NOTES on:
Pelletier, C (2009) Rancière and the poetics of
the social sciences. Online:
http://eprints.ioe.ac.uk/3198/1/
Pelletier2009Rancière267.pdf [also in IJRM 32(3)
267-81]
[Difficult rambling, full of special pleading...
Also refs to untranlsated Rancière]
Methodology should be reconsidered as an aesthetic
endeavour [ie someting which partitions reality],
recognizing that research intervenes in social
order and takes on political significance, as in
the classic debates about science and
ideology. Rancière's own method is seen as
arguing 'for a democratic research practice
organized around a "method of equality". He
has to be compared with an 'openly ideological
feminist ethnography' if we are to investigate
affect and subjectification.
Rancière contrasts the idea of democracy as a form
of government with that of 'an action which
disrupts social altering', and this has been
discussed in terms of education and democracy, for
example in Biesta, who considers inclusion models
of education as bringing into order those who are
not already included, while Ruitenberg (2008) sees
the dangers of making education a qualification
for participating in democracy. Rancière
particularly argues that even the ignorant people
can teach and therefore 'anyone can govern'(2).
A number of educational researchers [including
Hey] have launched research which looks at how
education orders people into more or less valuable
and significant categories, drawing on Foucault
and Bourdieu. Rancière specifically defines
politics as discussing how power and domination
produces disqualified others [I gloss]. But
what are the implications for research
methodology? Rancière himself seems to
oppose any sort of methodology, especially if it
is enshrined in academic disciplines like
[Bourdieu's] sociology. His interest [is a
classically abstract one] 'to question the
partition by which kinds of discourse - the
discourse of research objects and the discourse of
science - are differentiated from one another',
and how this gives rise to specialist ways of
knowing and techniques of research. Rancière
says that this sort of discourse claims to
'produce a discourse which is of a different order
to that which is the object of study: non illusory
knowledge, or knowledge which is not rooted in
ideological fantasy'. [So a dangerous
relativism or indifference beckons as in
Baudrillard's critique] [NB he goes on apparently
to argue that academic research is also based on
fantasy. Of course, all this could apply
equally well to his own work about which he
remains confident, as argued below -- unlike
reflexive feminists]
This can lend weight to some criticisms of
critical pedagogy which implies the critique
masters its object [better than the usual popular
readings] and is therefore hierarchical.
Rancière's emphasis on poetics and aesthetics
denies the particular privilege claimed by
scientists in overcoming ideology [by seeing all
discourses as poetic ones etc -- as in Foucault]
. The very claim to be scientific relies on
an assumption that 'the domain of science is then
cast as that which its object (ideological
subjects) cannot know'. [cannot know ever, or
cannot know until they begin to study?]
This is not relativistic, however because it wants
to open the possibility of politics on the basis
of equality, which in turn means challenging
claims to epistemological superiority [but
ordinary people claim superiority all the time for
their local knowledges, as Jacotot noted].
Sociology in particular overemphasizes social
locations and social attributes, which
'effectively denies the possibility of
collectivity on the basis of the lack of social
attributes—in other words on the basis of
equality'[sounds like some liberal fantasy about
how order emerges from enlightened self interest,
while collective identities are oppressive].
Nor does it help to acknowledge the location of
social science in the social order, because this
is 'simply reconfirming its hegemony, or its lack
of difference from itself' (3) [so the only
alternative is a reductive populism, with no
possibility of critique?]. The way to
challenge this is to rethink 'the equivalence
established between discourse and social location
in both the object and the subject of study—in
other words, by challenging the idea that a
statement, or discourse, is the expression of the
sociological condition', especially position in
the social order [an absurd denial of the social
location of philosophers,in effect,who think they
have escaped the effects of their social location.
A fantasy of the autonomous intellectual].
