Notes
on: Ranciere, J. (2011) The
Emancipated Spectator, translated by
Gregory Elliott, London: Verso.
Dave Harris
Chapter one The Emancipated Spectator.
This book originated from reflections based on The Ignorant
Schoolmaster [IS, summarized,
1, and also 8-11], and led to a speculation about
the relationship between intellectual emancipation
and the issue of the spectator, breaking with the
usual discussions found even in
postmodernism. These usual notions had to be
reconstructed first, in terms of a 'general model
of rationality'(2), and theories relating to the
political implications of spectacle. These
amount to a classic 'paradox of the
spectator'—there is no theatre without a
spectator, but spectators are passive and
ignorant, unaware about the process of production
involved. 'To be a spectator was to be
separated from both the capacity to know and so
the power to act'. Two conclusions
follow—the theatre is a scene of illusion and
passivity, offering only spectacle and ignorance,
as in Plato, and this is mediated through a
particular 'optical machinery that prepares the
gaze for illusion and passivity'(3). For
Plato, true communities avoided theatrical
mediation, and preferred instead direct community
thought and action.
This action has persisted into modern theatrical
critics, some of whom have suggested a different
kind of theatre instead, where barriers between
performers and spectators are broken down, and the
'passive optical relationship' replaced by a more
dramatic one—'Drama means action'. The
audience is to be mobilized by the bodies on
stage, by performance, intelligence and energy as
an active power, with only active
participants. In one version, the spectator
must empathise with the characters on the stage,
offered a mystery to resolve, or 'an exemplary
dilemma' of the kind facing all human
beings. In another version, the distance
itself 'must be abolished', where audiences are
drawn into theatrical action. Brecht and
Artaud represent the alternatives in terms of
developing distance for the one and foregoing
distance for the other, refining the gaze or
abandoning 'the very position of viewer' (5).
However, both ironically support Plato's critique,
replacing the evils of theatre with community [in
Plato's case 'the choreographic community', where
everyone follows the community rhythm]. This
division is preserved in the current distinction
between the theatre and the spectacle, and the
audience been transformed into the
community—'"theatre" is an exemplary community
form', the community is self conscious not
distanced through representation, 'the body in
action' (6). The theatre is seen as a
particularly potent way to do this, to make
ordinary people become conscious, 'the purifying
ritual in which a community is put in possession
of its own energies', breaking with mimesis.
The critique of the spectacle in DeBord supports
this view, with the spectacle as a matter of 'self
- dispossession'. The approach seems to be
anti-Platonic, derived from Marx through Feuerbach
on religion, and depending on the 'Romantic vision
of truth as non-separation'. However,
Plato's notion of mimesis remains, 'contemplation
of the appearance separated from its truth' (7), a
contemplation of an alien version of
activity. All that happens is that Plato's
prohibition of theatre is now changed into a
policy of reform, but the principles, equivalences
and presuppositions remain. Theatre blames itself
for rendering spectators passive and therefore
sees itself as the only way to reverse these
effects by restoring ownership to the audience,
leading to 'the virtue of true theatre' which does
not mediate. The theatre itself breaks
spectators out of the passivity and makes them
want to act, alienating them for Brecht, or
forcing them to participate for Artaud.
This is the link with intellectual
emancipation. This is the pedagogical
relationship criticized in IS.
Pedagogues must constantly recreate distance in
the very activity of reducing it, constantly
combating ignorance by always being 'one step
ahead' (8). Ignorance is not just a matter
of lacking concepts, but ignorance of what people
do not know nor how to know, and schoolmasters
know how to develop knowledge. Ignoramuses
have knowledge, but it is not ordered and
stratified, and it is extended at random through
comparisons with what is already known: it is not
a matter merely of accumulating knowledge [lots of
hints of the distinctions between surface and deep
approaches here]. The nature and depth of
ignorance is not realized, except by
schoolmasters. For them, ignorance is the
opposite of knowledge, unbridgeable except through
pedagogy, a matter of 'two intelligences: one that
knows what ignorance consists in and one that does
not'(9). This radical difference is the
first thing that progressive teaching teaches,
which implies the inability of the pupil without
pedagogy—this 'is what Jacotot calls
stultification'. It follows that
intellectual emancipation requires 'the
verification of the equality of intelligence' in a
radical form, the intelligences that all human
beings possess, shown in the way in which they
learn before they get to school. This is
'comparing one thing with another, a sign with a
fact, a sign with another sign' (10)—for example,
teaching an illiterate by comparing a prayer she
knows by heart with the words of this prayer
written down. This is no different from the
way in which scientists operate—'the same
intelligence is always at work', a matter of
translating signs into other signs, developing
through comparisons and illustrations,
understanding other intelligences, and
communicating one's own: a 'poetic labour of
translation'.
