplicity'. There can be no negativity in
becoming. The notion of return is also
involved, seen initially as 'the being of that
which becomes... The being which is affirmed
in becoming' (23). This means the eternal
return is also something to be affirmed, 'as law
of becoming as justice and as being'[as usual, we
have definitions that support each other here
rather than logical implications]. There can
be no blame attached to existence.
The links between the many and the one, being and
becoming 'forms a game'. We need first to
affirm becoming and being as becoming, and then we
can introduce the third term 'the player, the
artist or the child'[seeing the gods as childlike
was a feature of Greek thought, apparently, and
even Dionysus has his divine toys]. As
players, we can temporarily abandon ourselves to
the game of life. The artist creates within
the rules of the game, sometimes addressing those
rules explicitly. The being of becoming also
plays the game itself, in aeon [this
rather mysterious form of intensive time operating
beneath objective time, also discussed in Difference and
Repetition]. The eternal return
is a moment of the game [again defined as the
being of becoming], and a return of the action of
the game back from that moment. Apparently,
Heraclitus used the notion of the game to mock
human hubris, to explain justice as the law of the
world in the form of play or innocence.
The Dicethrow. There are two moments:
the dice are thrown and then they fall back.
For Nietzsche, there are two tables for the throw,
the earth and the sky, where the dice fall back to
the sky, as in Zarathustra.
But the earth and sky are part of a single world,
midnight and midday in Zarathustra
[actual and virtual?]. Human players and
artists can also divert attention from birth to
sky, temporarily at least. The dicethrow
'affirms becoming and it affirms the being of
becoming' (24) [it maintains the importance of the
game itself and the actual results of each
turn]. We're not talking here about a series
of throws which will eventually produce the same
result as initially. A single dicethrow
reproduces itself, representing all the
possibilities [a very abstract and philosophical
way to put it -- you can't play dice if you do not
accept the rules or the random results]. One throw
affirms chance, but the result should be seen as
the affirmation of necessity, just as being is
necessary to becoming and and unity to
multiplicity [this notion of necessity is quite
useful then - presumably not so much divine
necessity as necessary reason, but based on
chance?]. Of course, chance will not always
produce a particular winning combination, double
six, which allows us to start all over again, but
[by way of compensation], the player can at least
affirm chance itself, as a counter to what might
be seen as iron necessity [never mind if you're in
poverty—better luck next time with your kids].
We can see the metaphor of the dicethrow as chaos,
and again there is an implicit affirmation and
innocence [only because Nietzsche admires the old
noble spirit that laughs at fate? I am sure it
pleased some of them to think of their fortunes as
being accumulated only because of lucky
chance]. It gives a higher purpose to the
actual, a chance to dance, to experience chance
[could be Giddens on the dubious universality of
'choice' in modernity] . Nietzsche wants to
call this necessity or destiny, affirmed of
chance, a way of celebrating the particular throw
of the dice, a particular 'fatal number which
reunites all the fragments of chance'(25).
Such affirmation of chance implies another
dicethrow [seems very similar to hope for a better
life following reincarnation --or posthumous
fame? I could have been a contender?
Better luck next time? Best of three? Not my
fault if I lose all my money?].
Most people are afraid to play, however, and find
it impossible to laugh at any adverse results like
real players. We selectively interpret the
results, approving the ones that we like and using
notions of causality and probabilities to explain
them. Causality and finality domesticate
chance. Probabilistic estimates of the
results of the throw prevent affirmation.
This sort of reason actually originates in
ressentiment and revenge. Probability will
not deliver, because there is no purpose in the
universe, and we can only play as well as we
can. If we do not affirm chance, we are not
celebrating the dicethrow nor encouraging it to
return. We need to break away from notions
of probability and finality, and think of events
in terms of a coupling of chance and destiny
rather than a probability distributed over several
throws, opt for a fatal combination, 'fatal and
loved, amor fati' (26). [Deleuze sees THIS
as some wonderful refutation of scientism?]
Consequences for the Eternal Return.
We have to distinguish between single throws of
the dice and those which 'fall back' and
reintroduce the notion of destiny. The
eternal return brings both moments back.
Another absurd quote from Zarathustra
implies that if we welcome chance and see it as an
expression of will, we can make it our
friend. It would be wrong to take the
particular 'fragments of chance' (26) as dominant,
as masters [especially if they disadvantage us],
and all the fragments have to be reunited and
affirmed. Nietzsche apparently [in Will
to Power] sees chaos as some underlying
necessity for purposeful activity, '"an irrational
necessity"', an attempt to unite the notion of
chaos and cycle, becoming and eternal
return. Chaos is not entirely constrained by
becoming, and chaos guarantees that becoming
cannot be judged against any other external
criterion [so all this follows from having to make
things consistent]. Becoming has a law in
itself, and as long as we affirm chance, there is
a compensation [because chance is at least better
than chaos?]. Chance does not finally
conquer chaos, however, but the two are linked in
a circular movement. This is Nietzsche's
departure from earlier conceptions of eternal
return: there is no subjugation of becoming [as in
the notion that the identical is what returns?].
Nietzsche's Symbolism. The dice throw
is multiple affirmation which challenges the
existing forms. It is sometimes rendered as
fire, transforming force. Human activity can
be seen as something less than combustion, more
like cooking [could be Levi-Strauss here on
cooking in the culinary triangle, mediating the
raw/natural], putting chance into the fire, which
is always there to reheat it. There is
always multiplicity in unity. There are
metaphors of dancing and dancing stars to
represent the game and chaos. Zarathustra
himself is a suitable figure for Nietzsche because
he introduces morality into metaphysics, and
denounces the mystification of other forms, but he
also sees the chaos and affirmation of chance in
fire and stars. The images of chaos, fire
and constellations are also found in the myth of
Dionysus, once interpreted, of course, in the
figure of Dionysus as game player. Nietzsche also
attempted to deal with the physical science of his
time, and 'dreamt of a fire machine completely
different from the steam engine' (28) [prat], but
preferred poetry and philosophy and dreams to
actual science.
Despite the interest in poems and aphorisms,
however, serious philosophy was the point.
An aphorism can be seen as a fragment, 'the form
of pluralist thought' (29) aimed at articulating a
sense of being, or action. It is not the
same as the maxim which tends to relate only to
human phenomena. Nietzsche was not
anthropomorphic [handy for Deleuze -- but that all
turns on the preference for the aphorism?].
The point is to evaluate and interpret, and both
the aphorism and the poem do this, but both need
to be themselves evaluated and interpreted.
Nietzsche in particular urged us to practice
exegesis on the aphorism from a pluralist
standpoint, going back to the differential
elements which produces sense and value [the
social hierarchy?] This element is always
implicit, waiting to be developed in philosophy
[that is interpreted in terms of Nietzsche's own
wacky ideas about strong men and wild
beasts]. Again some notion of eternal return
is involved as a second dimension of
interpretation. 'All aphorisms must
therefore be read twice' [once literally and once
in terms of symbolism?], once as a specific throw
of the dice, and once as the game itself.
Nietzsche and Mallarmé. [Similarities
and differences are discussed pp 30--32.
Mallarme composed a famous
'concrete' poem about the throw of the dice,
of course]. Both saw the dice throw as two
dimensional, and suggested that human beings want
to domesticate chance in the name of the rational
and the human. Both saw tragedy as
important. Both saw works of art as
constellations. Both affirmed multiplicity
and unity. However, M saw necessity as
abolishing chance, the dice throw as stopping its
operation, as in the poem, with direct
implications for humanity, with chance needing
justification in another world. For N, the
two aspects are joined together, and ressentiment
lurks in the idea of redemptive art.
Tragic Thought. Is affirmation
simply the result of an optimistic mood or
tone? Nietzsche are denies that ressentiment
is just a psychological state, but vis and
biological states should be understood as examples
of a typology, some underlying principle that
explains psychology. Even Christianity
cannot be blamed specifically for producing
ressentiment, which is 'the element of history as
such, the motor of universal history' (32) [absurd
naturalism]. Similarly, all metaphysics of
whatever kind implied judgment of the world.
Ressentiment is a force which produces all the
psychological and cultural notions, including
identity, causality and reason. It began
with human thought itself. It drives our
nihilist [denying nature] thought as some kind of
'transcendental principle'. Struggling
against it will imply serious criticism of
metaphysics, history, psychology and
science. It's difficult at the moment to
think what life would be without
ressentiment. Perhaps we would all have to
become Overmen. Ressentiment marks a
fundamental difference among us, producing both
genealogy and hierarchy.
Nietzsche's philosophy aims to overthrow
ressentiment and transmute it, to oppose
asceticism, realize the positive and affirmative
aspects of will, unlike all those philosophers who
were afraid of it and wanted to constrain
it. The past and future are both innocent,
and the eternal return is to be welcomed.
The price is to accept tragic thought, however,
which is not a struggle against ressentiment but
something joyful and creative, 'pure and multiple
positivity', an acceptance of chance. 'All
the rest is nihilism' (34).
The Touchstone. We can now charge
all earlier tragic philosophers as failing to
break sufficiently with ressentiment, even those
who are able to criticize Christian
morality. They were still ascetics, for
example, upholding abstract reason, some notion of
interiority, often developing anguish or
guilt. Nietzsche offers instead 'full virile
maturity', dancing and playing [playing is not
betting, so we can accuse Pascal of not accepting
the full implications of chance, but representing
some kind of timid attempt to turn chance into
probability]. Nietzsche welcomes the end of
god, the acknowledgement of monstrosity in chaos,
and in this he has gone much further than the
others to fundamentally oppose asceticism, bad
conscience, and ressentiment.
Chapter two. Active and Reactive
Spinoza said that we should redirect our attention
to the body instead of just thinking about
consciousness and spirit all the time, and that so
far we did not even know where the body could
do. Nietzsche continues this with his view
that consciousness is nothing but a symptom, and
is the passive partner when it comes to
establishing values. This explains the
frequent characteristics of it as a slave
consciousness, usually appearing only when some
superior possibility arises, defined as a superior
body. The body is not just a field of
forces, [a distinct object] since there is no
external reality apart from force already.
Quantities of force in relations of tension is all
there is, and forces are hierarchically arranged –
they either obey or command. A body is this
relation between contending forces, including
chemical biological and social bodies. This
also explains why bodies are 'always the fruit of
chance' (37), something astonishing [I think the
astonishing thing is that the relation of forces
has an outcome]. Inevitably, the body must
be a multiple phenomenon, unified by
domination. It possesses superior or active
forces and inferior or reactive ones. A
hierarchy is this difference between forces, and
quantity and quality are combined.
Obeying and commanding relates to power, but power
never dominates completely, with no trace of
struggle. It is more that inferior or
reactive forces use their power to adapt [almost a
notion of hegemony?]. Reaction involves
accommodation and regulation. However, it is
not enough just to chart these, fascinating as
they might be, and we often see them as means or
even ends in their own rights, without referring
to what it is that these dominating them.
This neglects all the spontaneous form-giving
active forces, but these do not appear to
consciousness, since that consciousness is
reactive [keep up!]. This is why we do not
know what a body can do. It is also why we
have only a limited understanding of memory, and
nutrition and reproduction as well. It is
not just a matter of mechanism vs. vitalism, since
vitalism can also be misled in its emphasis on
reactive forces. There are unconscious
active forces as well, which explains the
importance of the body [and, presumably, gives a
foundation to all that crap about
physiology?]. The body is what makes the
self into a potentially very powerful being.
Science must study the active forces, not the
activities of consciousness, and this also has a
moral implication [helping us develop a critical
stance towards the world and to the old slave
moralities?]. The active reaches out for
power, imposing forms and creating them.
Darwin is mistaken for seeing evolution entirely
in a reactive way, and N preferred Lamarck [who
fitted his preconceptions better, even if it was
highly dubious – so much for science].
Transformative energy is the same as
nobility. It is Dionysian power.
However, reactive forces always accompany such
power [and vice versa].
It is the qualities of forces, active and
reactive, that we must think about first.
However, there is a quantitative dimension, and
Nietzsche was well aware that science was able to
quantify: indeed, he thought this approach would
even one day generate 'the scientific order of
values' (40), although this would be abstract and
ambiguous. Quality was important if we were
to move beyond description. Quality cannot
be reduced to quantity, but rather the reverse,
quantities are signs of quality. Deleuze
argues that this means in general that quantity is
important because it generates differences which
describe the essence of force, and it is only
useful in this context, say for describing how
unities form when quantitative differences are
equalized [maybe]. These differences in
quantity should not be neglected, however [as when
we take averages instead of ranges of
values? And of course, Deleuze has to
preserve the importance of difference]. It
is never possible, therefore, to reduce
differences by describing numerical equalities,
since quality persists, and it can be seen as
something that cannot be represented in numerical
equality [what a long winded way to say
this]. Since differences always persist, so
qualities must also be involved [does this
argument work backwards? All depends on
Nietzsche deciding that qualities are the same as
differences in quantity—only the
same?]. In a strange bit, Deleuze says
Nietzsche goes on to talk about subjectivity,
which seems to be involved in what could be an
anthropomorphic argument {because we are really
thinking of human qualities underpinning our
quantitative measures?} , but says that Nietzsche
is only interested in cosmic subjectivity
[Somehow, this lets him off the hook! He denies
human subjectivity by invoking some mystical
one?]. Chance is important and can bring
together and relate all forces. Chance is
affirmed in the motion of the eternal
return. However, the chance relation of
forces takes place at the concrete level [Deleuze
likes to argue that Nietzsche says that chance has
a heavenly level as well]. This is the
affirmative dimension of chance, which creates [?]
the potential for power, by bringing quality to
the relation. Nietzsche says 'in an obscure
passage' (41) [in Will
to Power, apparently] that although
the universe itself generates arbitrary qualities,
this somehow generates an order of quantities as
well. The arbitrary origin of quantities
apparently means that we can't calculate forces
quantitatively alone, but need to include the
equalities and 'the nuance of this
quality'[obfuscation in my view, and circular
again -- if qualities have nuances, obviously you
can't quantify, since 'nuance' here means
something unquantifiable?].
Apparently, the discussion about science depends
on the theory of the eternal return, suggesting
that Nietzsche was interested in science only if
it favored the eternal return [!], and in areas
where it did not, he neglected it. Deleuze
has a different take. Nietzsche was no
scientist, but he did have a suitable way of
thinking. He did assume that science always
ends in equilibrium and equality [assuming natural
equilibrium? If so, that explains a lot in
the paragraph above]. Quality and difference
must be preserved instead. It might be
possible to develop some sort of quantitative
scale nonetheless, but not a ratio one.
Science was obsessed [in his day] with
utilitarianism and egalitarianism. His
critique sets out to challenge these views,
especially taking on the current 'three forms of
the undifferentiated'[logical identity,
mathematical equality, physical
equilibrium]. [The old elitist opposed
egaliatarinaims on political and cultural grounds
-- no need for the eternal return to intervene].
By insisting on reduction to the quantifiable,
science becomes nihilist, denying life with all
its vital differences, and predicting eventual
equilibrium [as in heat death of the universe
]. The basic categories of matter, weight
and heat, for example depend on this underlying
notion of equalizing quantities. Science
thus belongs to asceticism. Science is
nihilist because it focuses excessively on the
reactive forces, and therefore describes only the
petty side of things. Reactive physics is
also riddled with ressentiment, and so is biology,
although this is not initially clear.
Science either affirms or denies the eternal
return. The critique of science makes it
clear that this return cannot be mechanistic, more
can arguments from thermodynamics be decisive in
rejecting it [so this was one of the objections in
Nietzsche's day? That the eternal return did
not incorporate entropy?]. We can see in the
insistence that energy must be conserved, for
example, a view that says the cancellation of
differences is inevitable. This is how a
nihilistic principle creeps in, from an undue
focus on 'finitude'[as in the objective
illusion?]. Obviously a mechanistic version
also assumes some long-term balance or
equilibrium, despite short term changes in the
intermediate term. Thermodynamics assumes
that differences in quantity cancel each other out
in the long-term, as with the properties of
heat. The first and final states are
undifferentiated in each case, and if this were
true, becoming would end either in the same state
of being or in nothing [classic philosophical
argument, not willing to be compelled in any way
by science in this case,but wriggling round
inconvenient arguments by saying they cannot be
true if some valued principle is not to be
sacrificed --exactly how Deleuze proceeds in this
discussion of the eternal return]. The
eternal return therefore cannot be [!] the return
of the identical, but a different sort of
synthesis, which science cannot deal with.
Somehow, diversity and difference itself has to be
reproduced. It is not identity that drives
the eternal return, but its opposite, not the same
but the diverse. [So Deleuze is arguing for
this congenial version of the eternal return not
from what Nietzsche actually says about it, but by
following an implication from what he says about
quality, quantity, and science].
If equilibrium was the goal, it would've been
achieved already [see above]. An examination
of the present shows that there is no equilibrium
[!] Given the elapse of infinite time, becoming
would have already started, and the notion of
becoming excludes the possibility of ending in
becoming something. Therefore, since
becoming has not attained its final state this
means that becoming is not a process with a
beginning and an end. If it is finite, what
started it? Can there be any single moment
of being that is not affected by it?