This is a fundamental challenge to the idea of
scientific knowledge of social order, and also the
categories commonly found in sociology, such as
woman or carpenter. Butler argues in a
similar way in suggesting that 'sociological
categories (notably a feminist "we")'hold a
constituency together by means of exclusion of
some part of that constituency' [she seems to mean
subdivisions among women on the basis of colour or
sexuality]. There is, however, always
a 'supplement, or excess', and we might read
Rancière as the attempt to make this supplement
visible, but not by just adding qualifications,
such as 'lesbian woman'(4). His work is
therefore in affinity with Zizek and other
Lacanian feminists on the dangers of 'any effort
to posit identity' [cf the absurdities of the
nomadic subject in Deleuze and Guattari-- all this
happens in the world of thought occupied by
autonomous academics, but in cold reality,
institutions impose identities all the time -- as
Bourdieu notes] . Rancière argues similarly
that 'repressions and foreclosures' accompany any
attempt to establish specific academic
disciplines: there is always what Butler calls
'"the failure to complete"', and in the case of
Rancière, this leads to an emphasis on
'"displacement, indistinction, de-differentiation
or de-qualification"'[quoting Hallward]
[Where? Is this a gloss on Proletarian
Nights?] [ Reminiscent of familiar critiques
of positivism like Adorno's in Negative Dialctecics]
. This involves rejecting methodology 'as an
ordering mechanism' perpetuating particular
disciplinary categories. While he is there,
he is also 'profoundly antithetical to a
conception of discipline' [So what remains is
free-floating virtuoso thought?] .
However, the work actually depends on social
science, if only by exploring what is
disavowed. This helps form alliances with
other critics such as feminist and Foucaldian
ones, who have also looked at how discursive
categories in social science contain [ie
control] an excess. The exclusions
required to maintain disciplinary identity are
better seen as 'denials, repudiations - the
rejection of an abject other' [why abject? NB
Ranciere does a bit of this by ignoring 'older
workers', for example in Proletarian Nights,
says Reid in his intro] . This is useful for
anyone researching the connections between 'body,
speech and subjectification in research
practice'. The writing itself 'works as a
claim to affect', seeing research as combative,
'to make visible what has been denied, to argue
with widely used systems of categorizations'
[]Foucault's recovery of the excluded eg
'herstories'] . This is however a 'very
different in tone to feminist accounts which
foreground the uncertainty of their own claims to
knowledge'[there is a reference to Lather 2007,
who seems to have realized that if we take all
this seriously we can actually write about very
little other than 'fragments' etc. Of course
any critique of the categories of others is a
claim to knowledge].
The interest of researchers in education is
addressed by seeing education as a social science
discipline, not something with specific objects in
mind, although there are some 'alignments'
especially with feminist researchers who have
apparently 'been working on similar intellectual
terrain for the last 20 years'. Research is
seen as a democratic practice [not in the usual
sense of collaborative authorship, but in the
sense that the excluded are to be given a voice?]
, which links with the ideas of methodology as
subversive.
The aesthetics of knowledge means how discourses
'constitute themselves as coherent, valid, and
credible, in opposition to the forms of ignorance'
(5). Any account of knowledge produces a
form of ignorance [including his?] .
Scientific accounts must involve a category of
accounts which are non scientific, and ignorance
has a role, 'as a necessary corollary of knowledge
production'[must apply to Rancière as well
then]. Rancière's account developed out of a
critique of Marxism especially the concept of
ideology, which apparently has been defined 'as a
set of false beliefs, or post Althusser, as a set
of practices which bring about false
judgments/perceptions/sensibilities/actions - as
in Bourdieu's notion of practice' (5) [lots to
discuss here], things which are not necessarily
untrue, but sustain domination, and this argument
runs from Marx and Engels to Bourdieu.
Perceptions are limited by social location and by
'ignorance of the means in fact of
domination'. This is expressed in Bourdieu and Passeron,
where a school actually produces ignorance of
domination, ignorance of how the social order
works [ is Rancière denying that groups do this in
order to legitimate their rule?]. Making
this claim involves extricating yourself from that
social order, and this is what the concept of
reflexivity amounts to in Bourdieu, when his
knowledge takes place as somehow outside of the
social order. Specifically, Rancière sees
Bourdieu as placing knowledge outside the division
of labour in order to study ignorance.