This is what the ignorant schoolmaster does
instead of preserving 'stupefying distance'.
Distance is normal to any communication, and human
beings have learned to overcome it, to
'communicate through the forest of signs'.
This is the normal path to knowledge from what is
already known, the art of translation, of
expressing experience, translation and
counter-translation. The ignorant
schoolmaster is not someone who knows nothing, but
rather someone who has 'renounced the "knowledge
of ignorance"' (11), and separated mastery from
knowledge. Pupils do not learn his
knowledge, but learn how to see, and think of what
they have seen. There is no inequality of
intelligence. Distances are factual matters,
and can be combated by 'the path traced between a
form of ignorance and a form of knowledge', and
this does not take the form of fixed positions or
hierarchies.
Modern theatre no longer explains to audiences
what the truth might be, but presuppositions
remain. New forms of theatre possibly even
increase the pressure on spectators to think for
themselves, after their passive attitude has been
disrupted. This is the same stance as the
pedagogue, however, assuming two initial positions
separated by some gulf. However, the very
fact of desiring to abolish distance also 'creates
it' (12), by assuming the spectator is passive and
inactive in the first place, and assuming that
spectators were only there to pursue pleasure in
'images and appearances' and are not interested in
the truth, or seeing speech as 'the opposite of
action'. These are not logical or natural
oppositions but offer an unfortunate 'distribution
of the sensible, an a priori distribution
of the positions and capacities and incapacities
attached to these positions. They are embodied
allegories of inequality'. The value of the
specific positions can be reversed, but the
opposition remains.
There is also still a distinction between those
who have these radical ideas and take a
comprehensive view, and mere practitioners.
This goes back to the old notion of property
owners as active citizens, while mere workers were
passive ones, and these two categories
remain. Emancipation involves challenging
this opposition, questioning this implicit
structure, seeing that 'viewing is also an action'
(13), and spectating also involves selection,
comparison and interpretation—'She composes her
own poem where the elements of the poem before
her'. Spectating is participation. It
involves withdrawing from the intentions of the
performance 'in order to make it a pure image',
which can be given personal associations.
Spectators 'compose their own poem' just as much
as actors and dancers or performers [if they have
the cultural capital that is? Otherwise they
pastiche popular culture? Of course, R is right to
argue that capacities are not identical to
social categories].
[A curious example as evidence here, observations
of participants in a Shiite religious drama.
The contemporary example might be spectators faces
at football matches? Incidentally, try the account
of wacky and pretty aggressive Danish
participatory theatre in Sundbo
and Darmer, ch.10].
Pedagogues insist on some notion of uniform
transmission to be conveyed, so that pupils and
spectators can only learn what it is they are
supposed to be being taught. Ignorant
schoolmasters break with this system, splitting
their energy and enthusiasm from their mastery of
knowledge: the latter 'forces [the pupil] to
search and verifies this research'(14).
Artists will often deny that they wish to
instruct. They claim they are producing
consciousness and intensity, but this still is
supposed to be conveyed only by the dramatic
performance: there is a cause and effect notion
here and this is itself 'based on an inegalitarian
principle', that the pedagogue/artist knows best
how to abolish distance. What is not grasped
is that the performance itself is also different
from these pedagogic intentions, as 'an autonomous
thing, between the idea of the artist and the
sensation or comprehension of the spectator'. In
order to pursue emancipation, there is always 'a
third thing—a book or some other piece of writing—
alien to both [pedagogy and pupil] and to which
they can refer to verify in common what the pupil
has seen, what she says about it and what she
thinks of it' (15). This third thing, and
its meanings, is owned by no one.