Apparently, all the earlier thinkers confirm this
view of becoming, although this was usually
accompanied by theological ulterior motives, an
unwitting sense of tragedy. Only Heraclitus
thought of this sort of pure becoming.
The idea that this present moment is a passing
moment forces us to think of becoming [Deleuze
uses the same sort of argument in his discussion
of Bergson].
If we take seriously the notion of becoming, it
follows that being, as a moment of becoming, must
include becoming. As a result the eternal
return shows is a world of becoming to a world of
being [an actual quote from Nietzsche's French
version of Will to
Power supports this, 44]. It
all looks like the problem in Bergson about how
the present somehow contains the past, how the
past comes to be: the moment must be somehow
continuously present and past, and yet to
come. The eternal return is a process of
this kind. It is not being that returns, but
'rather the returning itself that constitutes
being' (45). Returning is the process, and
that affirms 'diversity or multiplicity'.
The eternal return synthesizes different moments
of time, diversity and its reproduction,
being and becoming: being is 'affirmed in
becoming'. This fulfills 'a truly sufficient
reason' [this process of C19th sufficient
reason, systematically working from principles to
conclusions is the heart of philosophy for
Deleuze, and is discussed best in the book on Leibniz].
Not only that, mechanism does not actually imply
eternal return [in this sense], but focuses only
on the 'the false consequence of a final state',
reproducing the same set of differences in a
cyclical way. For Nietzsche, this would not
explain the impulse that leaves the initial state,
and reenergizes the final state to repeat
itself. Not only that, it would ignore the
diversity in each cycle [one of those
philosophical arguments again]. 'We can
only' [!] see the eternal return as an expression
of 'difference and its repetition'. [Note
that this does not seem to be much of a difference
[!] between the processes of difference and
repetition and multiplicity, despite some attempts
to see an important shift marking some kind of
breach from formal philosophy to politics].
This principle is the will to power, and, here,
power is used as a supplementary force to
mechanism [expressed in one of those classically
backward philosophical arguments - since we cannot
think the will to power in mechanistic terms, the
mechanistic order is a mistake].
The will to power is spelt out in various ways
[references to the French edition of will to
power]. It is a completion of the important
concept of force in physics, one which adds the
notion of inner will. It is added to
force. It involves a separate will [so force
cannot act on its own]. We have already seen
that forces are always related and that
quantitative differences are signs of qualitative
ones. The qualitative ones are those derived
from the will to power. In this way, the
will to power can be seen as synthesizing or
relating forces [dizzy logic, leaping over all
sorts of steps in between]. The synthesis of
forces also helps us understand time. A
particular kind of synthesis produces the eternal
return, so [wait for it] the eternal return 'has
as its principle the will to power' (46) [here as
elsewhere,' principle' is understood as the
opening statement in a chain of sufficient
reason?]. However, Nietzsche thinks the
principles are too general 'in relation to what
they condition', which is why he thought
Schopenhauer on the will to live was too general
[and not hierarchical enough politically] ,
compared to the will to power. A good
principle 'reconciles empiricism with principles',
and does this by being 'no wider than what it
conditions, that changes itself with the
conditions, and determines itself in each case
along with what it determines' [highly suspicious
in my view, allowing all sorts of adjustments to
move from principle to empirical cases, and making
it so flexible than it can never be
falsified]. In this way, the will to power
is never separable from actual forces and is
'always plastic and changing' (47).
To separate too drastically the will from its
manifestations risks metaphysical abstraction, but
to equate the two supports mechanism [nasty
dilemma]. There is a difference between
forces that can and power that wills
[anthropomorphism again?]. Relations of
forces always reproduces relations of domination,
but domination always involves an internal will in
order to achieve it, otherwise there would be
indeterminacy. We have already seen that
forces need to be produced both by differences
between themselves, but also something that
generates these [qualitative] differences – this
is the will to power, the genetic element.
This is 'in no way anthropomorphic', but [or
because?] it can be rendered in mathematical terms
[very weak defense] by referring to it in terms of
(x+dx) [where dx is presumably changes in x.
I don't know if this is one of the examples in
Sokal's polemic], and we can then go on to
describe the relation between the forces as
dy/dx. We have thus seen the will to power
as 'the genealogical element of force and of
forces'[this seems to be relating back to Leibniz
and the discovery of an abstract relation which
underpins actual relations of x and y, and which
is detectable even when the arithmetic values of x
and y are reduced to zero. This adds some
mathematical credibility to Nietzsche, although
whether it is implicit in what he sees is of
course highly debatable].
However, we have still not elucidated or analyzed
the will to power, nor seen how this combination
of abstract and concrete relationships produces
the eternal return 'in conformity with its
principle'. We need to examine Nietzsche's
relation to Kantian notions of synthesis, and the
subsequent critiques [that it was not clear how it
worked or related to the objects that were being
synthesized?]. A true notion of genesis or
production would also require some constant
['eternal', but I am thinking this could be a typo
for 'external']process of synthesis, to replace
the strange role of 'miraculous harmonies between
terms that [still somehow] remain external to one
another' (48). Nietzsche has been influenced
by these critics, and turns synthesis into a
matter of relations of forces [which makes it
appear much more material and external?], and
added the eternal return as a constant generation
of diversity, which requires synthesis to operate
[so here we have a motion of the eternal return as
pretty well constant in its operation?].
This gives Nietzsche an implicit Kantian heritage
and a rivalry with his [Hegelian?] critics.
He thought he had rescued Kant by going beyond him
internally, so to speak, with the motion of the
eternal rreturn and will to power. [So the whole
argument is also addressing other philosophers and
their controversies, as usual].
We have to tidy up the terminology, and then we
can make his philosophy rigorous. First the
notion of genealogy involves both differential and
genetic components, and this is how the will to
power produces differences in quantity and
something that produces the quality. It also
implies chance if it is to be plastic [!], and
only the will to power can affirm all
chance. Second, forces are dominant if they
possess a certain quantity, but they are active or
reactive depending on quality. Even the
reactive forces express a will to power. The
differences in quality actually explain
quantitative consequences. The task is to
interpret these qualitative differences and see
how they affect particular events or phenomena,
and thus to work out the relation of forces: this
will not be easy, and we need a method as finely
discriminating as that of chemistry. Third,
the will to power is the principle of the
qualities of force, and that also means the act of
interpreting. It follows that the will to
power must have qualities itself, quite fluent and
subtle ones [because it has to do this clever
interpretation first]. These qualities
appear only momentarily. They are separate
from the qualities of force itself: force can be
active or reactive, but the will to power is
affirmative or negative. There is even a
will to nothingness. However, there is a
'deep affinity, a complicity'(50) between action
and affirmation, reaction and negation.
Action and reaction appear as a means to exercise
the will to power, and they both have to be
affirmed [which I think means given philosophical
significance]. Affirmation is a kind of
license to become active. Affirmation and
negation are immanent [and transcendental, he
says] to action and reaction. Fourth, the
will to power both interprets and evaluates [since
we like affirmation, it is Dionysian], and, more
technically, it is the will to power which adds
value, as something qualitative. Values are
always connected to evaluation of this kind, so it
is the will to power that produces specific sets
of values: they represent a particular quality of
force which is active or reactive [there's also
the term nuance, unexplained so far]. Thus
values are valuable [!] if they express an
affirmative will to power. All these
operations are considered to be inherently
connected, which gives some problems with
Nietzsche's terminology, so that he uses terms
like noble or master to refer both to active
force, and affirmative will, and the
converse. These notions of nobility or
whatever provide a clue to the value of a belief
system, and hint at its genealogy, but it requires
genealogy to further uncover how nobility gets
connected [a very fancy way of saying that
philology shows that the terms good and valuable
originally also referred to the nobles, advanced
in Genealogy of
Morals -- pretty thin stuff I
thought]. In this way, genealogists are the
best able to critique systems of values.
There is no other way, since values are not self
sufficient, and it is not enough to praise all
values alike, since some of them are clearly based
on slavery: unfortunately, Nietzsche's system
turned into the most appalling conformism, driven
by ressentiment [no one is specifically
mentioned].
Action and reaction coexist. The negative is
already solely reactive. Only active force
asserts itself and affirms its difference, but it
can be limited by reactive and negative
forces. There appears 'an inverted self
image' (52) of an element in its origin. In
social terms, noble active forces are confronted
by plebeian images, and this connection appears
usually as an evolution, sometimes in dialectical
terms as the development of contradiction,
sometimes in utilitarian terms as a kind of their
derivation or development, say of the
economy. Beneath these reactive images lies
genealogy. Reactive forces deny that they
are anything other than an evolution, because they
have to oppose any fundamental difference.
This produces mediocre analysis, and a preference
for reactive forces [at the conscious
level]. However the original inversion in
genealogy is what is responsible, and it is this
that produces consciousness of reaction.
Certain factors can assist the development of
reactive forces, including a negative will to
power or will to nothingness. Is it just
that reactive forces develop so that they can
overpower active ones and become, in a way,
aggressively active themselves? Nietzsche's
answer [avoids this problem] by saying that what
the reactive forces do is to decompose active
forces from their content, stripping active power,
and making those active forces join them
instead. So we have an idea of subtraction
or division as the secret of reactive forces, and
this is what ressentiment, bad conscience, and the
ascetic ideal reveal. The separation in turn
depends on some mystification or falsification [we
are nearly at the concept of ideology!], something
imaginary [with a mystifying reference to a
'negative utilization of number' -- subtraction?
(53)]. Separating active force from action
is only the first stage, the second is to tie it
to some mystifying justification [maybe], and
Nietzsche has in mind the [eg Christian]
revaluation of slavery or the ignoble, and the way
in which it persists as an active force, even in
those who are politically dominant.
This means it is not enough to analyze actual
combinations of forces, since active forces can
incorporate [inverted] inferior forces. This
is why we have to actively support the strong, as
in Will to Power.
Success in the struggle does not always indicate
the triumph of the affirmative and active: that
still remains to be demonstrated after analysis
and interpretation. We cannot use simple
physics or mathematics, and must be prepared to go
beyond what happens to be the factual case in any
social system. Deleuze tells us this echoes
an old debate with Socrates [54, which seems to
tie in with Deleuze's view about desire].
Nietzsche also encounters the modern equivalent of
Socrates, 'the free thinkers' (55), positivists
who suggests that we must just accept accomplished
facts, dismissing any notion of independent
values. This is 'fatalism'[of a bad kind],
often uncritically accepting what has happened
entirely in positive terms [as social functions,
for example]. Positivist can still be
atheists, but still have this positive functional
view of religion. Anything human seems to be
praiseworthy, without asking of its origins.
Because there is no analysis of the struggle
between active and reactive, the reactive tends to
be seen as natural and dominant, providing a
series of facts that can be asserted against the
really strong, the free spirits as opposed to the
free thinkers. It is clear that a number of
ideologies can be criticized here, including
humanism and the dialectic [which is itself
obsessed with operating with already humanized
contents].
The term hierarchy refers to the difference
between active and reactive forces, with the
former always superior, and this is what makes it
innate. But [social] hierarchies show the
triumph of reactive forces, where the weak have
triumphed after all, with this system propped up
by morality or religion. This is a bad
hierarchy, and we miss that it is back to
front. [The old argument that it is the weak
who have really prevailed]. The weak happen
to be cunning and witty enough to perpetuate this
illusion [as in the crafty and charming
serpent]. To get to the bottom of this
inversion, we have to analyze forces
properly. [The term nuance appears again,
this time referring to a quality of a reactive
force, how it appears at a particular stage of
development. Still not very clear!
There is another quality of active force which
says that it must always go 'to the limit of what
it can do', whereas, presumably, reactive forces
have no such impetus of their own?].
The will to power is the genealogical element that
produces the relation of the forces and their
quality. It must manifest itself in
force. These manifestations have to be
carefully analyzed. One appears as a
capacity for being affected [by forces], which
introduces an apparently contradictory notion that
the will to power both produces forces and is
determined by them, 'always determined at the same
time as it determines' (57). Apparently,
this is Spinozist, where a capacity to be affected
corresponds to every quantity of force, as in his
notion of the body, where the more ways we have to
be affected, the more power we have. This is
not just an abstract possibility, apparently,
because we can detect it in the actual bodies in
relation. For Nietzsche, the capacity to be
affected is a sensibility or affectivity, some
feeling of power, which becomes an aspect of the
manifestation of the will to power. This is
why the will to power affects all the other
feelings, often acting as a pathos. This is
why the will to power affects everything, and can
even act at a distance if things feel they are
attracted. When the will to power is
manifested, it perceives some things and feels the
approach of something assimilable [getting really
into fairyland here]. Feeling the strength
of assimilation can therefore be a manifestation
of the will to power, even if this leads to
obedience or submission. Sometimes, an
interior force can decompose a superior one,
just as atoms can disintegrate. So [nothing
lies outside of the will to power]. [Also
think there's some equilibrium detectable in here,
where the capacity to affect somehow aligns up
nicely with the capacity to be affected: it seems
to require some 'process of sensible becoming'
(59)]. Again it is the underlying forces and
the interactions that produce sensibility.
Forces can change into the opposite, struggle with
each other or 'become'. So we're not
just talking about a struggle between opposites,
since the will to power has qualities which affect
the becoming of forces, it's sensibility [capacity
to affect or be affected]. Pathos --in the
sense of suffering-- is the most elementary or
common form in which a becoming appears [not just
anthropomorphism-- egocentrism].
We seem to have an argument that active forces
have a tendency to become reactive, with becoming
in the stronger sense. There might be other
forms of becoming, but we only know becoming -
reactive. Reactive forces seem to triumph
everywhere: they benefit from the will to
nothingness, and from the appeal of
negation. This explains the growth of
nihilism and its characteristic forms like
ressentiment, bad conscience and asceticism.
We would need a different sort of sensibility to
detect other kinds of becoming, which implies that
human beings are essentially reactive, and that
ressentiment and the rest are the very principles
of human being: this explains Nietzsche's disgust
at human beings. This argument has
implications for the eternal return, which seems
doomed to take a reactive or disgusting form, and
indeed Zarathustra says finds it nauseating,
in the first version. However, this would
introduce contradiction into the notion of the
eternal return, which now features becoming
nihilist. It requires the development of the
Overman to avoid the nausea.
Becoming active would be quite different from the
becoming that we know of now. If we are to
argue that Nietzschian concepts are consistent [!]
we will have to work out what it might be.
There are some problems to deal with. First
we have seen that active forces become reactive:
once they have done so, why don't reactive forces
also go to the limit of what they can do? Is
it this that produces the delusions of grandeur
that Nietzsche complains about [in connection with
Napoleon, as I recall], and has this not showed
that reactive forces have become active in their
own way? We can see reactive forces from
different points of view, as illness, for example
which narrows possibilities, but which also
reveals new capacities and new forms of the
will. Actually, Nietzsche is fascinated by
the ability of reactive forces to open
perspectives and reawaken will to power.
Even religion has certain admirable aspects.
However, we could argue that it is not the same
illness which has these apparent ambivalent
effects. This is where we have to consider
nuance, which affects the connection with the will
to nothingness. So reactive forces can lead
to resistance, contamination of active force, they
can grow out of active forces—there are different
types, with different affects. Nietzsche
seems to use the term nuance to refer to the
subtle differences that only long experience can
alert him to, for example his long experience with
decadence. Subtle forms of interpretation
are required for both active and reactive forces
[highly suspicious in my view, meaning he can make
them into whatever he wants]. Thus some
reactive forces become grandiose, some active
forces do not know how to turn into affirmation
[that typical fate of the cultured]: all depends
on the geneaologist's art. Nietzsche's
interest in physiology leads him to see this in
terms of sickness and health. Differences
remain when the forces go to the ultimate
limits. Becoming active leads to a link
between action and affirmation, while reactive
becomings are connected to negation and a will to
nothingness [repetitive assertion, circular
suggestions for analysis].
Becoming active must involve selection of the
activity and of an affirmative will. It is
the eternal return that acts as the selective
principle. It provides the will to power
with a rule: 'whatever you will, will it in such a
way that you also will its eternal return'
(63). [This is the bit that appears in Will
to Power as urging us to live as well as we
can, because everything will be repeated].
The alternative is to be utilitarian and
parsimonious with our pleasures, enjoy things only
once, and as some sort of reward. It is the
thought of the eternal return that selects, and it
also informs our willing, making it more
creative. Even so, this is not enough,
because reactive forces can still resist this
selection if they are combined with the active
ones. A second selection is required, and
this is both obscure and esoteric, so Deleuze has
to construct its for us. First the eternal
return makes the will complete, and this must also
mean that it makes the nihilistic will complete
[or no nihilism can be complete without it]
. Second, we saw before that the will to
nothingness is allied to reactive forces, and
appears in this universal form of becoming, but is
never complete, capable of conserving only a
reactive life, negation. Third, the eternal
return can make the will to nothingness complete
only by achieving some absolute negation, the
negation of reactive forces themselves, the self
destruction of the weak, indicated in Zarathustra
by people who will their own downfall [the
Prologue, apparently]. Fourthly we are not
just talking about turning against one's self,
turning active forces into reactive ones, but
proper self destruction, where even the reactive
forces are denied. This possibility of
denying reactive forces becomes a matter of active
negation or active destruction and is seen in the
ways in which the strong spirits destroy their own
reactive tendencies, by thinking of the eternal
return, and accepting the eternal return even if
it leads to self destruction. They are not
just admitting to judgment, but agreeing to self
destruction [I think the secular version of this
is being willing to sacrifice themselves in order
to become affirmative and strong]. This
negation of the reactive forces can become
affirmative, and lead to eternal joy, the joy of
destroying the negative as an act of affirmation
[with a link back to the Dionysian celebratory
acceptance of tragedy in The Birth of Tragedy].