Reflexivity involves somehow placing one's self
outside of that social order, and this is
performative [i.e. produces desirable effects] in
the sense that ignorance, '(the logic of
practice)' is a product of Bourdieu's own
discourse [only? Not convinced by the examples eg
of the common failure to appreciate the real
importance of kinship in the preservation of a
dominant group? All must be like the
insightful workers in the 1830s?] . This
analysis is available only to sociologists and the
ignorant are excluded. The effect is to
secure the domain of knowledge rather than
describe a state of affairs, and sociology can
safely criticize while knowing domination will
always persist [so can Rancière who has made a
tidy living as a contrarian?] .
Rancière also criticizes those attempts to develop
the idea of authentic popular culture as
autonomous from dominant values, those social
histories which talked about working class
culture, resistance and agency. The
implications are conservative, since people should
remain authentic to their own culture and avoid
'middle class "intellectualism"' (6) [apparently
outlined in the introduction to The Philosopher
and his Poor]. Any intellectual
readings made by ordinary people become merely
Morley's 'populist ventriloquism', since popular
people cannot think authentically while remaining
popular: they must stick to their own domain of
knowledge, which serve to protect intellectual
knowledge, and maintain a split between science
and popular knowledge. [I think Pelletier has an
unusual meaning of the term ventriloquism here --
Morely used it to show how media experts claimed
to talk on behalf of ordinary people]
The common issue is that there is a claim to know
about 'the poor' [which could include women and
black people, says Pelletier], and in this way we
can see that 'sociological knowledge emerges as
the surplus value of the poor's labour' [nice --
but fair? Reminds me of the idea of the 'knight's
move' in ethnography -- or Bourdieu on the
symbolic violence of ethnographic accounts] (6),
but which has to be interpreted by
scientists. The whole argument depends on
assuming some connection between sensibilities and
social location, so that social location
determines understanding of social
practices. This is what current sociology
does. It ignores the contingency or
arbitrariness, even of domination [but Rancière
asserts it and overpredicts it].
'Consequently, and tautologically, the fact of
being in a certain social location (e.g. being
poor) becomes the reason for being in such a
location, since people can never do anything else
but "be" an instance of a social location' (7).
Both these critical approaches attempt to explain
mechanisms of domination, and consciousness of
domination, but claim that ordinary people do not
understand it [this is partly in empirical
question, surely—what sort of evidence does
Rancière adduce?]. There is no understanding
of domination, despite Althusser
arguing that ideology is a practice rather than a
cognitive limit. But any sort of knowing
'divides the world into two: people who are
ignorant and people who know'. R discusses
this in terms of the aesthetics of scientific
discourse, where all discourse divides the world
up into those who speak and those who
ventriloquise, those who act and those who simply
obey, those who can discuss, and those who are too
caught up in their own occupations and
culture. Normal attempts to gather knowledge
about domination ignores 'the possibility of
social disorder' in the sense that the poor can
never do anything outside what is understood by
the social sciences of domination [a fancy way of
saying that social control is overdetermined?].
This leads to the methodological issue, which
turns on 'presuppositions made in reading data, or
more specifically, with the way a discipline
positions its own discourse with respect to that
of the object of study'[which obviously includes
any academic discourse, including R's own].
There are some 'affinities' with Foucault on
archaeology here, since disciplines constitute
objects as objects of thought, and allocate
certain roles, which are compatible with
disciplinary thought and knowledge. This
happens with the very narration of the discipline
itself. This involves not methodology but
aesthetics [because it offers a dramatized picture
of the world].
Research either explains domination and poses as a
remedy to ignorance, or ignores domination and
offers knowledge of equality, which is R's
alternative. Knowledge production
necessarily generates a type of ignorance, so the
inequalities implied have to be challenged.
[Then a classic piece of idealism: 'If one is
"ignorant" of inequality, if one denies the
reality of inequality, one is in effect asserting
and instantiating equality' (8)]. We have to
be [nice and positive], not to research inequality
but 'to "verify" equality'.