Emancipation is not a matter of allowing
individuals to reappropriate something that they
have lost. We find this in DeBord's critique
of the spectacle, Feuerbach on religion and Marx's
notion of alienation. For these people, the
third term only pretends to offer autonomy but it
is contaminated by 'dispossession and its
concealment'. Radical theatre abolishes the
distance between audience and players, or takes
performances outside of theatres and offers a
redistribution of places, and some interesting
performances, but it is mistaken to think that
this will create some new community who will
penetrate alienation and the spectacle [same
follows for progressive especially community
pedagogy?].
Directors think that if they can abolish the
immediate hierarchy between actors and spectators,
a proper community will emerge, one that is quite
different from the passive audiences for
television and film, even though electronic images
are incorporated increasingly in theatre.
This is a [behaviourist, positivist] mistake,
since 'the mass of individuals watching the same
television show at the same hour' can also be
interactive and communitarian (16).
Conversely, the audience for the theatre is still
'only ever individuals plotting their own paths in
the forest of things, acts and signs that confront
or surround them'. If there is a collective
power, it is this general capacity to make sense
on an individual level, to pursue a 'unique
intellectual adventure that makes [the individual
spectator] similar to all the rest in as much as
this adventure is not like any other'[abstract and
idealist in my view, and very uncritical].
We all display performances, including spectating,
and these demonstrate our anonymous capacities
that make 'everyone equal to everyone else',
emerging through 'an unpredictable interplay of
associations and dissociations' (17) [it is just
assumed that these are individual, of course]. It
is normal for us to be active interpreters, and
'we all learn and teach, act and know'. We
encounter 'constant starting points intersections
and junctions' between things that we know,
between boundaries and territories and between
roles. Every spectator is also an actor, and
vice versa.
R's personal experience shows this. He was
exposed to progressive pedagogues who wanted to
prepare him for struggle [Althusser], and he also
encountered those who thought intellectuals lived
in ivory towers and needed to be taught by workers
[students went off and worked in factories --
these radical options for maoists are discussed in
Reid's Introduction to Proletarian Nights].
R was not convinced by either, and preferred to
undertake some history of the working class
movement [!] to find out how workers and
intellectuals had interrelated.
Investigating the correspondence of workers in the
1830s leads him to see how two Saint-Simonians
spent their time when not at work—this included
cultural activities in the evening, and
fascinating walks in the countryside. This
is not just recreation but 'the leisure of
aesthetes who enjoy the landscape's forms…
Of philosophers who settle into a country inn to
develop metaphysical hypotheses… Of apostles
who apply themselves to communicating their faith
to all the chance companions encountered' (19)
[danger of talk up here, obviously]. Reading
these accounts persuaded R of a fundamental
equality, and of the critical stance towards their
own social class activities [sad git -- didn't he
know any clever proles personally beforehand
then?]. There was no barrier between working
and contemplation in leisure: they were spectators
and visitors of their own lives. This
disrupted the distribution of the sensible, and
blurred the boundaries between actors and
spectators, individuals and members of the
collective. Leisure activity was not just
tied to work, but was 'the reconfiguration in the
here and now of the distribution of space and
time, work and leisure'[cries out for Parker's stuff on the
relations between work conditions and leisure
activities, which included 'extension' as well as
neutral and oppositional forms]. The workers
were intellectuals 'as is anyone and everyone'
(20), no different from the researcher who read
the letters in the library, or from Marxist
theorists and activists [Hammersley would be good
here -- there is a difference between codifed and
systematic intellectual activity and
experience etc -- mere pedagogic ideology
for R or rejected on a priori political or
axiomatic grounds?].