Fifthly, since the eternal return destroys
reactive forces, they cannot return themselves,
and nor will those representatives of reaction
like the small man. Negation has been
affirmed [seen as part of life as in
Dionysus]. This is different from the simple
idea that we should will everything that returns,
since here the eternal return makes something come
into being, but only by changing its nature: 'the
eternal return is being and being is selection
(Selection = hierarchy)'(66) [all this is still
definitional really?].
We have to elucidate these points. We have
to remember that transmutation of values means
affirmation instead of negation as in 'the supreme
Dionysian metamorphosis'. Eternal return is
the being of becoming, and becoming itself has two
aspects—becoming active and becoming reactive--
and the transformations of both into their
opposites is possible. 'But only becoming
active has being'(66), since becoming reactive is
dependent on active being, or is itself nihilistic
[maybe]. There can be no becoming based on
the return of reactive forces, so an eternal
return says the [nihilistic] reactive forces must
be overcome. Affirmation thus has a
particular support, in being the only force to
affirm being [on the other side of the eternal
return]. The eternal return helps us see that
becoming active is the only kind of becoming which
can possibly have a universal application to being
[both here and on the other side of the eternal
return] . Affirmation therefore gains
profundity from its connections with the eternal
return, as it 'changes nuance' (67). The
eternal return also has a selective ontology by
preferring affirmation as universal
becoming. This is all spelled out in terms
of the discussions that Zarathustra has with his
animals, who cannot understand his disgust at the
prospect of an eternal return that does not
select. What he is trying to say is that
affirmation covers the whole, universal being,
because affirmative force has been selected as a
single becoming [maybe]. [ The terms and their
properties depend on each other again -- the
eternal return validates affirmation, because
affirmation is the only force to survive ,because
reactive forces are nihilistic, meaning they
perish before the eternal return -- etc].
Chapter three Critique
Overall, sciences dominated by the passive and
reactive concepts, we can see this in human
sciences as well, which are dominated in terms of
utility, adaptation, regulation, and forgetting
[all Nietzsche's terms in Genealogy...].
They lack genealogy. In each case, the facts
dominate, but they are never interpreted as a
result of a will, to truth and to power. As
science progresses, so it becomes more submissive
to the established order [I'm not sure this is at
all true of the latest theoretical physics].
Sciences are also dominated by a heartless
scholasticism. Nietzsche's attack on
utilitarianism was important in its decline [in
France?]. It is inevitable that questions of
utility must involve someone making a judgement
about what is useful, and how best to judge action
anyway, despite what the actors themselves
think. Utilitarian thoughts claim some
special privilege, but they are really based on
ressentiment. If this sort of generalization
is a necessary part of science, it is also found
in philosophy, so Hegel can also be criticized on
the same grounds as utilitarianism. Real
activities are replaced by generalizations based
on the third party's perspective: which itself
produces some profit for the third party. We can
apply this critique to linguistics, which is
usually judged from the point of view of the
recipient. An active philology would be
different, reflecting how language obeys force
rather than reacts to it. Again, the meaning
of the word depends on the will of the speaker,
suggesting that the noble business of naming
things itself as the origin of language. It
then becomes important to ask who it is that is
doing the speaking and naming and what they might
will by it. Once uttered, words can be
possessed by another force and another will.
We see the best analysis of this in the discussion
of the word 'good' in Genealogy...
[I wasn't terribly impressed I must say]. It
follows we should be developing an active science
based on active forces not just reactive
ones. This leads to a symptomatology, where
phenomena are treated as symptoms of some forces;
a typology, since we can see different forces at
work in terms of activity; a genealogy tracing the
origin of the forces in terms of their nobility
and will. All sciences should work like this
and so should philosophy. We see this in
Nietzsche's speculation about the philosophy of
the future [which apparently appears in Will...
and elsewhere].
We also have to rethink what a question is.
It seems obvious to ask 'what is', but there is an
implicit metaphysics, beginning with the Greeks
and Plato deciding to focus on ideal rather than
specific cases, the distinction between beautiful
things and Beauty, something rooted in being and
essence. This form of questioning was not
always very successful, however, as a way of
getting to the essence, and the sophists preferred
another question – 'which one?'. This, they
thought would lead to the issue of what continues
as essential qualities among concrete
objects. The procedure also offered an
empirical form of enquiry, and was pluralist
rather than dialectic. Nietzsche follows
this argument and says that 'which one' means
inquiring into the forces and will that possess a
given thing – which force or will is manifested in
it. Essence express the value or sense of a
thing, and thus in turn is determined by the
forces with affinities for that thing, and well
with affinity for the forces. Still asking
what is it assumes that there is some external
sense, whereas really, essence is perspectival
[depending on the person asking in this case, but
there's also some non subjective
standpoint?]. It follows that there is a
plurality of essence, and that essence is always
related to sense and value. The whole thing
can be symbolized by Dionysus, the gold of
transformations, 'the unity of multiplicity' (72),
so it is always him that we find when we ask which
one is it [t is Nietzsche's poem Ariadne's
Complaint, where all this is to be found
apparently, in Dionysian Dithyrambs].
The method then involves symptomatology first, to
ask first which the one is that says something
thinks or feels and wills. This is useful
for asking, for example, what someone wills when
he appeals to some ideology, or pursues some
action. Even those apparently without a
will, like ascetics are willing something.
There must be a will to power, otherwise nothing
could be thought or experienced. This is
also the tragic method, or the method of
dramatization, although we must strip that term of
'Christian and dialectical pathos' [Deleuze has a
more secular version of his method of
dramatization. I think in Two Regimes of
Madness]. What the will wants is not
simply an objective or object, since these are
still symptoms. What it wants is to affirm
its difference, which might include denying other
forms of difference. Qualities are willed,
whether something is heavy or light [remembering
that something light means something noble and
affirmative]. In other words, when we ask
which one, we require an answer that refers to a
type, one reflecting the quality of the will to
power and its nuance. [I am confused].
It is a 'type of the one that speaks of the one
that thinks, that acts, that does not act, that
reacts etc' (73). We ask what wills
typically want in actions of this kind [so it is
an ideal type?]. Again this looks
anthropomorphic, but we're only talking about
types of man [feeble], and we can use this to
question some of our earlier generalizations, such
as that man is always reactive. Animals,
things and gods can also dramatize, since all are
transformations of Dionysus, [who in this case
seems to refer to some universal will]. Thus
we can ask interesting philosophical questions
like what would the will of the Earth look like,
and Nietzsche is able to answer by assuming that
it must be Dionysian lightness [circular arguments
again, one that first asserts that Dionysus is
some universal will, and then we discover that any
particular objects that might have a will must
therefore represent the characteristics of
Dionysus!].
A will to power does not mean that the will wants
power: the two are inherently connected, thus
there can be no separate will like the will to
live [in Schopenhauer]. The Nietzschian will
to power is therefore entirely new, and even
though others have used the term, they used it in
a different sense, as if power were the ultimate
aim of will and its motive, and Nietzsche
criticized this view. It is based on three
misunderstandings.
First, it involves
a particular representation of power, activated
by the will. This is the conception in
Hegel [and Hobbes and others]. It also
involves recognition, some 'comparison of
consciousness'(75), which involves some other
dimension of will which takes the form of a
motive to compare, and which we might find in
vanity or pride, or even inferiority. This
again involves the fundamental question of who
is conceiving of the will to power like this,
who wants to be represented as superior, or
gratifyingly inferior? Nietzsche suggests
it will be the weak or slaves. So this
notion of power is actually a slave notion, when
he imagines himself in his master's place.
It is a representation of nobility, which
clearly signifies the lack of real
nobility. This has been classically
misrecognized in the master slave
dialectic. The passion to have things
represented, even to have representatives is
found in slaves, as 'the only relation between
themselves they can conceive of' (76), and this
conception has limited to grasp of philosophy
when it considers power.
Second if we make power an object of
representation, we make it dependent upon the
processes of representation and recognition, and
this delivers us straight away to accepted
values, which alone can grant recognition.
It is really an argument that current values
should be attributed to ourselves. There
is no alternative for the common man who is not
in a position to go beyond values that have been
assigned to him. Hobbes' philosophy just
takes this picture of the common man, and so
does Hegel's: neither sees the will to power as
a mastery of creating new values.
Thirdly, established values are attributed
through combat and struggle, driven by an
attempt to profit from current values [a crypto
theory of social class, except that the
universal class is 'the strong']. It is
typical for any social struggle to be judged by
established values. However, struggle,
war, rivalry and comparison, 'are foreign to
Nietzsche and his conception of the will to
power'(76). [I am not all convinced by
this, since war and militarism, not to mention
knightly combat, are occasionally admired, not
least in The Gay
Science]. He does not see
struggle as creating values except those
of the triumphant slave, so struggle helps
slaves reverse hierarchy, but never expresses
active force nor an affirmative will to
power. Struggle rewards the weak against
the strong [because we are defining struggle
here as popular upheaval, not as the constant
grinding of the face of the poor]. We see
this in the opposition to Darwin, who could not
see that selection really favoured the weak [I
read this differently, as Darwin not emphasizing
the creative aspects of the evolution, which
might be the same thing]. Nietzsche
himself says that he 'is much too well bred to
struggle'(77) [no doubt, but he admired men of
action nevertheless].
We have to be careful not to introduce 'emotional
tonality' into the discussion of the will to
power, as when we discover its essence only in
grief or dejection, and yearn to escape from
power, as if it were possible. This follows
from seeing the will to power as a desire to
dominate, which can then be rendered as something
contradicting a universal will to power [a will to
live]. It is common to note the
contradiction between the good and the bad sides,
between particular representations or appearances
of power. It follows that the bad sides of
power needs to be limited, say by social
contract. Schopenhauer draws out the
implications by making the will to power the
essence of life, producing appearance in general,
power as representation again. This is a
mystification, uniting representation with the
world in principle, seeing the world itself as
some kind of appearance or illusion. For
Schopenhauer, this produces people who limit their
options, not only by contract but by a form of
'mystical suppression'(78). [this is beyond
my competence, but I have commented on it in my
discussions of what Nietzsche says about
Schopenhauer here and there].
The old metaphysics is to be superseded by
focusing on the will. The will is both
affirmative and creating, and joyful. It
liberates [all the references are to the joyful
bits in Zarathustra].
The strong should create their own values.
We see the point if we consider earlier
conceptions of the will as above, which have
enshrined slave ideas, together with an
association of suffering. However, to avoid
anthropomorphism, we have to see that power itself
wills, and, for that matter, power cannot be
[conventionally] represented or evaluated, since
everything depends on what power lies behind these
representations [heading towards Weber again here
on power as the underlying category for social
stratification? Same problems of overgeneralizing
and losing specificity?]. Power wills the
regulation of forces [and is now actually,
determined by forces at the same time!], and
either affirms or denies. Again we can think
of a typology of combinations which will produce
different phenomena. This is to be seen as
something creative, not that phenomena simply
reflect types of power and force. Power
energizes these combinations, does not desire or
seek them. It 'bestows sense and value' on
behalf of the will. What results is a
variety of cases, not just the unitary or
the multiple, since 'unity...is affirmed of
multiplicity': 'the monism of the will to power is
inseparable from a pluralist typology'. If
we think of power as active or reactive, we do not
just get a typology but rather 'a hierarchical
whole', in which active forces prevail over
reactive ones [who form some sort of subordinate
whole, presumably because they have to in order to
perform this mysterious stripping away of active
force from actuals]. Nietzsche uses the
terms high and noble to depict superior active
forces which affirm, and sees these as light, and
the opposite terms for the reactive. It has
been said earlier, that human phenomena are
manifested by the reactive, but here, the human
[some humans?] is rendered as being animated by a
base, heavy soul. Of course, even Deleuze
notes, the whole thing is based on some assumed
superiority of the noble and light, the
affirmative, but this again links to 'the test of
the eternal return', which will select what is
absolutely better, while canceling out the
reactive and the negative.
We can now see critique as anticipating this
transformation of the negative, as joyful and
aggressive because it is creative. Critics
cannot be distinguished from antisocial persons,
like criminals [suits Deleuzian misosophy].
The Genealogy should be seen as a key for
interpreting aphorisms and evaluating poems.
It provides a detailed analysis of the reactive
type. The first form to discuss is
ressentiment, the second bad conscience, and the
third asceticism, the three characteristic feeders
of reactive forces and nihilism. The first
part is needed because the reactive forces
themselves prevent interpretation. The two
aspects together form a critique.
The reactive forces depend on a mystification, to
strip active forces from what they can do.
Ressentiment is an imaginary revenge, implying a
particular paralogism [in this case, a fallacious
argument that looks as if it's logical], to
justify the separation of force from what it can
do. Bad conscience is similarly inseparable
from spiritual or imaginary events, resulting in
the inverted world, a force turned against itself,
antimony [the opposition of two theses in the same
argument: Deleuze says this goes beyond Kant,
however, claiming to be more fundamental].
The ascetic ideal offers a particularly inclusive
ideal to inform or contain morality and knowledge,
by misusing syllogism. There is a will here,
but it wants nothingness. These essays
appear in this order, because Nietzsche wants to
go beyond Kant's critique of pure reason, to show
the limits of Kant's critique. It also
attacks the Kantian heritage through to Hegel and
Feuerbach: Nietzsche sees this as ending in the
critic himself adapting to things and ideas, or
uncovering determinations of which he had been
deprived, 'in short, the dialectic' (82). [I
much prefer Bourdieu's version of how this works,
in Distinction] The main question about
who should undertake critique is neglected in
favor of generalizations about reason and man,
without spelling out which men or whose
reason. By leaving spirit general and
abstract, it inevitably means incorporation with
existing forms of power. If it is underdogs
who do this sort of critique, it looks
progressive, but it's often still the case that
we're talking about reactive forces, which change
positions, but not the power of the ideology
itself [as with religion]. Kant similarly
compromised, and stopped with this
compromise. It even validated further
reactive forces like religion, reason and
morality. Here, the relation is like Marx's
to Hegel, standing critique back on its
feet. But there is no connection with Marx
because Nietzsche wants not just to put the
dialectic back on its feet, but to challenge the
need to do any kind of dialectics, which was
inverted in its very conception.
Critique must be both total and positive, applying
to everything and affirming. Nietzsche can
be criticized for overemphasizing elements in Kant
which led to confusing the power of critique with
some support for the rights of the
criticized. However, this is an unintended
outcome, and Kant can be forgiven for merely
extending an existing conception of critique,
which applied to everything except knowledge and
truth itself, to claims of morality, but not to
morality itself. This had long been
established, and it leaves Kant with a belief in
'true knowledge, true morality and true
religion'(84), what was seen as facts. This
fundamental belief is what ends in
justification. So far, we still do not have
the politics, however, since Nietzsche's critique
is aimed at categories themselves, and how they go
over into actual practices. It is not just a
matter of opposing false morality or false
religions, since we then become institutionalized
critics. At the level of knowledge, Kant's
critique suggested that there was false knowledge
of what was really unknowable, but he should have
focused on the true knowledge, on what can be
known. Inevitably, Nietzsche is forced to
adopt perspectivism, denying any absolutes and
stressing the crucial role of interpretation of
morality or knowledge. Indeed, there is no
knowledge as such, and anything that claims to be
[absolute] knowledge is an illusion, an error, or
falsification.
Kant did develop the notion of immanent critique,
instead of looking for errors introduced from
outside, say from the senses or passions.
There is clearly a risk of contradiction [or
infinte regress] here, if reason is to be used to
critique reason. Kant chose instead to look
to the transcendental but only for something that
conditions reason rather than generating it.
We need a genesis of reason and of understanding,
the will on which it is based, the will to power
as its genesis. Principles [logical
premises] are never transcendental, but come from
the manifestation of the will to power, its
transmutations. In the future, it will be
possible actually to create values, to turn
philosophers into lawgivers [!]. At least
this is better than the dream of dominating the
whole of being [maybe—as in positivism].
Metaphysics began when the old philosophers failed
in this project, saw the limits of sufficient
reason. It is not that philosophers are
somehow more sagacious than other lawgivers,
rather that the destruction of the old values must
result in legislation, creation. In this
happy state, the will to truth is a will to
power. It looks like this is the same sort
of process by which secular philosophy displaced
theology, when philosophy comes into its own.
Nietzsche versus Kant: Nietzsche has genetic and
plastic principles that produce beliefs,
interpretations and evaluations, not
transcendental principles which condition mundane
facts. He wants to develop thought against
reason rather than one which is immanent to
reason, and we find this in what is normally
called irrationalism, where the thinker himself is
opposed to the reasonable being: 'this was the
sense of the dicethrow'. Genealogy is
preferred to Kantian legislation which would
distribute domains and allocate values.