The first step is to ignore material inequality,
and this runs the risk of simply overlooking or
dismissing it. Instead, we are not to assume
inequality, for example by seeing art as the
result of particular sociological conditions, such
as being female in a patriarchal society: this
only confirms inequality. Instead we have to
start with discourse [and research is itself only
a discourse]. It is not a matter of
respecting the words of others or celebrating
them, but it turns on 'classifying words, by a
reordering the way in which words take on meaning
by virtue of the category/body to which they are
assigned in the social order', ignoring any claims
to legitimacy involving the social status of the
speaker. This might include rereading
scientific statements as literary prose, or even
reading history as a form of speech in the
present, as R himself did in Proletarian
Nights, aiming to break with the usual
distinctions between popular culture and academic
culture in favour of '"a poetics of knowledge",
that claims to break with all subject
disciplines'. This poetics of knowledge
starts with equality, and tries to find a research
method to open the possibilities for equality, at
least in one's own writing [yet Proletarian
Nights is riddled with commentary, including
realist conventions that allocate any quoted
discourses to particular places].
There is admission that not much might be done,
but it is better than intellectual speaking on
behalf of others, which only delays equality
endlessly, as in pedagogy. The work must
begin by disrupting inequality, and not waiting
for it to be achieved later. Again, some
feminist writings also argue this. There is
also a new value given to actions which had
transgressed categories, in this case popular
culture. Any data confirming inequality
should be neglected or ignored [I think this means
in the form of an assumption that speaking will be
limited]. Data must be read
differently. It is like the redemptive
reading of drag in Butler, which challenges the
ontological status of gender [makes it
performative?] [so again a rather abstract
philosophical project, illustrated in R's case by
'making prominent in one's analytic strategy
discursive practices which make the contingency of
inequality sensible' (9) [wha? -- explaining
inequality as arbitrary and contingent? This sort
of academic discourse itself reinforces
inequality!!] We can see how this works by looking
at one of the more substantive studies [I do hope
so].
We can compare R with Bourdieu esp. with Language
and Symbolic Power. Bourdieu found
misrecognition in the speech of the exploited,
because the role of symbolic capital and its
exchange is misunderstood. R by contrast
found only disagreement [and misunderstanding, I
think the French term translates as] . He
came to this view by looking at worker history and
working class speech, which he saw as an attempt
to locate an identity in common speech [that is an
attempt to belong and not to develop a separate
identity]. Thus the workers engaged in all
sorts of cultural activities in their free time,
poems, letters, newspapers and so on, speaking in
ways which 'exceeded any coincidence with
themselves as occupants of a specific social
place'(10). It was a demand for leisure,
denial of the 'identity category' worker (11),
insisting on subjectivation, a person not being
explained by their work or by the absence of a
role. Workers are 'doing something else than
their social identity' and this is to make a claim
towards commonality, denying their conventional
lack of identity [and there is a curious defence
of indirect free discourse in the book by Parker,
2004 - it is apparently the result of 'the book's
commitment to an equality legible even in the form
of its Darstellung [narration]']. The work
leads on to challenging conventional social
histories and reunderstanding them, for example
the struggle over the time of day as a demand for
humanizing leisure and a denial the workers are
only productive work. R replies to the
criticism of non representativeness by saying his
effort is simply to 'multiply the images of
workers' not to challenge the more statistically
based histories, and 'to evoke images which
suggest the workers have something else to
contribute to communal life'. This is what
is involved in disagreement rather than
misrecognition, centred on 'the disputed status of
speech': there is positive speech as well as
ventriloquism, and the issue is whether speakers
actually speak for themselves. [Bourdieu is
presumably being accused of taking the same line
as did Marx on these unfortunate Proudhonists].