Given this blurring of boundaries, the problem
emerged on how to tell the story. R found it
necessary to compare the workers story to the
model in Plato's Republic [so it wasn't
that Platonism had survived and been detected in
later positions, more that it helps him tell the
story as a kind of trope?]. The resultant
account blurs the boundaries between history and
philosophy, and between levels of discourse.
It was not a matter of developing a factual
narrative accompanied by a philosophical
explanation. Instead, what was required was
a 'work of translation', between the
workers' letters and philosophical
discourse. In turn this meant developing a
new idiom, even if this remained 'unintelligible
to all those who requested the meaning of this
story, the reality that explained it, and the
lesson it contained for action. In fact,
this idiom could only be read by those who were
translated on the basis of their own intellectual
adventure' (21). [Unfortunately, Proletarian
Nights is also elitist in the scholarly and
literary commentary on worker letters and press
articles -- give me EP Thompson any day]
In the domain of modern art, barriers have been
lowered. Techniques and skills swap places,
leading to theatre without speech, installations,
photographs as historical tableaux, sculpture as
multimedia and so on. These practices can be
explained in various ways:
- the re-emergence of
the notion of the total artwork, although this
is now associated with artistic celebrities or
consumerism rather than arts become life;
- a general postmodernism,
affecting all forms of life, but with similar
consequences—'it often leads to a different
form of stultification, which uses the
blurring of boundaries and the confusion of
roles to enhance the effect of the performance
without questioning its principles'[so
Ranciere's tastes intrude here? Art has
to have some underlying principle or serious
intent?];
- a new way to call into
question cause and effects relationships and
to attack the logic of stultification.
The latter wants to revitalize the theatre as
community, to make it equal to the other arts,
to see it as a new kind of equality 'when
heterogeneous performances are translated into
one another' (22), breaking the barrier
between performer and spectator as above,
producing intellectual adventure with emergent
consequences. This will require
'spectators who play the role of active
interpreters'[avoided like the plague by
normal people is my guess].
This whole argument could just be seen as so many
words and empty formulae, but words still have a
value in this debate that often relies on
installations and spectacles or religious
mysteries. [almost a plea for systematic and
coded knowledge?]. We need to know that words are
merely words, and spectacles merely spectacles, so
that we might be able to 'change something of the
world we live in' (23).
Chapter two The Misadventures of Critical
Thought
Is the classic tradition of social and cultural
critique gone? No one believes in a reality
as opposed to appearances, nor in a dark side of
consumer society. However, the critical
tradition is still required, although applied in a
different way, to invert the usual notions of
interpretation.
These usual notions are still found, for example
in the idea that art reflects the state of the
world, criticizes globalization, or war [examples
25-27]. One major tradition is collage and
photomontage which clashes heterogeneous elements:
surrealists used to think that this will expose
the workings of unconscious desire underneath
normal reality. Marxist traditions used it
to show how class violence underpinned apparent
peaceful societies, as in the Vietnam war
[Rosler's example below]
Later efforts also intended to make spectators
feel guilty at our own complicity for not wanting
to grasp or act on hidden realities. Some
photomontages served to criticize middle class
demonstrators in this way, by photographing them
with evidence of their own consumerism [the
example is the installations of Josephine
Meckseper, 28, below:], or that political protest
is a form of youth culture, that modern politics
itself is based on the consumption of images and
spectacles, and it constructs spectacles of its
own.
This seems to rule out any kind of critique based
on contrasts with the present reality, although
even the demonstrators can be shown yet another
reality, including their own complicity in the
spectacle—the ideas of revelation and shame are
still present. This shows the [dialectical]
contradictions in critique, as the features of
earlier critique become incorporated leading to
further critique. Apparently, Sloterdijk
sees modernity in this way, as 'a process of
antigravitation' (30). First there is the
familiar argument that the solid industrial world
has been replaced by communication and virtual
reality, but secondly, a source of critique and
unease, 'gravity' has also been lost, or at least
replaced by nostalgia for solidity, a matter of
'necessary illusion'. The process works as a
kind of reverse of Marx on Feuerbach—the current
'generalized lightening' is projected on to some
'fiction of a solid reality' as an inverted
image. This is also a way of coping with
guilt and embarrassment. There are echoes of the Manifesto
on the solid melting into air, and Marxist
critiques can now be denounced and laughed at as
ideological.