Genealogy predicts wars of the future, instead of
rational harmony and thoughts of creating values,
instead of judging justice and hierarchy.
There is no support for the reasonable being as
either the priest or legislator, and the reactive
man acting according to his self interest is even
preferred, nor does God find a place: the will to
power provides the critical perspective in the
form of a critical type of man [not exactly the
Overman who is to emerge from critique, but a kind
of ancestor of the Overman]. It is the ends
of the Overman that are served by critique: the
point is not to justify anything, but rather usher
in a different way of feeling altogether.
The will to truth was seen as the most important
source of judgement, with God as the highest court
of appeal, but this needs to be critiqued
itself. Kant is the last of the classical
philosophers still believing in the value of truth
as something external, not wanting to ask who
seeks truth, what do they want and what mode of
power are they deploying. Most human beings
do not seek truth, against a philosophical view of
itself, but this only ignores the issue of forces
and the qualities of the will to power.
Nietzsche thinks that the issue is to ask what
truth means in actual circumstances, and how it
became some ideal. It needs to be dramatized
[brought to the forefront and interrogated,
perhaps by asking why we want truth, what might be
wrong with untruths or ignorance]. Concepts
like truth presuppose a truthful world, just as
science posits a world of phenomena different from
actual phenomena. The truth-seeker is
supposed to be at the centre of the truthful
world. Allegedly, he wants not to be
deceived, because that is harmful, but this
opposes that the world is truthful ultimately, and
in a false world it would be better to go along
with the deception. This want is often
disguised under wanting not to deceive [Gay
Science?]. However, wanting the truth
implies that the world itself is not truthful, and
this implicates differences of power. It
also opposes knowledge to life, and preserves the
world of truth for some beyond. This world
becomes just appearance. Ultimately, this is
a moral issue, however, to do with wanting a
better world, one that reflects the virtues of the
one willing the truth. It is a form of
judgement, denouncing appearance and accusing life
itself. Beneath this still lies another
want, wanting life to become virtuous to correct
appearances, to turn against itself, and this is
the 'religious or ascetic
contradiction'(90). This contradiction is
itself a symptom, and the question comes why would
anyone will a diminishment of life,
nihilism? This is a classic issue produced
by reactive forces, which, ironically, pretend to
offer a value superior to life itself. Those
superior values are deeply connected to a desire
to annihilate life, to favor the reactive forces
until they lead to nothingness. The whole
argument shows how knowledge, morality and
religion are linked together as layers, and why
asceticism is so widespread and difficult to
critique, because it wields these different layers
differently: even science with its will to truth
is compromised.
However, morality has replaced religion, and
science is increasingly replacing morality.
Christianity has declined through its own
paradoxical development [I like this bit, in Genealogy
and in Gay Science], and is now clearly a
form of thinking belonging to the past.
Current Christian spokespersons just seem immoral
themselves. Morality continues religion, but
in a more creative way. It's also true that
knowledge is the continuation of morality and
religion. Asceticism dominates but it rings
the changes on these elements. This is one
reason why settling accounts between the elements
looks like critique but is not. Will the
paradoxes of the will to truth ruin morality as
well? Could we suggest some other moral
ideal? Again it is hard to avoid asceticism
and its ideals, and that tends to offer regression
back to religion. One conclusion follows:
truth itself can be criticized, and critique must
be a critique of truth. If the will to truth
prospers in this new way, morality will perish,
and this is predicted to be happening in Europe
over the next two centuries. Deleuze likes
the rigor of this argument, its connected steps
[I'm much more skeptical, I just think one
implication follows from the definitions at the
earlier stage]. If the argument is
successful, the ascetic ideal itself can no longer
hide behind some will to truth, some claim to be
the only way to truth. By breaking with the
will to truth, Nietzsche thinks he has prevented
the ascetic ideal from mutating into yet other
forms, and claims this is another form of seeking
the truth or knowledge. Again the point is
to destroy first so as to leave a place for a
completely different will.
Deleuze works through some apparent contradictions
between difference texts to argue that Nietzsche
is really saying that existing knowledge should
not be set up as an independent set of judgements
opposed to life. In another text he says
that knowledge is too close to life. Deleuze
explains that we have two notions of life here,
one referring to life as a whole and the other
referring to the main forms of life as produced by
reactive forces. There's also a difference
between knowledge and thought: knowledge
domesticates thought as soon as it becomes a
powerful institution, and confines it again to the
reactive. This applies especially to
rational knowledge. Critique, on the other
hand, brings into play new forces and therefore a
new kind of thought, one that can affirm life
without limits, in harmless with affirmative life
itself. Thinking therefore involves
discovering new possibilities of life, even though
this produces serious difficulties for the
thinker. Nietzsche wants to argue that such
thinking is equivalent to the great explorations
of the day, but it faces two constraints, urging
it to be useful knowledge for reactive life, and
that includes the need for thought to establish
itself. Thinking aims at this 'noble
affinity of thought and life.
Nietzsche thinks of art as similarly split.
Proper art expresses 'desire instinct or
will'(95), and stimulates the will to power.
But there's also reactive art, arts with a
therapeutic intent, supporting the reactive
forces. Kant attempted to destroyed this
union, but was forced to see the spectator as
someone who was disinterested, so that Nietzsche
can ask the usual question about who looks at
beauty in this disinterested way. A proper
aesthetics of creation which would support
affirmation, in which the artist would lead an
affirmative and active life. However, art is
also complicit in falsehood and deception, indeed
celebrates it. The point, however, is to
take this power of falsehood deliberately to
combat asceticism [I'm not at all sure I
understand this], stripping out the negative
associations of appearance, but somehow adding to
a deeper sense of reality, and also showing that
power can be brought into effect in the interests
of truth.
The dogmatic has to be opposed. It
argues that thinkers want and love truth; that
proper concepts contain truth; that thinking is a
natural faculty, so that if we think properly we
would end with truth. This implies that
sincerity is the route to truth and that there is
a 'universally shared good sense' (96). It
also argues that are diverted from the truth by
outside forces such as passions, which affect our
sincere thinking and produce errors.
Finally, it is a method that will deliver truth as
long as we adhere to it, and this method is
universally valid. This image of thought
sees truth as an abstract universal and we never
understand the real forces that affect thought
[these would be social forces for most of
us]. Nor is any sense of the truth emerging
in some way separate from its presuppositions [no
empirical truth]. For Nietzsche, there are
these forces at work affecting what we can sense,
and thought will not find the truth just by
itself. It is these forces that produce
obvious truths. Reactive forces clearly are
at work in producing conformist truth as an easy
and pleasant discovery that will not trouble
anybody. The established forces are
concealed, but are 'ideally expressed in truth in
itself' (97). Philosophers personally tend
to be a 'a thoroughly civil and pious character',
happily fitting in two existing culture and
morality. Even science fails to really offer
critique, since after judging the powers of the
world, it tends to sanction them as truth.
A new image of thought would not pursue this sort
of truth, but would focus on sense and value,
trying to identify the noble and the base, and the
forces that they express. This goes beyond
the notion of truth and falsehood, because there
are different source of truths, and even higher
thoughts might contain falsehood, indeed use it,
as with art, to become affirmative, something that
'becomes true in the work of art'. We also
have to abandon simple notions of error as well,
which clearly depend on some absolute notion of
truth, and which somehow express the worst aspect
of thought. Nietzsche says that philosophers
often use extremely simple examples to try to
illustrate this notion of error, as something
arising from simple stupidity. However,
stupidity is a full aspect of thought, 'it
expresses the nonsense in thought by right' [which
means, I think, the assumption that correct,
dogmatic thought achieves truth by right --if so,
there should be no errors]. Stupidity has
its own truth, the truth 'of a leaden soul'.
Thought based on reactive forces displays its own
kind of stupidity, which appears this time as a
symptom of an ignoble way of thinking.
Nietzsche uses this analysis to oppose dominant
thoughts of his time.
We have to accept pluralism and a typology of
truth, locating truth and error to particular
types of knowing, and asking who it was who
formulated such knowing. We have to suspect
the base in the notion of truth, and the high in
the notion of falsehood. This is the purpose
of philosophy. It is supposed to 'sadden'
people, exposing any kind of baseness in thought,
criticizing all mystification, demonstrating the
complicity between victims and perpetrators, and
becoming active and affirmative, even if
aggressive. The point is to create free men
who are not domesticated by culture, state or
religion. We have to identify and combat
ressentiment and bad conscience and its role in
thought. Philosophy does not always succeed,
but it has stopped things getting worse.
Philosophy itself has become mystified. We see
this in the caricature of critique associated with
the dogmatic image of thought, but it starts the
first time that philosophy attempts to relate to
the established powers. The classical
philosophers avoided this, and became
'comets'. The philosopher is constantly
domesticated as a sage, an uncritical friend of
existing wisdom and truth. But truth must be
dismembered as was Dionysus, partitioned according
to sense and value. This kind of philosophy
must be constantly revived in each epoch. We
must see that terms like stupidity or baseness are
always related to a particular time, our
contemporaries, and the same goes with error, even
though that poses as atemporal. This is why
philosophy is always marked by time, always
against the current times, as critique, with
concepts that are untimely, not of the
present. This opposition is crucial.
The kind of truth presented by the untimely is
'truths of times to come' (100). The
succession of philosophers is not some 'eternal
sequence of sages' or historical development, but
a series of comets, marked by a 'discontinuity and
repetition', between the eternity of the sky and
the historicity of the earth. Thinking is
never just an actual exercise of some faculty, nor
does it precede somehow on its own: rather it
depends on forces which affect thought, sometimes,
with reactive forces, to constrain it. Once
thinking becomes thought, it can be occupied by
reactive forces, and the 'fictions' crucial to
reactive thought become elements of it, preventing
proper thought. Nietzsche thinks we should
be awaiting the forces and power capable of
affirmative thought. Thinking itself is not
a natural exercise but 'an event in thought
itself, for thought itself' (101) [in less fancy
terms, actual thinking is conditioned by the
existing structure of thought]. Thinking could
become particularly light and affirmative, but it
must be forced to do so, by a perception of
violence having been done to it, forcing it to be
active. These activities, forcing thought to
be active, are found in culture, which Nietzsche
sees as a matter of training and selection.
We can see the dynamic aspects of culture by
comparing it to method. Whereas method
'always presupposes the goodwill of the thinker,
"a premeditated decision"', culture shows the
violence undergone by thought, something
selective, a training which awakens the
unconscious. The Greeks had this sense of
thoughts being activated not by goodwill but by
force being exercised on them. This explains
some of the strange passages in Nietzsche about
punishment and force as necessary components in
developing thinkers, and that tyrannical laws are
more effective than schooling. Deleuze says
these texts are ironical, designed to tease
the Germans for thinking of themselves as a
rational nation of thinkers, but this is an irony
turning on the claims about cultural developments,
how the Greeks turned into the Germans.
Violent elements produce people who do not confine
thought to the existing state, whereas the good
works of churches and states produce martyrs,
always with the needs of the state in mind.
The church and state harness the violence of
cultural change and turn it into reactive force,
[possibly] under the illusion that they are simply
managing violence [if so, we are close to the
themes of Anti
Oedipus here, with people designing
their own repression and so on]. As a
result, culture is turned into something reactive
itself, something limiting thought, making people
even more stupid, cultural degeneration, and
Nietzsche sees this as a historical theme [I still
think Adorno and
Horkheimer are much better].
At least we can see that images of thoughts imply
a complex relation of forces, which in turn
depends on the typology of forces. As
before, typology depends on topology [the division
between noble and base]. Present
circumstances produce particular kinds of thinking
so 'we have the truths that we deserve'
(102). There are no non-cultural origins of
truth. We only think outside of cultural
constraints when we are forced to do so, when we
are forced to become active and affirmative: this
requires not a method but a particular cultural
conjuncture [a paideia, which I have seen
defined as a broad character-forming kind of
education leading to maturity, something which
transcends the instrumental elements in
culture]. Method involves avoidance and
escape from confronting the real issues [the
metaphor here is the thread in the labyrinth – I
would've thought this is a pretty useful form of
escape, which makes it a rather unfortunate
metaphor]. Thinking has to be suited to the
place, the time and the particular elements [of
force?]. Great thinkers use aphorism and
anecdote, usually to refer to extreme places or
extreme times, not to temperate moderate zones nor
to the 'moral, methodical or moderate man' (103).
Chapter four. From Ressentiment to the
Bad Conscience
Normally, reactive forces hinder action, by
delaying it or dividing it, but they can also
produce a burst of creativity in order to adjust,
a riposte, and again this relation is
normal. This means that ressentiment is not
just simple reaction, rather that it leads to no
compensating action: the former response is the
rare one [Deleuze for some absurd reason sees
'normal' as involving '"normative" and "rare"'
(105)]. We can turn to Freud to understand
this, with his notion of the "topical hypothesis",
where one system receives some stimulation, but
another system retains a trace of it, assuming
that recording a transformation limits receptivity
to fresh stimulation. These two systems can
correspond to the conscious and the unconscious,
implying that the unconscious retains memories,
while the conscious is the one that acts at the
boundary between the outside and inside, like a
kind of skin, developing its capacities to
respond. Although Freud had subsequent
doubts, this is what is going on in Nietzsche,
also using terms conscious and unconscious.
The reactive unconscious is the one that stores
lasting imprints in a form of digestion or
rumination. Reactive forces attach
themselves to these imprints, but this can never
be the only mechanism because adaptation is also
required, which provides a reaction to present
stimulations, and this one features reactive
forces in the conscious. Nietzsche sees the
conscious as only a limited area of human thought,
and sees it as wholly reactive, but it is slightly
better than unconscious reaction, because at least
it's more transparent [maybe, or at least the only
one linked to action?].
However, the two systems have to be kept separate,
and traces must not interfere with consciousness:
the fluidity and mobility of consciousness must be
retained. This happens through the 'faculty
of forgetting' (106). Unlike Freudian
psychology, forgetting here is not seen as a
negative operation, but something active and
positive, not just inertia, but more a matter of
absorption, even repression. There is thus
an immediate conscious reaction to stimulation,
and an imperceptible trace of it in the
unconscious. And forgetting also has the
positive function of helping us see happiness or
hope in the present. Forgetting is a kind of
guard keeping the two systems apart, with a purely
functional activity, and energized by reactive
forces [there's even a suggestion that this
unconscious energy is transferred to the
conscious, 106 -- all very Freudian I
think]. If humans have the capacity to
forget damaged in some way, they can never '"have
done" with anything'[citing Genealogy],
and consciousness is absorbed by the traces of the
unconscious and overrun. Indeed, as soon as
we become conscious of these traces, we can no
longer act out reactive forces [that is, the ones
presented to our consciousness?]. This helps
[old] reactive forces prevail, and action [in the
present] is limited [sounds like a basis for
current notions of mindfulness, being in the
present]. The result is a triumph for
reactive forces over active: is not just a matter
of greater force, more that forgetting is no
longer able to draw energy from reactive forces,
and the only reaction is between old and present
reactive forces. A kind of modulation takes
place, where some forces are supplemented, and
others destroyed, in the form of a 'strange
subterranean struggle' (107), going on entirely
between reactive forces but with the implications
for activity. We can now define ressentiment
as a reaction which becomes perceptible but which
is drained of energy and can no longer lead to
action, the concept of sickness in general: thus
ressentiment is a form of [wasting] sickness [a
pretty good description of depression based on
endless reworkings of past stressful events].
So again we have a topological model based on
reactive forces and how they interact in the
relation of dominance. The man of
ressentiment is dominated by memory traces
saturating these consciousness. There is,
luckily, a more active memory too [below?].
A typology of ressentiment follows, one type is
when reactive forces prevail over active ones,
with one symptom being 'a prodigious memory'
(108). This type is 'a reality which is
simultaneously biological, psychical, historical,
social and political' (108). It looks as if
this happens almost by accident, as a result of
strong experiences which are overwhelming, and
which lead to a general notion of revenge.
However, we must not see this exclusively in
quantitative terms, and there are particularly
strong relations between some forces and some
subjects, as in Nietzsche's types. There's
no need to have experienced something
overwhelming, nor any need to generalize.
There is no such energetic reaction, rather a more
endless feeling that substitutes for action, one
which blames its object. Strong excitation
can be beautiful and good, even for the resentful:
the issue is whether it becomes a matter for
'personal offence and affront'. The object
is blamed because it can produce no other reaction
but the effect of a trace in the memory, 'a
qualitative or typical [constituting a type]
powerlessness'. The more effect it has, the
more it tends to produce offence, and in this
sense beauty and goodness can be as equally
outrageous as pain. Nothing can penetrate
the system. Consciousness itself becomes
hardened. The memory stores more and more
traces of hatred in itself. Only the object
can be blamed. This is why revenge becomes
imaginary or symbolic. Freud and Nietzsche
share an interest in the relation between the
anal/digestive and sadism, as in Nietzsche's
'intestinal and venomous memory'(109), or the
poisonous spider. What these thoughts also
reveal is an attempt to rework psychology, to turn
it into a typology of subjects [Deleuze uses an
expression referring to putting psychology 'on the
plane of the subject' and says, in a note, that
Jung was on to this in his denunciation of
Freudian objectivism, 198]. The only
possible cure is to transform the type.