These debates are reminiscent of feminist
research, particularly ethnography. The
criticism has been that this work is openly
ideological, standing in for others, adopting a
position of mastery itself, especially as we know
that knowledge and power are always
entangled. One solution might be to
deliberately break with conventions of legitimate
knowledge to produce what Lather calls '"doubled
science", or new feminist ethnography, where the
aim is to show the failures of existing
representation and '"about troubling the very
claims to represent"'(11). Feminist
ethnography has addressed these issues of
'textuality and disciplinary history' as well as
using more personal data sources, to avoid writing
which is exploitative and which ignores 'the power
imbalances of research situations', aiming at
transparency while avoiding a mastery. In
the case of Lather this produces a new landscape
for research of partial truths suspension and
undecidability, '" stammering"'.
R by contrast offers a partial truth [but without
these hang ups] [he has certainly never lacked
confidence!]. Hey explore some of the issues
through 'academic melancholia', a Freudian term to
describe the ways in which feminists write about
their own working class origins [and they include
Walkerdine]. There is a challenge from
poststructuralist notions of the subject, but
autobiography in research still maintains some
sort of '"passionate attachment"'(13) kind of
taking a melancholic form. This resembles
the 'research landscape in ruins' of Lather
above. Research is seen as 'bearing witness
to the lives of marginalized others'[Lather seems
to find in this sort of project a relief from post
structuralist critique and to get back to
emancipation, 13, displaying a 'tension between
emancipatory desires and post structuralist
suspicions'].
Rancière does not have this sort of scientific
melancholia, rather developing 'a heroic allure'
in the great project to redistribute the
sensible. He still sees a role for academic
writing in politics and agency—'academic writing
can instantiating quality by reconstituting the
world', denying 'post' skepticism. There is
no self doubt, leading to no 'space for examining
the effect of verifying equality beyond the text',
just simply opening our eyes. Academic work
can 'instantiate quality by reconstituting the
world' in the old ambitions before the
posts. There is no self doubt. There
is even some doubt about ideological post
structuralist research, since, for R, 'there is
nothing to understand, there are only things to be
said about the world'[apparently in Ignorant
Schoolmaster] [I think this is a
denial of social science in general, a consequence
of his totalizing critique]. [Amazingly]
'There are thus many similarities between
Rancière's methodological concerns and those of
contemporary feminist ethnography', although there
are 'differences in poetics': both disagree with
some strands of postmodernism.
Hey talks about melancholia, and this is similar
because there is an important 'affective dimension
of accounts' in R. There is a similarity
with Foucault in that affect is also distributed,
along with the sensible, by discourses. This
helps him challenge Bourdieu, especially in Distinction.
Difference in the aesthetics is read as a
protective strategy by the elite. It is used
to justify the position of the inheritors.
In this way, Bourdieu can be seen as helping to
'satisfy this rich clientele'(14). What Distinction
does is to force 'privileged readers to
contemplate the fascinating horror of popular
culture', while the lumpen proletariat can only
reproduce it. This is a version of the
platonic fantasy that there is a difference
between workers and thinkers. It arises,
despite Bourdieu's 'intolerance of hierarchy',
because disciplinary theory itself expresses
certain wants rather than modeling the world—'in
other words [it is] structured by fantasy'(14)
[presumably Plato's fantasy referred to
earlier?]. The point is not to address
fantasies at the individual level, but at the
level of discourse. To some extent, this
might be the same as the passionate attachments
described in Hey. However, the point is 'not
to get away from fantasy in academic writing, but
to structure it in more egalitarian ways' [Bizarre
and wriggly form of argument here to rescue Hey
from the criticisms aimed at Bourdieu].
What follows for the practice of educational
research? We find no prescriptions in R:
empirical research is fictional, 'the
demonstration of fantasy' and can disclose no
other material forces outside discourse.
This applies to constructivist epistemologies too
which cannot deliver even partial truths through
reflexivity. These are common in
ethnographic accounts.
R thinks his own research is 'unequivocally true,
fictional and structured by the political fantasy
of equality'. The terms are not mutually
exclusive, however. Much of the work can be
seen as a genealogy of research objects in the
social sciences—the poor, the image, the school,
the unconscious. Genealogical approaches
'fuse "truth" and "perfection" by demonstrating
the way in which truth emerges within historical
"regimes" of thought' (15). This method is
not the same as Foucault, however, since there is
no separation between the discourse of the past
and the discourse of the present, the data of
genealogies, and the writing of genealogies.
