Notes on: Maton,
K. (1999) 'Extra curricular Activity
Required. Pierre Bourdieu and the Sociology
of Educational Knowledge'. [I have the draft
version, downloaded from Academia.edu, and I use
the draft page numbers, but the published version
is found in Grenfell M and Kelly M (eds). Pierre
Bourdieu: Language, culture and education.
Bern, Peter Lang: 197-210.]
Dave Harris
We have long been interested in how educational
knowledge is 'selected, organized, distributed,
transmitted and evaluated'(1), although this is
been marginalised in British sociology.
Bourdieu's framework provides one option, but
there are possibilities for development. The
examination of cultural studies as an academic
subject provides an early impetus for such study
[discussed further here].
Bernstein offers an account of the early formation
of the problem in the New Sociology of Education
developed in the 1970s. This replaced the
earlier philosophy of education and how academic
subjects became logically cohesive [for example
through Hirst]. There was also the history
of education. However, both decontextualised
academic subjects. In the New Sociology
there was originally more an emphasis on knowing
rather than on knowledge as such, inspired by
phenomenology. This subjectivism
overemphasized the possibilities for change and
ignored wider structural relations.
Later neo Marxist accounts used the term such as correspondence, reproduction or hegemony, and stressed
external power relations, although they also had a
problem of appearing to be over simple at first,
[and ignoring resistance and struggle, even though
that was pretty marginal]. Together with the
earlier emphases, there is a promise of a more
general emphasis on the active construction of
curricular, but a more 'empirically applicable,
conceptual framework is required' (2).
Bourdieu sees higher education is a relatively
autonomous social field, with its own logic and
structure, but still with external
pressures. Academic subjects are differently
located in this field. They struggle and
compete over hierarchies. Within
disciplinary discourse there are similarly some
autonomous and even '"economically heteronomous"
poles'(4), and high status permits more distant
from external interests. There is still a
homology between educational and social dominance,
however. Cultural studies is particularly
heteronomous opposing both liberal and vocational
poles. The field itself is dynamic, with the
possible subversion from new subjects, following
strategies over what counts as legitimate
knowledge. Sometimes a change in the
audience is engaged as well, so that the policy of
encouraging student choice and educational
expansion has had effects in the UK.
However, limits appear as well because Bourdieu
cannot account for the forms of educational
knowledge and practice, and he still sees these as
'epiphenomena of the play of positions within a
field' rather than having 'structuring
significance' of their own (5). This makes
operationalizing the concept in empirical research
more difficult. For example, the concepts
change across different contexts, especially
'"pedagogic authority" and "cultural arbitrary"'.
There is a relationship between habitus and field,
so that practices followed by structuring
qualities of the habitus. However habitus is
described only in terms of its outcomes, appearing
as only another layer of ethnographic
description. Bernstein argues that this
shows a lack of necessity between the concept and
the realization [and a suggestion that Bourdieu
selects his examples to illustrate his
points]. Bourdieu is aware of the possible
circularity of the term habitus, but awareness is
probably not a sufficient safeguard. What he needs
is more work on the form of the habitus, to turn
it into a methodological tool. Otherwise,
Bourdieu is offering only a different approach or
perspective, a different way of seeing the objects
of study, and this is amplified, says Boudon, by
the relational analysis itself. The habitus
might be a 'highly perceptive and heuristic
metaphor', but it 'remains more of a black
box'[much of this seems based upon Bernstein
(1996) Pedagogy, Symbolic Control and
Identity: Theory, Research, Critique.
London: Taylor and Francis].
Secondly, Bourdieu needs to realise that
educational knowledge is not just epiphenomenal,
but has a structuring role itself. It is not
just arbitrary in an absolute way, and so there is
no need to look at the history of educational
knowledge, for example. In Homo Academicus,
there is no discussion of forms of knowledge and
practice [I'm not so sure - there is certainly
criticism of Barthes' interdisciplinary
work]. Knowledge actually has two relations,
epistemic and social [discussed further here], and
both need to be analysed. Bourdieu's
emphasis on power relations ignores the first one,
and pedagogic discourse in particular is
'arbitrary and contingent upon what has
historically been associated with
dominant/dominated positions'(7) [this could be
defended on empirical grounds by arguing that
pedagogy is just not something to be highlighted
in elite institutions of higher education].
[The example again is cultural studies claiming to
pursue subversive forms of pedagogic discourse -
but my example of the influence of the open
university teaching system is much better!].
The form of educational practices is not described
only by their function, and the epistemic relation
is not irrelevant. We are offered only a
sociology of knowledge, 'not an analysis of
knowledge itself'[again, the discussion of Kantian
philosophy seems highly relevant
here]. Academics also pursue curricular
activity. Ignoring this reintroduces social
reductionism, despite the claims about relative
autonomy, and 'the structure of what is said is
unimportant' (8). We have a form of
'meso-externalism', where 'knowledge reflects
relational positions'. The structure of
knowledge remains arbitrary [surely an
exaggeration of Bourdieu's position? The
point is that these relations intrude into 'pure'
knowledge at crucial points in the form of
presuppositions dispositions and visions which,
despite the critical focus of philosophy
elsewhere, remain uncriticized - which is surely
unarguable. I don't think Bernstein or
Popper would disagree. These presuppositions
and visions are precisely what later generations
of philosophers go back and rework]. Some
forms of knowledge are 'more epistemologically
powerful than others', however [again surely
Bourdieu does not disagree - he claims that social
science is one of these. He might be
convicted of being tactical here, however, and is
open to the kantian retort that he risks being
caught in a contradiction or antinomy , where
either all knowledge has social roots, including
his own, or his knowledge has somehow escaped
altogether, and thus must be inspired by god].
We need to analyse the relations behind the
epistemic relation as well, 'the relation of
knowledge to its constructed object of study'
[that is, we need to do philosophy as in
Popper? Would this break with the
contradiction as above?]. It is true that
Bourdieu considered relationism to be an
instrument of rupture, a transitory phase to
combat idealism [citing a rather obscure
publication - Bourdieu (1988) 'On interest and the
relative autonomy of symbolic power'in Working
Papers and Proceedings of the Centre for
Psychosocial Studies, 20 --got it here]. This
transitory quality is in danger of being lost,
however.
Overall, Basil Bernstein's work seems more
productive, citing one of his own papers in 1998.
Back to Bourdieu page.
|
|