The resentful develop a clear spirit of revenge,
and 'spirit' here refers to the means for
revenge. It is not just a strong desire for
revenge, but because the reactive forces are
incapable of action, the only form of revolt is
spiritual. This is the only way the weak can
triumph, and introduce a new type of their own:
they triumph by harboring a prodigious
memory. Other characteristics follow.
The resentful cannot admire, respect or love
because hatred dominates everything. Self
reproach is really a form of reproaching the
person who's supposed to be cherished. This
is why self abasement and modesty is
'frightening', because it conceals hatred.
The same goes for 'buffoonery or base
interpretations', for ever seeing traps to be
avoided in things, [including refusing a battle of
wits, which could describe Deleuze himself],
permanent malevolence and disparagement, even
addressed to friends or enemies. This
reduces things, even misfortune, to matters of
blame—everything is someone's fault. This is
not at all like a healthier aristocratic
indifference to fate.
Ressentiment is also a narcotic leading to
passivity, which in Nietzsche means something
which is not acted rather than not active.
Passivity shows the triumph of reaction, the
moment at which reactive forces become
internalized. The resentful are impotent,
frigid, insomniac, touchy, wanting compensation,
and hence 'the man of profits and gain' (110): the
system of profit and gain which dominates society
shows the imposition of ressentiment. The
only crime becomes one of failing to recognize
profit [it is even a crime against the spirit for
theology]. Slaves adopt this morality of
utility, which includes judging things on the
basis of good and evil. Even the 'incredible
notion of disinterestedness' (111) conceals an
interest, and in fact is a form of praise for a
third party who enables an actor to benefit.
Utilitarianism itself has such a standpoint, some
passive third party who regulates interactions,
really representing 'the triumphant standpoint of
the slave who intervenes between masters'.
This perpetual accusation replaces
aggression. It becomes a goal in itself, so
that everything disappoints. There is a
particularly 'dreadful feminine power' here, which
blames partners for failure and misfortune.
The resentful want everyone else to be evil so
that they can appear good, a display of the
essential characteristics of the type. It
leads to the denunciation of the strong as
necessarily evil, an inversion of values for
Nietzsche responding to the need for slaves to
have someone who is eternally evil to blame.
So the system that argues that someone else is
evil therefore we are good can be spelled out
using 'the method of dramatization', asking who it
is who might be making these statements. The
implication is that there is no single notion of
good, because what is good for one is evil for the
other, so no agreed semeiology or axiology is
available. Dramatization involves pluralism
and immanence. Anyone claiming just to be
good would be acting affirmatively and joyfully,
revealing some quality of the soul, the certainty
that only noble souls possess. Nietzsche
uses the term 'distinction' to refer to this
affirmative character, which is just automatically
acted upon or enjoyed: it even implies,
etymologically, someone who is real, actual
and true [is this 'good', or 'distinction'?],
implying that only people who act have a real
existence, and possess reality. In this way,
people claiming to be good are also claiming to be
able to create values. Such people feel
power and happiness, a kind of wealth that can be
distributed. They are to be contrasted with
all that is 'low minded common and
plebeian'[citing Nietzsche Genealogy].
Nietzsche sees this as [disconnected from social
or political interests], offering just a typology
or an ethic of living, something that naturally
follows from the claims to be good, something
which affirms aristocracy in the full sense: what
is evil is actually of little importance, existing
just to amplify the affirmative nature of the
good.
Claiming that someone else is evil therefore we
are good is quite different, beginning with a
negative premise, and allowing the positive only
to appear often negation. This is the
'strange syllogism of the slave'(113), invoking
two negations—just like the dialectic! This
makes the dialectic 'the ideology of
ressentiment'[a highly suspicious deduction]. The
slave's values are created from this
negativity. They also involve negating
action of the masterly kind. This requires
subordinating every action to the standpoint of
the one who does not act, the one who faces the
consequences, or to one of those mysterious third
parties who are the ultimate judges of
intentions. This is how the conventional
notions of good and evil arise, and how they lead
to moral judgment. What looks good according
to the masters' ethics of life becomes the evil of
morality. This is why conventional notions
of good and evil are inverted and based on
passivity and denial, although they appear as
divine and transcendent. They conceal hatred
for life. Religion follows this negative
syllogism too, which makes its positivity
misleading. The religious have invented 'the
good weakling: there is no better revenge against
the strong and happy' (114). This is the
judaic legacy of ressentiment which goes over into
Christianity, and Christian love is actually based
on it. [This looks like it's heading towards
a depressive entirely negative eternally
remembered ressentiment of Christianity itself].
The whole argument also conceals parologism [in
the sense of mimicking logic?]. The problem
lies in the middle premise, where an opposition
with the master is taken to be a guarantee of
possessing of the opposite value, of being
good. If we assume that what the master does
is the result of the abstract nature of events,
and not personal evil, the whole thing
falls. Because masters are seen as
responsible for their actions, so the weak feel
entitled to react. The whole argument
displays one of the classic fictions of an
abstract force independent of what it can
do. It is not enough to abstain from actions
like those of the master, but necessary to counter
the abstract force detected in it, and thus claim
some superiority. In this way reactive
forces appear as abstract and neutral notions of
force, something that can be countered, something
that can be divided into blameworthy or deserving
vectors. There's also a curious assumption
that more abstract force is required to abstain
from action, and this also provides reactive
forces with 'a contagious power'(115).
First, force is split into two, and the
manifestation of it is seen as an effect of the
force which is seen as a separate cause: this is a
convenient illusion in science, but it ignores 'a
real relation of significance'. Second
substantive force is projected onto a subject who
decides whether to manifest it or not, becoming
the act of the subject: for Nietzsche, this sort
of subject is a ' fiction or grammatical function'
(116). Thirdly, a force is seen as something
moral, because it is capable of not operating, and
this requires this projection on to the subject:
the weak in particular see their very weakness as
something meritorious [for Nietzsche it is
'natural'?].
Getting onto bad conscience, it can take two
forms, a 'raw' animal like form, and of form which
takes advantage of such content and gives it a
shape, just as topology shapes typology.
Ressentiment possesses these two aspects,
constituted in the unconscious first, then finding
form in typical characteristics of the kind we
have discussed, like revenge and perpetual
accusation, turning unconscious forces into things
that can oppose active ones and separate them from
[suitable, rational] objects [Nietzsche doesn't
seem to discuss active political revolt against
the strong as a rational outcome, of course.
Blimey, my prodigious memory has also dredged up
Merton's typology of possible responses to social
strain—revolt, retreat, anomie, conformism,
ritualism. While we are here, inversion also
looks like one of those prophetic ways in which
juvenile delinquents establish their 'own' values
in subcultures]. Once more, it is not just a
matter of quantity. Instead we have a
displacement of reactive forces [from conscious to
unconscious] which in turn separates forces from
what they can do. The displacement is
covered by a mystification ['reversal by
projection'(117)].
What seems to happen is that reactive forces
produce an inverted image of themselves, so that a
difference between reactive forces becomes a
definite opposition between reactive and
active. As this image is developed, so the
values corresponding to forces are inverted.
In this way reactive forces are projected and
become a fiction, developing a fictional relation
between God and [natural] life, for example, or
between the immediate and the 'super sensible'
[heavenly?] worlds. We have a difference
here from the active power of dreams or the
positive images of affirmative gods: the fiction
in question does not reflect reality but falsifies
and denies it [already covered under
'inversion']. We can now see how the
evolution of ressentiment develops, from the
separation of active forces from action [which
Deleuze calls falsification], from attributing
blame, and inverting the values of these
forces. Reactive forces come to appear
superior, capable of undermining all the movements
of life and beauty, and inventing instead a world
in which these movements seem evil.
The full development of ressentiment requires yet
another stage, arising from having 'an artist in
fiction'[a type again?], and again we have to
establish who is responsible. The first
answer is 'the priest', especially the Jewish
priest, or at least one who has the 'judaic
form'(118), who uses dialectics to perform this
inversion. Divine love, taken up by
Christianity, emerges as the greatest
accomplishment of this inversion, 'the venomous
flower of an unbelievable hatred', something that
persuades the wretched that they are the only good
people, blessed by god. Without such a
person, slaves would remain in raw
ressentiment. The priest does not share the
goals of the slave exactly, but expresses his own
will to power, in the form of nihilism.
Nihilism is interdependent with reactive
forces. Deleuze insists that this is not
anti Semitism. Although the Nazis filtered
his work through their own interests, Nietzsche
himself had no truck with the then current
Bismarckian regime or with German anti Semitism,
which he saw as'" this shameless racial hoax"
[citing a letter to Fritsch, in which, apparently,
he explicitly attacks German anti Semitism].
He explicitly distanced Zarathustra from anti
Semitism [I have noted these occasional comments,
and given my own interpretation of them in my
notes on some of these books—my own view, for what
it is worth, is that Nietzsche does get
occasionally close to anti Semitism, even if it is
not the precise German kind]. Deleuze
explains that 'the Jewish question' had become a
topic for a great deal of discussion among
Hegelians, but that Nietzsche had his own
particular take on how judaic priests had been
affected by German history. There are racial
elements, says Deleuze, but only as an element of
'crossbreeding' [indeed -- a racist concept this
time] the development of a particular historical
social and political complex, a type. So
we're talking about the type of the priest [rather
similar to defenders of Marx who suggest that his
comments about Jews are also of comments about a
type of capitalist]. Actual Jews have a
positive role, [developed best of all in Beyond
Good and Evil, says Deleuze].
Ressentiment aims to separate active force from
its 'material conditions'[allegedly natural
associations with the aristocracy?]. It is a
fictitious separation, but it has real
consequences, of turning active force back against
itself, being interiorized. This is what
produces bad conscience, which continues the same
role as ressentiment. Ressentiment is some
sort of infection, concealing hatred under love,
spreading to other people disguised as joining
with them [or pitying them]. If successful,
the fortunate will also develop bad conscience
about their good fortune. This is the final
triumph of ressentiment, getting the accused to
admit their guilt and to blame themselves, to
introject active forces, to produce another type
of bad conscience, residing in masters as well as
slaves. Active force in this case produces
pain and suffering, and even magnifies them in a
'squalid workshop' (120).
Pain is given an extra dimension which multiplies,
some inward dimension that follows from seeing
pain as the result of sin, and also as a way of
redeeming sin. Here we have the full
development of bad conscience as guilt, a
typological innovation. This involves
understanding that pain is connected with the
issue of existence, the possibility of acting,
appearing as an external constraint on
action. The strong have always understood
that the only meaning of pain is in gaining
pleasure at the expense of someone else.
This is recognized in Greek culture as the
edifying pleasure the gods get in seeing [human?]
evil, such as the trojan wars which acted as a
festival for the gods. Seeing pain as
something that constrains existence results from
reactive thinking, sometimes an excessive
identification with the one who suffers, or the
passive one, and this is an identification with
ressentiment. Pain should be seen instead as
a stimulant to life, inflicting suffering as an
'active manifestation of life'(121).
Nietzsche notes that cruelty was a major feature
of the leisure activities and festivals of former
times. It must be the internal dimension of
pain that causes us to suffer, and we can only
resolve it by manufacturing more pain, internalize
and you more, turning it from one of life's
[Dionysian] tragedies into something personal [and
therefore base and trivial?]. Again a priest is
needed to perform this evolution, especially a
Christian priest in this case: they urge us to
internalize pain, and connect it to sin, making it
more than just some raw animal experience.
This is achieved by altering the direction of
ressentiment, finding something outside to focus
upon as a cause, something or someone other.
However, the explosive nature of ressentiment also
needs to be channeled, and this is accomplished by
coming to blame oneself, through a bad conscience
and guilt: this is achieved through the invention
of sin.
Christianity completes the project of Judaism
here. St. Paul is particularly influential
as a 'spiteful character', and the new testament
clearly shows its base origins. Even the
death of Christ is worked back into the scheme,
and the connection between Christian love and hate
is disguised by JC's death and sacrifice:
'the truth that Pontius Pilate discovered [ecce
homo?] remains hidden'(123). However,
Christianity has one element which it adds to
Judaism, in that it changes the direction of
ressentiment to produce the bad conscience.
This does not diminish the force of ressentiment,
but adds something to it. In particular,
ressentiment can now be appeased by being spread
to others and to entire lives: it only works if
everyone feels guilty, including the strong, in a
'dreary refrain'. This is how the priest
becomes a master. In terms of philosophical
implications, this can be read as an attack on the
dialectic, replacing antitheses and oppositions by
differences and correlations: Hegel's unhappy
consciousness is a mere symptom of bad
conscience. We have a story of a two stage
development both of ressentiment and of bad
conscience, both involving the priest and the
particular fictions that he specializes in.
However, culture is also implicated.
Culture means both training and selection, and its
morality is contained in its customs, and its
violence. However, it turns into domination
by one group, 'people, race or class' (124) [how
is the question] , and thus it always has an
arbitrary or limited element, it is always
reactive. However, there's always something
that appears to go beyond arbitrary rule, a
certain active force, something that expresses
generic humanity. These two aspects must be
distinguished genealogically, even if they are
confused concretely. Nietzsche thinks that
primitive societies featured the domination of
custom, something generic, which preceded history
as such. That appears as the need to obey
laws [Deleuze links to Bergson
on the natural tendency to develop habit].
However, the whole point of socializing
['training'] people is to get them to act out
reactive forces, through the imposition of habits
and models. However, certain aspects of the
unconscious, including the dubious physiological
stuff about digestion, are attacked by culture,
since the main role of culture is to train the
consciousness, including the ability to forget and
be consistent [through being internalized, but not
in a nasty way]. This is a future oriented
commitment, a matter of 'promising commitment to
the future'(125) [presumably, some memory of
freedom which is projected into the future as
well, or seen as inherent in humanity, waiting to
be realized]. In this way culture also
produces free powerful and active men, those who
promise a better future [a charismatic?].
Culture has always been connected to violence,
both to train reactive forces, and to
constrain them, as well as making memory
particularly vivid [!]. The early notion of
justice involved clear punishment to compensate
for any injury caused, and this restored human
relations [if it was redemptive, that is, and did
not develop into murder or blood feuds]. We
also see the early emergence of the notion of debt
and credit [as in 'payback']. All these
eventually help produce active people [and nasty
utilitarian ascetics, as we saw].
So far, we've not really explained the emergence
of bad conscience or ressentiment.
Certainly, they did not originate with conceptions
of justice, as their exponents claim. For
the moralizer, justice is secondary, the result of
the reaction to offence. This is
unsatisfactory, however, since it is not clear how
some just retribution will satisfy pain, the
desire for revenge. The whole equation
between pain and injury only works if we include
the pleasure in inflicting pain, or contemplating
it, some external meaning of pain. But that
is a legacy of an active standpoint, where
reactive forces train people to pursue
pleasure. Reactive forces do not lead to
action or the search for pleasure. They
represent the last area which can be conquered by
the spirit of justice. The same goes with
bad conscience. Punishment can never make
culprits feel guilty, and often has the opposite
effect. In early societies, punishment
indeed hindered the effect of guilt.
Something else must develop before human beings
can feel themselves to blame for active
forces. The same goes for those gloriously
free 'sovereign individuals' [sic] who are
produced by the triumphs of culture: they consider
themselves liberated from morality and custom, not
in debt in some way. The responsible and
moral man is not to be confused with these free
people. Free individuals will assume power
over themselves, as well as over the law: they
will be irresponsible, they will not have to
answer, they will be liberated from feelings of
debt and from the claims of masters to manage
them. Nietzsche argues that this means the
individual emerges at the expense of the species.
This evolution of culture displays the eventual
superiority of active forces over reactive ones,
but, in the middle, the reactive forces triumph,
as we can see from looking at actual history
[rather than pursuing this idealized notion of
what culture must deliver]. Culture is
perverted by history. History shows us the
process is of the degeneration of culture, where
various groups, including churches and states,
somehow stand for the species. They are
reactive forces, falsified as species
forces. Another collectivity formed by this
activity is the herd. This society does not
wish to self destruct and usher in a future.
[nearly sociology!]. The whole comes to
stand for particular contents, reactive
ones. The domesticated man is the goal, not
the sovereign individual, the sick, mediocre and
gregarious man. The violence of culture gets
associated with the property of people and
organizations. Violence continues, but in
order to domesticate human beings: the strong are
domesticated as much as the weak. Selection
now becomes an activity to reproduce the reactive
life.
This is no accident, but an inherent tendency in
history, its 'principle and meaning' (130).