Genealogies are 'moments of enacted equality in
the construction of research objects', not
reconstructions as in Foucault, but interventions
in contemporary debates which 'intervene precisely
by collapsing the apparent oppositions in such
debates - in other words, by creating a situation
of mésentente'. We can see this in
the genealogy of the school, written as a
deliberate intervention in debates about how to
create a more egalitarian school system, with
republican universalism on the one hand, and
cultural inclusion on the other. Both
rationalized inequality. The story of
Jacotot revealed this contempt for the people in
both positions.
The work on the unconscious can be seen in a
similar way [French reference]. It is not
that Freud reduces or cites dubious
evidence. The point is that he 'turns a
literary "truth" into a scientific one',
incorporating literary works to argue that
phantasy is socially significant, and is not just
ignorance or a series of false beliefs.
Oedipus is central not just because it features
sex and incest, but because Oedipus does not know
he is committing incest and has to learn.
This is 'the model of knowledge as affect', when
knowledge is delivered in a particular situation
[ie not anything abstract]. Freud then turns
this into a common condition, the result of
childhood trauma. However, for R we see 'an
image of the unconscious as a statement of
equality', although it has been subsequently seen
as a particular scientific object helping to
'secure epistemic mastery over research
participants' (16). The account also argues
that equality can be understood as '"the capacity
to be verified by anybody"', also found in Proletarian
Nights, and the notion of equality as '"
indifferentiation of collective speech, a great
anonymous voice"', which 'invites comparison with
Lacan's Real'. The point is to show how
phantasy can be seen as knowledge and as endemic
to research, not the opposite of reality, and as
something with political salience. It is
about scientific research not just Freud.
For R, science has a different status, and
methodology is not just about discovering the
properties of an object of research, but rather
'building a stage and sustaining a spectacle', an
act, the configuration of the sensible. We
are interested in the affects of scientific
statements the way they produce divisions between
what can be seen and what can be said.
Ethics becomes more a matter of 'the poetics of
academic discourse and how they performatively
constitute the world' [very much like the abstract
notion of ethics in Deleuze?]. Ethnographic
accounts can reject positivism, and if science
constitutes the world not just understands it,
this removes the need for apology and any anxiety
over partial truths [because they still turn on
acknowledging positivism as the only way to
generate truth?]. Again relativism is
denied, however, but we are forced to display 'the
labour of articulating one's fantasies, or the
fantasies of one's disciplinary identity, and the
"wants" satisfied in return for producing
knowledge'[acknowledging the pleasures of academic
work?]. We should also recognise that we are
positing the other, addressing an ignorance [which
research implies].
A lot of educational research assumes a knowledge
of inequality and turns on policies or practices
to help those who are rendered unequal, developing
a fairer curriculum or assessment scheme.
'Rancière's work is an argument against these
problematics'.
What he does do is help us investigate
subjectification, to move away from the emphasis
on habitus and issues like student background and
how this leads to a different interactions in
schools. Arguments in favour of literacy,
for example, have used Bourdieu to show that there
are no universally valued forms of linguistic
competence. R would not disagree with the
diagnosis, but offers a different research
agenda. It's more optimistic than 'the
mournful tracing of an inescapable symbolic
violence' (17), not offering a better
future, but 'exuberantly anarchic'. This
opens more possibilities for researching
subjectification as the disruption of categories
found in education, classifications between
vocational and academic, gifted and talented
students and those with special needs, excellent
and satisfactory teachers. [Bourdieu on the
arbitrary would do all this of course]. This
is a parasitic endeavour. It is unlikely to
win research grants. It does at least open
possibilities for research in ways that no longer
rely on 'an ethic of increasing effectiveness or
of hermeneutic suspicion' [ie we can develop new
research programmes etc]
|
|