We see this in the disappointment about how the
Greeks become Germans, and also through a symbol
in Zarathustra: the fire dog, which comes to stand
for species activity, the relation of human beings
to the earth. But this refers to
domesticated men and deformed species activity
serving reactive forces. Zarathustra rebukes
the dog for defending these institutions
masquerading as self important representatives of
the species. Another fire dog is required,
symbolizing species activity in pre history: this
explains why Nietzsche is so keen on the Greek
notions of culture [very clear in his work on the need for
classical education – strangely, this work
is not cited specifically anywhere in
Deleuze. Maybe it is included in one of the
other editions?]. All this stuff about the
two aspects of culture might only be one of
Zarathustra's visions? Can we separate
culture from history? Is species activity a
suitable clear idea? [we could never know it
even if it was, of course because we cannot undo
the effects of our own history]. Have we not
already argued that human beings are essentially
reactive, which makes it difficult to see how an
active person could appear – Deleuze promises
answers below. Well—narrative
tension!]. There is a clue [in Untimely
Meditations, apparently] that becoming
suitable for service to society is always
ambiguous, particularly in the ways in which
reactive forces themselves can produce a kind of
activity, in the development of ressentiment and
bad conscience. In this way, reactive forces
can come to pose as species activity [no different
really from the formation of the other fictions
and illusions discussed above. A good
discussion of ideology covers most of it, say
Marcuse on the various devices like the
'technological veil', or the reduction of needs to
one dimension; or Habermas
on distorted communication]. The normal
social processes like cultural training are then
used to develop reactive conceptions.
So again reactive forces split activity from
active forces, this time by projecting concepts of
debts on to them, and engineer some relationship
with other reactive forces in a 'a complex
association' (131) [we could even call this a mode
of production]. The projected section even
comes to set itself up as a judge. Debt
itself widens to involve debts to divinity or
society, it becomes inexhaustible and
'unpayable'(132). In the example of
Christian redemption, it is not discharged but
deepened, and becomes lifelong [nicely discussed
in Genealogy].
People internalize suffering and feel guilty about
debt: no human being could ever repay the debt
incurred through God's sacrifice. What might
be seen as normal forms of debt and responsibility
originate from activity in culture, and it can
disappear or be discharged, with pain playing a
role. But when those forms grow from
ressentiment and become part of culture, they
change direction, becoming internalized.
In particular, first reactive forces bring into
creation associations which are diversions from
creative activity, such as herds. Second,
bad conscience emerges in this context, so that
debt is no longer an aspect of species activity,
but becomes connected to 'reactive association'
(133). It also becomes unpayable, and
associated with internal guilt: this is one way in
which the original tendency to blame others
becomes a tendency to blame ourselves as unworthy
in the face of the church or God. Thirdly,
priests actively organize associations like the
herd, and invent ways in which we can internalize
and endure guilt and pain. They invent a new
kind of community and invite us to join.
This can help reduce ressentiment, but only by
discharging it towards others: the whole system
becomes contagious, and the men of bad conscience
find satisfaction in recruiting others by making
them feel guilty.
Nietzsche might be working with two or even
several types of religion, and not all of them are
essentially linked with ressentiment. The
cult of Dionysus, for example is associated with
the opposite sense, of lightness, with
affirmation. Everything depends on the
forces which take possession of religion.
The religion of the strong is selective and
educative. If only we could separate Christ
as a personal type from Christianity, we could see
him as affirmative. Different types of
religion are also associated with different
quantities and qualities of force, and these
develop an affinity with particular forms of
religion. Religions can even ally
themselves to different forces as they
develop. This is the normal state of
religion, to be determined by external forces,
including the actions of philosophers. The
life of Christ is such an example, rapidly
dominated by a force that minimizes the actual
feeling of divinity. As religions gain
powers of their own, they always have to pay the
price of borrowing 'a mask to survive'(134).
St. Paul is more important in the development of
Christianity than Christ. This provides the
essential link between religion and bad conscience
and ressentiment: the latter are reactive forces
which manage to colonize religion as a way of
escaping from the domination of active forces.
They develop in an increasingly religious form as
religion itself becomes socially important.
The very development of religion shows that it is
not just driven by reactive forces, that it must
incorporate some kind of will, discussed in the
form of the ascetic ideal. Asceticism was
always present, feeding on ressentiment and bad
conscience, but as it develops, it mixes the two,
and also shows how reactive forces can become
livable [just like Weber on the Protestant Ethic],
in what turns out to be 'the fundamental
complicity' between reactive forces and a
particular form of the will to power. Even
so,[ ideological] fictions are required to
strengthen this complicity, such as 'the fiction
of the world beyond' (135), and this one happens
to be good at combining a number of other
fictions. Similarly, the will to nothingness
needs some sort of force behind it, the reactive
forces, something which helps it react to the good
life. Both the will and these forces are
required, and both might survive had they not
become allied, but in a very different way.
Asceticism is the key.
This typology draws upon psychological metaphors
of depths or caves, developing a theory of the
unconscious 'which ought to be compared to the
whole of Freudianism'. However, Nietzsche
does not just deal with psychology, since the type
is biological and sociological etc, and he also
wants to include 'metaphysics and the theory of
knowledge' (138) to develop a fully fledged
philosophy to reject the old metaphysics and
transcendentalism, and found itself on genealogy
instead. Psychological readings
misunderstand this: wills to power do not have
motives; nor is genealogy just a philosophical
genesis.
[And there is this lovely table below, pages 136,
137]. [Deleuze has certainly done his best
to systematize Nietzsche's ramblings]
Chapter five. The Overman: Against the
Dialectic
Nihilism means not nothing, but having a value of
nil. This can only be achieved by a fiction, one
that separates one aspect of life and sees it as
opposed to life itself, something unreal, an
appearance, valueless. In particular,
there's a connection with the ideal of another
superior world, superior to life: inevitably this
means 'the depreciation of life, the negation of
the [this] world'(139). It is not that these
higher values leave behind human will, rather that
they offer a will to deny: this is the nothingness
of the will, originally a concept in
Schopenhauer. It remains a will.
Nihilism negates the [affirmative] will to power,
reducing its value to nil. Nihilism in a
more colloquial sense means a reaction to
something, even to the superior world and its
values, to higher values themselves: here, having
values is seen as valueless! This occurs
when we see behind apparently higher values,
denying God, or any other form of the
supersensible. All will is negated, life
becomes tedious and pointless. This second
sense actually belongs to the first one as well,
because the first one began to devalue life, and
this depreciated life now continues in a world
without any values or purpose. Essence was
once opposed to appearance and life became an
appearance, but now essence is denied, leaving
nothing but appearances [sounds like
Baudrillard]. Nietzsche calls this the
"'pessimism of weakness"'(140), ending in a
completely reactive life. If the first kind
of nihilism can be seen as 'a negative nihilism',
the second kind is 'a reactive nihilism'.
The will to nothingness allows the full triumph of
the reactive forces, and life itself becomes
reactive and unreal. But reactive forces
still need life providing the energy to
continually deny and contradict [a strange bit
says that life becomes a witness or even a
leader]. However, life is increasingly
threatened in case it sparks some alternative to
reactive forces, and this, in effect, makes the
reactive forces separate even from the negative
will, and attempt to replace it. It is
better to have total stagnation, strength without
will, and for life to fade away passively.
'Passive nihilism' [a third type] triumphs in the
end, ushered in by reactive nihilism. We see this
in the remarks about God. He is dead, but he
died of pity, almost of weariness, or sometimes is
killed by vengeful human beings who resented such
an omnipresent witness.
Pity involves tolerance for a 'state of life close
to zero' (141), for the life of the weak and the
sick. It validates the final victory of the
poor. Humans feel pity only if they need a
reactive life themselves, like those who turn it
into a religion. Pity always combines the
will to nothingness and reactive forces, so it is
'"practical nihilism"' (142) [especially in The
Antichrist, apparently]. It disguises
itself, of course, by appearing to obey higher
values. If humans adopt pity as their major
value, they can put themselves in God's place, and
ressentiment becomes atheistic [although still a
rather Christian form of it]. In Zarathustra,
the ugliest man is the one who kills god, the most
reactive. However, there's at least a liberating
consequence of killing god, in taking
responsibility for one's own destiny, being better
as a human fool than a religious one. It
might be better to have no values rather than a
nothingness of will, better to fade away.
This passivity will follow the death of God, said
the 'prophet of weariness' [in Zarathustra].
The 'last man' shows the option of having no will,
living in a single herd, no rulers, no herdsman.
This does not happen all at once, and there are
some intermediate stages. The reactive life
hangs on for a long time trying to perpetuate its
own values, which include social and community
values, which, so exponents think, will lead to
happiness. This seems to vindicate those who
think that some kind of god will always be needed
[Heidegger is mentioned explicitly, but this might
apply to Durkheim too]. The reactive life of
religious periods is prolonged, and it requires
some supersensible authority. Eventually,
the second stage arises, turning against any
superior values. Then the exhausted life,
not willing at all, content to fade passively,
completely reduced to a reactive form. In
all the stages, the nihilistic perspective is
prominent: indeed, for Nietzsche, nihilism is 'the
motor of the history of man as universal history'
(143). We find it following the same stages
in Judaism leading to Christianity, leading to
democratic and socialist ideology, and ending with
the last man.
We now need to discuss the famous section about god
being dead. In the first place, saying
that he is dead puts god into 'time, becoming,
history and man' (144), as synthesis, arguing that
once god must have existed but now he's dead --
'and he will rise from the dead'. If god is
to be synthesized like this, his death is an
obvious component. Indeed, life and death
themselves are traced to the synthesis 'with or in
the idea of god'. It also raises important
questions like who has killed god, and how did he
die. Several options are possible:
First, we can look at the problem from the point
of view of 'negative nihilism: the moment of the
Judaic and Christian consciousness'. Here,
god expresses the will to nothingness and the
depreciation of life, since he exists entirely in
the beyond. This glorifies the reactive
life, and leads to the Judaic notion of
ressentiment, after the 'golden age of the Kings
of Israel'. Anything universal appears as a
hatred of life, prompting the opposite view that
what is particular is pro life, but sick and
reactive. These inner connections are
hidden. The first stage is to see the Jewish
god killing his own son to make him independent of
himself, and also of Jewish doctrine—a first
notion of the death of god. This helps god
be reconstrued as a god of love, preferring to
'suffer from hate'. The independence
involved in the crucifixion makes god universal
and cosmopolitan [sounds like borrowed Hegel
here]. On the cross, god ceases to be a
jew. The old god dies and a new one is
born. The crucified god insists his father
is a god of love. This means that we can
love Jesus rather than hating god, as long as we
believe in him. This disguises the 'hateful
premises' of the reactive life. [Very
convoluted stuff]. St. Paul develops these
ideas and makes them central to Christianity as
such, via the gospels, 'a grandiose falsification'
(145), and insists that Christ died for us, as a
redemption of our sins and the unpayable debt we
owed to god. We are therefore necessarily
guilty, and constant self rebuke and guilt
prolongs the debt. As a result, 'the whole
of life becomes reactive', it is resurrected as
reactive. St. Paul again connects these
notions to the notion of an afterlife, where love
and the reactive life will be reconciled. It
is for our sake that all this happens. For
this reason, St. Paul needed Jesus to die on the
cross, and be resurrected. Ressentiment is
hidden, and diverted into bad conscience.
Universal love is the principle, and undying
hatred the consequence, to be directed at anyone
who resists.
Second, we can examine the implications from the
point of view of reactive nihilism: 'the moment of
European consciousness'(146). The will to
nothingness and the reactive life are synthesized
in a different way. One unintended
consequence is that if we are to be blamed for
putting god to death, there must be some
possibility for atheism, and for the ascent of
'the reactive Man instead of God'. This is
the European man, who killed god again, in the
guise of the ugly man. The reactive life
itself cannot tolerate even god and his pity, and
assumes him to be really defunct. There is
no resurrection, no connection with divine will,
but a displacement of god altogether, and the
triumph of reactive man. 'God is suffocated
by the ungrateful one whom he loves too much'.
Third, from the point of view of passive nihilism:
'the moment of Buddhist consciousness'.
Christ assumes a different form from the one
depicted in St. Paul, a 'personal type'. We
can get to this through the massive contradiction
of the gospel for Nietzsche. The true Christ
brings glad tidings, abolishing the idea of sin,
ressentiment and revenge and a refusal of war, the
kingdom of god on earth, and the acceptance of
death. Christ comes to resemble
Buddha. His intention was to let the
reactive life fade away, into passivity. The
old reactive life at least had a certain nobility,
with men considering whether they could replace
god [the last man]. Jesus offered a gentle
decadence into passivity, but this was so far
ahead of its time, that the whole death of Christ
had to be falsified, moved backwards into reactive
nihilism, mixed with paganism [says
Nietzsche]. Proper Buddhism is appropriate
to a fatigued civilization, but there was no
civilization in the west, and it had to be
established first, by violence, before it could
progress to its final end. Christianity
could indeed become a kind of European Buddhism,
but there are still periods of violence to come,
progress through all the stages of nihilism, 'the
result of a long and terrible politics of
revenge'.
There are actually substantial differences with
Hegel. Nietzsche sees no world significance
in the death of god, and thinks the potential is
yet to be realized, and will depend on various
combinations of forces: it is not a matter of
waiting for the immanent meaning in an event to
unfold. In particular, there will be no
reconciliation of man and god, even after a number
of intermediate forms. The relevant forces
will have to be given time to form up, and bring
meaning from the outside, and these are not just
mere appearances of inner dialectical
forces. The intermediate forms and the
claims made for them are only symptoms: we need to
ask which particular subject, which notion of
infinite are being invoked, and what the will is
that is driving it. Hegelian dialectic does
not penetrate to this interpretive level, and
explains changes and developments at the
superficial level instead, or as some 'abstract
permutation where the subject becomes predicate
and the predicate, subject' (148). This
provides little interpretation, in favor of some
eternality [combinatory, we might call it] [I must
say I think Marxist dialectic is harder to
criticize on these grounds, although Althusser's
version of it has been]. The abstract logic
of opposition and contradiction substitutes for
awareness of 'the real element' which produces
forces. [We then leap to Deleuze's old
conclusion in Difference
and Repetition ] difference produces
events, with opposition 'as mere appearance'
(149). With Nietzsche we have typological
and topological differences.
We see the difference in comparing Nietzsche's bad
conscience with Hegel's unhappy
consciousness. [I found a bit of Hegel's
Phenomenology of Mindrff on the Web
which defines it thus:
In Stoicism,
self-consciousness is the bare and simple
freedom of itself. In Skepticism, it realizes
itself, negates the other side of determinate
existence, but, in so doing, really doubles
itself, and is itself now a duality. In this way
the duplication, which previously was divided
between two individuals, the lord and the
bondsman, is concentrated into one. Thus we have
here that dualizing of self-consciousness within
itself, which lies essentially in the notion of
mind; but the unity of the two elements is not
yet present. Hence the Unhappy Consciousness.
The Alienated Soul which is the consciousness of
self as a divided nature, a doubled and merely
contradictory being. This unhappy consciousness,
divided and at variance within itself, must,
because this contradiction of its essential
nature is felt to be a single consciousness,
always have in the one consciousness the other
also; and thus must be straightaway driven out
of each in turn, when it thinks it has therein
attained to the victory and rest of unity. Its
true return into itself, or reconciliation with
itself, will, however, display the notion of
mind endowed with a life and existence of its
own, because it implicitly involves the fact
that, while being an undivided consciousness, it
is a double consciousness. It is itself the
gazing of one self-consciousness into another,
and itself is both, and the unity of both is
also its own essence; but objectively and
consciously it is not yet this essence
itself--is not yet the unity of both.]
[So both types are split, but
one by guilt and the other by inadequate
knowledge?]
The latter finds its meaning in the apparently
opposing forces, say between Christianity and
Judaism, but this opposition cannot be seen as
formative. It is only a symptom to be
interpreted. [I'm not sure that Hegel quote
above would support this, but there is no
definitive reading, of course]. Emphasizing
contradiction nieces important differences,
including genealogical ones. The 'labour of
the negative' is only an appearance of the
struggles between wills to power, and these
differences have been abstracted and then made
into some genetic law. The whole thing has
been made into fiction, and inevitably it offers a
fictional solution. Everything dialectic
includes fictions of various kinds, rendered as
moments of spirit. It is no good standing
this dialectic back on its head [ reference to
Marx as well as Feuerbach?], because the character
of the dialectic remains [needs much more
discussion in my view]. In particular,
accounts of social change and transformation are
always seen as 'permutations of abstract and
unreal terms'(149) [this is now looking a bit like
Rancière on
Marxism, although he wants to substitute concrete
hybrid struggles for class struggle.
Nietzsche wants to substitute hybrid forces?
If so, these are rapidly organized into
affirmative and negative types. A typology
is equally abstract for Rancière?]. The
dialectic fails to ask the basic question '" which
one?"'. Everything is assumed to run
according to preexisting principles heading
towards reconciliation.
After Feuerbach, man becomes god, and anthropology
replaces theology, but that still leaves a lot of
concrete [sociological work for me] work to do to
fill in these categories: indeed, the particular
needs to be separated from the universal.
The man for Feuerbach is still reactive man, the
slave, still seeing themselves as a form of god,
still needing god. God has not really
changed either, but remains divine, something
still 'manufacturing the slave' (150). It is
just that the intermediate terms have been left
out, or rather redistributed. The essential
categories of the reactive forces and will to
nothingness persist. Instead of proper
reconciliation, we have complicity between man and
god. This shows that the entire dialectic is
still contained within reactive forces, and that
it can only develop the kinds of nihilism
discussed above. Restoring man over god is
exactly like reactive nihilism. The
essential fictional dynamics of nihilism are
preserved. The only one who wills such
developments is the man of the unhappy
consciousness. 'The dialectic is the natural
ideology of ressentiment and bad
conscience'. Nihilism informs its
thoughts. It is still ' a fundamentally
Christian way of thinking'[Hindess
and Hirst say the same of any 'two level'
argument]. The death of god still happens
within reactive forces and nihilism.
We can now consider the work of Stirner
(151f), who apparently did pursue the issue
of 'which one', and argued that if we are asking
who is man, we already have an answer to hand,
since we mean a specific man, not the essence of
man, which haunts the old dialectic [his critique
seems to be similar to the one we've just seen
about how hegelian dialectic leaves god
intact]. In Nietzsche's terms, even the ugly
man who kills god then becomes an object of pity
by Men.
At the speculative level, dialectic proceeds
through contradiction and resolution, and at the
practical level, through notions of alienation and
the suppression of alienation, or its
reappropriation. This reveals the petty
conservative nature of the dialectic, for Deleuze,
a matter of endless 'quibbling', disputing
properties and changing proprietors, exactly as in
ressentiment. Stirner has noticed these
qualities as well, suggesting that hegelian
freedom is always abstract, and this leaves room
for existing social relations [as in freedom
within the existing notions of property, I
think]. What is it that drives
reappropriation, however? For Hegel, it is
yet another alienated form, Objective Spirit, and
the same goes for Feuerbach and the notion of
'species being'. For Stirner, these notions
are as alienating as the ones in traditional
theology. They still refer to the alleged
properties of Man, and offer the only resolution
in terms of switching positions to become a
proprietor oneself. Reappropriation becomes
more and more limited, until it can be fully
reconciled with religion and the state. We
know that hegelian transformations always preserve
[even if they transcend]. For Feuerbach,
reappropriation 'is less reconciliation than
recuperation'(152), the human ownership of
formally transcendent properties, but the human
remains as an absolute being. Apparently,
Stirner goes so far as to deny even human essence,
and says there is no need to reconcile humanity
with anything, because it affects everything with
its own power and for its own enjoyment:
overcoming alienation means just annihilating
things which get in the way. The ego is finite in
Stirner, and every notion of higher essence above
humanity challenges this notion of unique selfhood
[which would stop human beings realizing their
power?]. Hegelian history ends in nihilism [not
Reason]. The dialectic cannot control
history, because it is seen to have a history of
its own which is out of its control. Stirner
comes these conclusions by pursuing his own
questions about the role of particular
individuals, even though he has to still use the
classic terms of the dialectic. At least he
sees that nihilism is the end, where everything is
overcome, although by an ego rather than Spirit.
This helps us discuss Marx and the German
Ideology. Marx wants to stop the final
stages of sliding into nihilism. He supports
['Saint Max'] Stirner on the dialectic as rooted
in the ego, not even the human species, but sees
Stirner's ego itself as 'the projection of
bourgeois egoism' (153), and goes on to talk about
the limits to the ego, the species, and the
particular social order that shapes species being
and egoism. Deleuze wonders if this is
enough, however, unless we definine which bits
belong to species and which bits to the individual
[surely accomplished in the actual analyses eg of
the commodity or labour] . Again the issue
is which one. Until we answer this question,
Marxism is merely the 'avatar before the nihilist
conclusion', the last proletarian stage. The
dialectic and history are still running down a
common slope. [An interesting critique, very
condensed, and worth another read].
Nietzsche evidently knew his Hegel and Stirner: we
can tell not by frequent quotations or the usual
[scholastic flourishes] but by 'apologetic or
polemical directions of his work itself'
(153). We must see the whole work as
directed against dialectical themes, especially
hegelian ones. Nietzsche is always attacking
German philosophy for preserving theological and
Christian elements, and thus succumbing to
nihilism, and how this will only end with reactive
conceptions of ego or man. The whole thing
is mystified, and needs to be subject to a
thorough analysis of its underlying values [in the
Nietzsche sense, all that stuff about whether it
belongs to the strong or the weak]. Stirner
helped Nietzsche in this critique, but did not do
enough to abandon the abstract categories of
property or alienation. The power of the
dialectic is dissolved by his acute questions, but
it ends only in 'the nothingness of the ego'(154),
the question of humanity but one framed by
nihilism. He needed a typological method [to
flesh out abstract concepts like 'man', and
use instead farkin awful different types of man,
like those tedious ones that follow below].
In particular, we need to consider the higher man,
as in Zarathustra. We precede past 'the
prophet, the two Kings, the man with the leeches,
the sorcerer, the last group, the ugliest man, the
voluntary beggar and the shadow' (155), and see in
each the reactive being of men and also of human
species activity. The higher man is the
deified version of man, but also one that
represents the triumph of culture and species
activity. The prophet represents passive
nihilism, too tired even to die. The
sorcerer is the bad conscience, who fakes
suffering in order to receive pity, and thus widen
the contagion via false tragedy. The ugliest
of men represents reactive nihilism, where
ressentiment has been turned against god, but
still flourishes in humanity. The two Kings
refer to customs, species activity grasped as
custom, but also species activity in the 'post
historic' [the modern] where there are no enduring
customs: their problem is that the [popular,
populist]customs become triumphant themselves
rather than the species activity. The man
with leeches is the scientist, pursuing certainty
and acting conscientiously, and knowing that it is
a highly limited knowledge that results, one that
cannot subordinate knowledge to any broader
values. The last pope obviously represents
culture as it produces religion. His lost
eye represents his inability to see anything
active or affirmative, but instead to see
nothingness and eventually the replacement of god
by man. The voluntary beggar has experienced
the range of human culture from rich to poor, and
was seeking happiness, both in heaven, and in
cultural activity, but wondered what sort of
happiness he seems actually likely to encounter
and whether it represented 'science, morality or
religion' (156): he already knows that a self
sufficient culture, one that is only
'ruminative', belongs to cows not humans.
The shadow is the wanderer, 'species activity
itself, culture and its movement', seeking some
higher purpose and principle. All these
types are combined in two kinds of higher man, one
which shows the triumph of reactive forces, and
the other representing species activity and its
products. This is why Zarathustra relates to
higher men differently, seeing them sometimes as
the enemy and sometimes as a host or companion.
This ambivalence shows that man may not be
essentially reactive at all. So far, we've
examined lots of arguments for this proposition,
that nihilism is the concept of universal history
and so on, and that it is impossible to conquer,
at least without destroying 'even the best
men'(157), since they are in essence reactive, the
disease of the earth. On the other hand this
seems to be some potential after all in culture
and inhumanity, and it might just have been
misdirected. There have been active periods
in history. Zarathustra sometimes claims to
be on the side of this sort of man. What is
at stake here is ' modes of becoming of forces or
qualities of the will to power'. Human
beings have a deep essence as well, relating to
the 'becoming - reactive' (158) of all forces
[hints of Deleuze's virtual?]. Becoming is
only possible in the presence of the opposite
quality, health presupposing sickness, the active
man bearing signs of illness. These
qualities of becoming are always attached to human
'destiny', and Nietzsche notes, sadly, that even
the Greek world was overthrown, even the
Renaissance; but that presupposes active forces
having been overcome. What is
'deeply... truly generic' is the 'becoming
reactive of all forces', which presupposes
activity as we just saw [philosophical
rambling around definitions as usual]. When
Zarathustra tells his visitors they have failed,
what he means is that the goal of a higher
humanity is always missed, because of its
nature. Human activity inevitably produces
flawed products [maybe], since all culture is
inhabited by reactive forces [it is all based on
an attempt to domesticate active forces in order
to permit social order? We have
objectification instead of reification]. The
dialectic is limited for the same reasons, unable
to escape becoming reactive. All the higher men
are unhappy because they know this—the Kings know
they have unleashed a mob, the shadow knows that
he will never regain unity, species and cultural
activity is a false fire dog, just a stage in an
eventual becoming reactive. This explains
the two aspects of the higher man discussed
above. [In my notes, I've explained it in
terms of Nietzsche's manic depression! I
don't think even Deleuze can really represent it
as a consistent argument. It just vacillates
from optimism to pessimism, rather like Deleuze
and Guattari on politics].
We finally come to the Overman. This is not a
successful triumph over the higher men, nor is it
the realization of the true human essence [which
apparently is what Heidegger thought]. Human
essence is and always will be human, all too
human, becoming reactive as universal becoming,
driven by nihilism. But, why does species
activity always fail? We can see that it
would if its goals have been hijacked by reactive
forces, but this project itself simply cannot be
viable without the power of affirmation.
Reactive forces after all required an ally in
order to triumph. Active forces need to make
contact with an affirmative power, however, and
here is the problem in that they lack a will
outside themselves and thus are vulnerable to the
will to nothingness. It's necessary to
express a power of affirmation, a project to
become active. Zarathustra clearly is
pursuing this project, although Zarathustra
himself is not to be taken seriously [!], and he
evokes pity. Zarathustra knows he's being
pitied. Higher men remain too abstract to
connect with affirmation, wanting only to invert
values rather than changing them. This will
only end in becoming reactive, as we saw.
Reactive forces are organized. We need
something quite different to become affirmative:
'Dionysian affirmation rather than man's species
activity'(160). In more detail: first we
need to know how to play and dance, to
laugh, even at suffering, to affirm chance and
becoming. Second we should do away with
false gods [the higher men worship the ass who
only gives a simulation of affirmation].
Third we need to investigate the symbolism of the
shadow, and in particular and noting that it needs
light. Fourth, we need to distinguish the
two fire dogs, the caricature and the real thing,
the one that lives on the surface and thus only
warms up becoming - reactive and gets cynical, and
the one that is genuinely affirmative and speaks
from the earth. [All this the poetic stuff
is no doubt very interesting, but where exactly
does it lead? What sort of politics does it
produce? Do we just opt for Dionysus or is there
anything material or even essential that would
prompt us?]
So nihilism both appears in the form of superior
values, and it also draws on reactive
values. It ends in no will at all as its
final stage, but in the meantime, it depreciates
all life. Activity is powerless under the
domination of the reactive and can only turn
against itself, even support and energize reactive
forces. Faced with this domination,
Nietzsche argues that we should change the whole
basis of values, and this is what transvaluation
is. It is no good just changing values, no
good killing god, since the whole system is still
preserved 'even if the place is left empty'
(162). It is a matter of reversing our
values, in order to regain activity, to connect it
with affirmation as will to power.
This might be possible if we accept that nihilism
is always unfinished and incomplete, and thus can
become self defeating [classic philosophical
stuff]. In this sense, transvaluation is 'a
completed nihilism', focusing on the entire set of
values. However, in order to defeat
nihilism, it must be a focus on existing values,
all those that are known up until the present that
are transmuted. We can actually uncover
existing values that are present, manifested, in
ressentiment, bad conscience, and
asceticism. We realize the power of the
human spirit by examining the strength and
complexity of the spirit of revenge. We use
our sickness to complete our knowledge of the
body. We come to see the potential of the
will to power itself, 'in general' (163), and how
it underpins all values. We come to
recognize that it actually appears in the form of
the negative, but this is only one of its
qualities. We have to think of other
aspects, and again the thought of the eternal
return helps as [if we accept that is role is to
select only affirmative qualities]. [The eternal
return {?} is the ground for knowing that the
affirmative exists, its ratio cognoscendi]
This tracks back to earlier philosophers as well
[including the Kantian argument that the full face
of god must be unknown? Now we accept Kant if he
helps us here]. The will to power is not
only suffering but 'unknown joy'. We see
this argued in the poem about Ariadne and her
complaint, where Ariadne detects some unknown god
even behind pain. [This looks suspiciously
like the dialectical method, where we postulate
the existence of something that opposes or
contradicts what it is that we see.] That
there is a will to power means that affirmation
must exist [ its ratio essendi, the grounds by
which something comes to exist], and vice versa
[of course, guaranteed by tautological
definitions]. [It is as if knowledge of the
power of the negative helps us uncover the entire
will to power, while knowledge of the eternal
return addresses the affirmative?]. New values
appear from affirmation, which were not realized
before, not uncovered by mere scholarly
philosophy, but produced by a deliberate attempt
to creation. This is the equivalent of 'a
Dionysian transmutation of pain into joy '[by some
lofty understanding that both are attached to each
other in life?]. Ariadne has to be known as
negative first before she can become affirmative.
However, all this depends on nihilism proceeding
to its conclusion [and having Nietzsche remain
exempt, as the only one capable of interpreting it
in a positive way, while all the rest of us are
impatient to die]. Nietzsche offers a
particularly 'subtle' (164) argument here.
Once the will to nothingness has triumphed, the
reactive forces are free to establish another
target, assert their own values. Even the
arrival of the last man is not sufficient to halt
the 'enterprise' of the will to nothingness.
What results is wanting to not just fade away, but
to destroy himself actively, self destruction
rather than passive extinction, this is the "man
who wants to perish". This type is produced
following another selection continuing on from the
last men, and, says Zarathustra, the active self
destroyer is 'on the path of the overman'
[inspired by a maniac and optimistic phase:
there's no other reason for it; it just appears
like a rabbit out of a hat, unless we're going to
define the will of nothingness as necessarily
turning to activity in the end. It cold be a
classic two-stage argument, where nastiness a the
surface really depends on a balance {multiplicity}
of nastiness and niceness at the virtual level.
There also seems to be some self pitying sacrifice
ethic here, where the man who wants to perish does
so deliberately in order to bring about the
overman, and thus appears at last as a
hero]. When that the reactive forces split
from the will to nothingness, there is a moment
for activity, and, happily, a potential for
affirmation [echoes here of a man who kills
himself rather than waiting for death, as a last
act of will, just like Deleuze did?]. We end
with the '" eternal joy of becoming"', just like
the end of Greek tragedy. All this is found
in Dionysus and his philosophy [which we have
already decided is marvelous]. The negative
turns into its opposite [! not just a difference
here then], not as a substitution, but as a
conversion. The last man is not really the
last man, because he is succeeded by the man who
wants to perish, to break negation, even at the
expense of perishing. We can all follow this
path, Zarathustra urges us, helping to create the
over';,.man [you can see why the Nazis had a field
day with this]. Negation is completed, and
it negates even the reactive forces.
In more detail, transvaluation or transmutation
involves: first changing quality in the will to
power, turning from negative to affirmative,
affirming life against the one we have at the
moment, and making affirmative life central,
leaving no place for any other [the Dionysian
incorporates the tragic as well as the joyful as
in Greek tragedy
]. Second, moving from a mere basis of
knowledge [ratio cognoscendi] to a more positive
argument for existence [ratio essendi], [from
scholarly to existential reason, examining real
consequences not just persuasive logical
reasons?], seeing the will to power as it is,
after establishing its qualities and the reasons
for some of them being unknown. Third, the
negative itself becomes affirmative, subordinated
to affirmation, devoted to a full life, turning
against reactive forms, heralding the
Overman. Fourth, affirmation becomes fully
independent, producing and absorbing back the
negative, completing the sequence from the man who
wants to perish. This is the final
conversion of heavy into light, of nothingness
into play and laughter, 'what Zarathustra calls
"the Communion"'(166). Fifth, all the values
known up to the present are critiqued, negated,
but in the interests of greater affirmation and
transmutation. Sixth, affirmation turns into
a 'becoming active as the universal becoming of
forces'.
We can understand Nietzsche as offering a holistic
approach, where negation and affirmation exist as
opposed qualities, but also parts of the whole [a
multiplicity?]. Negation has certainly
been dominant up to the present day and has
produced the modern man and his world, including
the tendency to nothingness. Affirmation
appears as something outside or above man, the
Overman, and this is a holistic form of
affirmation that includes the negative but reduces
its power. The Overman represents not just
the human species, but everything, it offers an
eternal affirmation of all things. It is
true that affirmation in its normal appearance is
limited, and has negative consequences, producing
destruction [the rampages of the strong?].
First negation ascends to such a point that all
known values are destroyed, which explains the
bits about how the destroyers and criminals are
also creators [in Zarathustra].
Second, substantial negations are required before
affirmation can even appear [lions become children
etc], but destruction can also become active,
committing overcoming [which is one way in which
the negative allies itself with the active, or it
would have no force at all].
The ass, always saying yea, is Dionysian in
appearance, but 'wholly Christian', offering an
affirmation admired by the higher man. It
accepts everything. [Then an odd bit about
the affirmative qualities of having small ears,
like Ariadne, and apparently, Nietzsche himself,
taken as a symbol of not being at all like the
ass. This pompous and pseudo literary stuff got on
my nerves when I was reading Nietzsche. I
understand, of course, that it is a parody of
Christian parables. Nietzsche in his self
aggrandizing way claims that his small ears make
him a monster, the anti Christ, apparently in Ecce Homo –
I probably skipped that bit]. Deleuze
continues the style by arguing that it is 'more
circular ears favoring the eternal return'
(168). Constant affirmation means an
incapacity to actually articulate
affirmation. Nietzsche here is denouncing
this false total affirmation, that contains no
negation. That is different from saying that
we should unleash affirmation that does contain
it, which makes affirmation real and compete, once
the negative has been expelled. It is a
master of needing to affirm affirmation [!],
against the false totality of reactive
forces. After the great transmutation, the
negative will become affirmative itself in this
sense, as a 'mode of being of affirmation'
(169). This nice positive affirmation might
even involve aggression, but of a positive kind,
unlike that unleashed by ressentiment. Zarathustra
is constantly offered compromises and temptations
from buffoons, dwarfs, and demons, the latter
standing for nihilism, but they are driven by
ressentiment, and Zarathustra rejects them in
favor of a more positive power of affirmation
'(love)' (169). Only this sort of
affirmation can manage the negative, and let it
destroy itself through completion as above.
Nietzsche opposes every negative form of thought
which he sees as destructive, based on
ressentiment. Negation has to be
transformed, but by effectively attacking the dual
forces that underpin ressentiment, or the ascetic
ideal [see above]. Affirmation itself must
take on a dual form, and an aggressive one, for
example in dealing with Christianity and its
underlying ressentiment. [This helps us play
little games: 'to the famous positivity of the
negative, Nietzsche opposes his own discovery: the
negativity of the positive'(170)]. The two
negations are not like the two in the dialectic
[contradiction and transcendence?]. If we
look at the critique of the ass, we can see two
elements, a lack of affirmation, and also a
misunderstanding of affirmation. [So 'the
ass is also a camel'] —both are docile, patient,
accepting their burdens as inevitable and real,
not responsive to any other notions of the real:
for them, affirmation means taking things upon
yourself, 'acquiescing in the real'(171).
Nietzsche can see all the reactive forces here,
producing all the strengths of the ass. By
being limited to what is real in this way, it is
impossible to investigate the production of the
real, and this is the fate of most of us who are
taught to accept our lives and our
realities. The ass is even Christ.
Freed from this divine model by the ascent of man,
the ass accepts everything placed upon him, and
his identity itself depends on his ability to
accept the real. Human beings also are
too inclined to stick to the present instead of
looking to the future, the false positivity with
its false affirmation [all this is referenced to
the usual poetic rhubarb in Zarathustra].
A sense of reality and affirmativeness is attached
to everything that is heavy. This works best
in the desert [camel, geddit?] of nihilism, and
heavy reality tends to dominate everything else
anyway. Asses do not know how to say no to
this burdensome reality, because they cannot
identify nihilism as its context [and might will
prefer to cling to burdensome reality instead of
nihilism?].
This is not a stoical acceptance [of Fate in all
its manifestations?], says Deleuze, more to do
with linking affirmation to things that can be
seen, things that exist at the moment, however we
conceive of existence. Philosophy itself has
been apologetic, as in its strange mixtures of,
say, 'metaphysics and humanism' (172). [It
certainly lacks a sociological method which would
help it critique reality]. If existing being
is seen as affirmative, then affirmation must also
be found in human being [we get our sense of
ourselves by distinguishing ourselves from brute
reality, and being able to do things with it in a
positivist sense?]. Humans must relate to
being in a positive or a dialectical sense, and
Nietzsche singles out the latter, for offering a
more sophisticated, but still wrong, discussion of
the negative. Hegelian idealism, for
example, leaves being untouched, or something that
is transformed into nothingness. Feuerbach
restored a notion of the sensuous, real being, but
fell into the trap of affirming being as it is:
this real being is still produced by the
reactive. Nietzsche offers a different
account. First, conventional notions of
being truth and reality depend on nihilism and the
reactive, something constructed by the negative,
not self sufficient, but a symptom of a
will. Second, affirmation is not acceptance,
and we must be prepared to say no to affirm, be a
lion instead of an ass or camel. Third, this
sort of positivist affirmation still preserves
conventional notions of humanity, which is really
the reactive man: he survives, but only by living
in the desert [geddit?], living for a long time
only because he has lost 'the taste for dying'
(173).
Existing notions of reality celebrates dead
things, but the world is really living, subject to
wills to power, but also to a 'will to falsehood'
(174) [and what or who drives this
systematically?]. Making things false
involves an evaluation, and everything is an
evaluation, so there is no reality in brute
appearance or in trusting the senses. There
is even a will to appearance and illusion or
deception. The will to develop positivist
truth is just an example of this will to
illusion. This shows that the negative has
dominated the attempts to grasp reality
['actualizing the will'] so far, and this has
produced apparent opposites like being or reality
as opposed to life. Beneath these assertions
we will find evaluations or 'lies'. There is
the whole will to power, however, attempting to
grasp the whole of life, and to affirm its
particularity [defined, oddly as 'a higher power
of the false', meaning something which art
does?]. This still involves an evaluation,
but this time an evaluation based on enjoying
difference rather than setting out
oppositions. It doesn't try to rationalize
on the basis of what is, but to 'set free what
lives', not to accept the burdens, but to create
light values, new forms of life. However,
this is beyond human effort and strength at the
moment, but the task is to shake off these false
burdens. This is indeed an aspect of art as
the highest power of the false, a Dionysian
affirmation, something superhuman. [There is
a summary on page 175]. This higher form of
affirmation only follows an initial negativity
towards positivist forms of reality and the base
forms of experience that this produces.
There is a new conception of being proposed here,
linking it to affirmation itself.
'Affirmation itself is being, being is solely
affirmation in all its power' (175). The
normal conceptions of being and nothingness, the
actualized ones, are just abstract expressions of
affirmation and negation as they appear in the
will to power. How can affirmation be seen
as being? [Only by seeing it as two-level, actual
and virtual]. It has no actual objects in mind,
but rather becoming, which involves being
affirmative about becoming, a double affirmation,
both at the primary and secondary levels.
Again Deleuze finds reference to this in
Nietzsche's symbolic texts [oh no].
Thus the eagle and the serpent can be seen as
aspects of the eternal return, the great cycle of
the cosmic level, and individual destiny
respectively. This suggests a two-level
nature of affirmation. Dionysus and Ariadne
do as well. Ariadne is a complex character
who first loved Theseus, who himself stands for
the higher man, courageously taking on challenges,
but not rooted in the earth, too ready to assume
burdens. Ariadne is offered only the
feminine image of the higher man, whose power
turns on revenge and ressentiment. Once
Ariadne is abandoned by Theseus, she transmutes
and liberates her feminine power to become
something more affirmative, something more
suitable to go beyond the higher man to the
Overman. When she meets Dionysus, she is
affirmed again, and she energizes him. The
eternal return [French version of Will to Power]
shows the "closest approximation of being and
becoming"' (177), but itself needs to be affirmed,
in a Dionysian universe of cycles and rings.
Dionysus needs a fiancée [wedding ring, geddit?]
to be accepted and affirmed in his wholeness [so
here we have the final argument for Deleuze's
reading of the eternal return—it's consistent with
the poem about Ariadne and Dionysus!]. The
labyrinth is also an image in Nietzsche, and
representing the unconscious or the self, and we
need a guiding thread [!] to explore it. The
labyrinth is also the eternal return, something
circular, leading back to the same instant.
However, the labyrinth is also becoming, or even
its affirmation, something which leads to
being. Again the two levels are connected,
since the thread affirms becoming as well, but
first leading Theseus to a higher values, still
based on the negative. Dionysus tells
Ariadne he is the labyrinth and the thread is an
affirmation of him. She affirms this [!],
having heard him with her little ears [the ears
are another labyrinth]. So the labyrinth is
being that results from becoming, but it requires
a double affirmation of being and becoming
[Jesus!].
We now see that affirmation and negation are both
qualities of the will to power, but they are
asymmetric. Affirmation doesn't just oppose
negation [except at the actual level].
Affirmation enjoys difference, but negation is
entirely negative. At last, we can see that
affirmation is 'multiplicity, becoming and chance'
(178), and all are dualist in this case, linked
with their opposites [becoming with being, chance
with necessity] hence requiring double
affirmations [which at the higher level, affirms
the multiplicity]. In this way, [higher]
affirmation can be seen as 'in the nature of'
returning in a cycle of becoming and being.
[Assertion masquerading as some logical
deduction]. Apparently, all these 'are the
aspects of Dionysian willing', and 'principles for
the eternal return' (179). There is no
return of the negative, because being is itself
selection, and only something that is affirmed can
return, something that must preserve the relation
with becoming, something that is active.
Multiplicities contain difference but not
negation. This is the thrust of Nietzsche's
entire critique of the mystifications of
philosophy, including the apparent power of the
negative, or the lingering effects of bad
conscience. Nietzsche says that difference
is happiness, and object of joy, and 'that only
joy returns' [in his manic moments] . We
find 'philosophical joy' [aha!] in these notions
of multiplicity, becoming and chance, and the
satisfying unity which links them, in their
ability to explain things ['necessity'].
This has a universal benefit, however
[philosophers always speak on our behalf].
It is untimely, but it promises liberation from
things like the unhappy consciousness or the
negative generally. Even the death of god
will turn into a joyful event eventually, once we
realize that it is a step on the way to exclude
the negative and the reactive.
Instead of negativity and opposition, we have 'the
warlike play of difference, affirmation and the
joy of destruction' (180). We can see this
in Zarathustra, passing through the negative until
he reaches the point of transmutation, the story
of the struggle with the nihilist demon and his
various relationships with man [a burden, jumping
over men etc], preserving his negative power and
will in these different forms. Zarathustra
combats negation and stands for affirmation,
active existence, the sign of the lion, as a
symbol of affirmative destruction. The will
to power no longer produces only the negative, but
has an unknown face as well, making the negative
only one actualization. Z can be seen as the
father of the Overman, representing the final
precondition for his emergence. In this
sense, he is also an agent of the eternal return,
so 'Zarathustra is subject to Dionysus'.
Zarathustra, Ariadne, and Dionysus represent the
'Trinity of the antiChrist', but Ariadne only
energizes Dionysus. Zarathustra therefore
cannot bring about the eternal return on his own,
but can only father it. The eternal return
and the Overman emerge from two genealogies, 'two
unequal genetic lines'.
Thus Zarathustra is given the task of explaining
[actual?] causes and moments, while Dionysus
explains the necessary, absolute, even
'apodictic'(182) nature of these connections, how
actual moments are synthesized in becoming.
Thus the eternal return becomes an active moment,
itself determined, but also determining, at the
second level of affirmation. So Zarathustra
sees the connection between affirmation and the
will to power, but arguing that this is necessary
[my emphasis] belongs to Dionysus. It is the
difference between conditioned and unconditioned
affirmation [where conditioned here refers to
empirical or at least actual events?].
Unconditioned affirmation is required in order to
break the sequence of types of men. It
appears in a disguised way, as conditions Dionysus
sets which appear autonomous. This is the
creative moment, since these conditions contain an
excess, 'a deeper genealogy'.
So each concept in Nietzsche expresses these two
unequal genetic lines. Laughter, play and
dance bring about concrete transmutations in
Zarathustra, but are deeper affirmative powers of
reflection and development in Dionysus, affirming
becoming and multiplicity: 'play affirms chance and
[my emphasis] the necessity of chance'.
Conclusion.
Modern philosophy is full of hybrids and amalgams,
and this shows its vigor, but there are also
dangers [incidentally, phenomenology is seen as
'modern scholasticism' (184)]. Everything is
mixed together, and allegedly metaphysics has been
surpassed, even philosophy. Nietzsche wanted
to go beyond metaphysics, but so did Jarry! [There
is a short piece on Jarry in Deleuze's Essays...]
Nietzsche would've been tempted to withdraw from
this game, this incorporation of scraps of the
whole philosophical legacy into modern thought.
Nietzsche and Hegel are irreconcilable.
Nietzsche pursues a number of polemical projects,
including an attack on dialectic and its
mystifications. Schopenhauer began the task
but remained in Kant and pessimism, but Nietzsche
offers a 'new image of thought'. If the
dialectic is defined by: the power of the negative
manifested in opposition and contradiction; the
idea that suffering and sadness have value,
because they are manifested in split and loss;
that positivity is produced by negation, then
Nietzsche centrally attacks these three ideas [I
still think he has to revert to the first one to
explain the emergence of the Overman]. His
argument is that contradiction offers 'a false
image of difference', and inverts the whole
process, seeing difference as the thing to be
negated, the self as being affirmed only after the
negation of the other, and the negation of the
negation in order to make progress, whereas it
should've really argued for the affirmation of
affirmation. The whole thing is animated by
underlying interests [not class differences, of
course, but some abstract ontological or
philosophical interest], expressing every aspect
of reactive forces and nihilism.
Ressentiment requires a double negation in order
to produce a 'a phantom of affirmation' (185), and
asceticism requires both ressentiment and bad
conscience. The whole thing turns on sad
passions and unhappy consciousness. It is a
philosophy suitable for the theoretical man
reacting against life, trying to judge it [which
is what Nietzsche says about the Socratic
dialectic]. It is also the philosophy of the
priest, subduing life with negatives in order to
establish their power [actually, 'his power',
nearly an actual agent]. The dialectic
appears at its most authentic in Christian
ideology, where it appeals to the thought of the
slave, reactive life in itself. Even the
atheism produced is still 'a clerical atheism',
the image of the master is still a slavish
one. Positivity is falsified and highly
limited. Dialectical positivity, 'the real
in the dialectic' is 'the yes of the ass',
accepting reality in its entirety, including the
products of the negative. People embrace the
dialectic thinking they are being positive and
affirmative, and see it as powerful because it
apparently explains everything [not these days
matey. Positivism has conquered all].
Nietzsche separated ressentiment from bad
conscience, and this was itself of great
importance [why?]. His polemic 'is only the
aggression which derives from a deeper, active and
affirmative instance'(186) [see below] .
Dialectic and kantian critique, which are linked,
both preserved this notion of false
critique. A true critique takes an
independent developmental route, and sees the
negative as only one mode of being.
Dialectical philosophy just describes symptoms
rather than underlying forces or will. They
only asked the question 'what is?', 'the
contradictory question par excellence' [because
everything that exists must be contradictory,
heterogeneous?]. Nietzsche's method was
'dramatic, typological and differential', and
philosophy became an art, something involving
interpretation and evaluation. His focus was
on the 'which one?' involving the will to power as
a flexible and genealogical principle, an element
which determines the relation of forces in
quantitative and qualitative terms. This
fundamental difference is manifested in multiple
affirmation [it can explain any of the types?] and
has the potential to be creative because it
bestows, even 'bestowing virtue'.
Thus pure affirmation involves multiplicity,
becoming and chance. Multiplicity is
affirmed in a speculative proposition,
corresponding to asserting the joy of diversity as
a practical one [so all that stuff about joy
supports the philosophy of multiplicity and gives
it a 'practical' dimension]. We only lose if
we only affirm at the first stage, so to speak,
affirming particular outcomes, seeing chance as
negative, and becoming and multiplicity as
opposition. True affirmation of chance
'necessarily produces the winning number'so that
the dice throw can be reproduced [still a bit
mysterious. Does it mean that if you affirm
chance, you must be able to convince yourself that
you will win eventually? Or that no dice
throw ever produces a loss because the game is the
thing? Or that the eternal return will only
bring about positive outcomes so all we have to do
is wait for it?]. We have to affirm 'the
necessity of chance' [that is, see no real
alternative to it,so might as well celebrate
it?]. We have to see being as multiplicity
and becoming. If we affirm all this, we are
affirming affirmation itself at its highest
level. [We stay cheerful and whistle under
all circumstances, accepting what Fate gives
us]. Difference also repeats or reproduces
itself, and we see this in the eternal return,
which is its highest power, 'the synthesis of
affirmation which finds its principle in the
will'[the eternal return as combining affirmation
and being, justifying the affirmative will to
power?]. This is the affirmation of
affirmation, opposing the weight of the negative.
The will to power does clearly manifest negation,
and reaction is a particular quality of
force. But these are only options, and there
are other aspects of the will to power. We
are prevented from finding what those are because
conventional knowledge itself expresses reactive
forces. Human understanding is deeply
affected by negation pessimism ['Man inhabits only
the dark side of the earth']. That's why
human history so far has been all about nihilism
negation and reaction, but long term, negation
will turn back on reactive forces themselves, and
bring about transvaluation: negation loses the
power to negate and becomes active, appearing as
only one form of affirmation. It changes
quality. It becomes valued now only as 'the
preliminary offensive or a subsequent aggression'
(187). This is the 'negativity of the
positive', again a new development from dialectic
[I'm still not convinced, especially if
dialectical change involves a certain struggle
against the old constraints, which itself could be
seen as a positive one in the long run, something
justified in order to bring about a positive
end. Without some sort of qualification as
well, anything can be justified as positive
aggression, including the extermination of Jews in
order to bring about the new order]. It
follows that transmutation is a condition of the
eternal return [condition here meaning one of the
factors that brings it about?], or that it depends
on the eternal return, involving 'the standpoint
of a deeper principle'. This is because [!]
The will to power only returns what is affirmed,
having transformed the negative [first? How
long must we wait?]. The one 'is for the
other… in the other' [sounds very
Christian]. The eternal return is being, but
we have already seen that being is selection [ but
NOT that being always selects the affirmative,
quite the opposite]. The will to power has
affirmation as it's 'sole quality' [I think we've
changed the meaning of affirmation now, because
this refers to affirmation at the first level, the
affirmation that is necessary to pursue any
action, including actions under the sway of
reactive forces]. Action becomes the sole
quality of force [all this must be after the
eternal return: before it, reaction can also be a
quality of force]. 'Becoming - active as the
creative identity of power and willing'[we'll get
pie in the sky when we die, and can become fully
active affirmative characters].
back to Deleuze page
|
|