Even this analysis does not break with a critical
tradition, because it still argues that we are
engaged in some illusion, ignorant of the actual
processes at work in the 'dematerialization of
wealth' (31). Productive processes still
seem to be evolving and having irresistible
effects, even though these are denied.
Political intent is different, however, no longer
aimed at emancipation, but 'disconnected' (32) or
positively hostile.
60's radicals can now be seen as having been
recuperated. Godard, for example criticized
Vietnam protestors as '"children of Marx and
Coca-Cola"', but he has now become incorporated
into the system himself, 'the infamous father who
testifies to the shared infamy of the
children'. Other Marxists, including
Gramsci, saw the Soviet revolution as breaking
with the logic of Capital which had been
captured by 'bourgeois scientism'.
Rancière's generation can also be seen in this
way, originally denouncing commodification and
consumerism, but now offering 'the disenchanted
knowledge of the reign of the commodity and the
spectacle, of the equivalence between everything
and everything else and between everything and its
own image' [presumably he has Baudrillard in
mind]. However, this still makes domination
as an all powerful force even though this is not
recognized. Futility is accompanied with 'a
demonstration of culpability' (33). Leftwing
denunciations of commodities are now seen as fully
incorporated, even if melancholic and
ironic. Meanwhile, a new right wing critique
has emerged, focusing on individuals, sometimes
critically.
For the left wing critique, we are still either
fully incorporated into the belly of the beast,
seen in the popularity of reality shows on TV, or
the drive for self enhancement.
Spokespersons here include Boltanksi and
Chiappello on the new spirit of capitalism: the
revolt of 68 only energized capitalism, directed
its attention to disenchantment and encouraged
artistic responses, and diverted attention from
social and economic critique. A capitalist
flexibility, weightless innovation, and 'appeal to
individual initiative and the "projective city"'
have been the result.
However, this confuses managerial discourse with
the reality of contemporary capitalism.
There are still serious struggles over the notion
of labour flexibility, for example, despite the
attempts to make it look like human
creativity. In May '68, the demand was not
so much for creative work, as for rejection of
capitalism. So the new left theory of
collusion 'is not based on any analysis of
historical forms of protest' (35). Bourdieu
gets blamed here again, with his notion that the
workers struggle against misery and for community,
while only the big or petty bourgeoisie are
interested in autonomous creativity.
Instead, social emancipation is always mixed up
with aesthetic emancipation, free collectivity,
and 'the discovery of individuality for
all'. This would disrupt notions of class
and identity, but sociology has never accepted
this view, owing to its own ideological roots in
the 19th century. Sociologists saw '68 as a
matter of unwanted disorder and disruption
compared to the 'rightful distribution of classes,
their ways of being and forms of action'.
A 'melancholic' leftism has developed, denouncing
the power of capital, but also the illusions of
those who think they are opposing it.
Artistic revolts get recuperated. Change
looks impossible in a liquid or immaterial world
[with a reference to Bauman]. Again,
Bauman's prediction that even war would become
more liquid has clearly not been borne out since
2000 when he wrote the book. There are some
radical developments, like those involving 'the
mass defection of the forces of the general
intellect' (36) [Virno], or virtual subversion to
undermine virtual capitalism [somebody called
Brian Holmes]. There is also 'inverted
activism', recapturing the energies of
capital. Generally though, melancholy
triumphs because it 'feeds on its own
impotence', and still maintains its privileged
position in interpreting the system.
The new 'right wing frenzy' sees the current
market and media as ravaging the individual, free
to pursue their own lives only within the
constraints of the free market. Western
capitalism could be seen to be representing
democratic values until the collapse of the the
Soviet Union. The critique takes the form of the
denunciation of human rights, which has gone too
far, and led to rampant consumerism, egoism, and
an attack on authority, taking the form of the
domination of the market. Again, the
radicals of '68 are blamed for attacking the old
authority and only releasing rampant
individualism. This led to'the destruction
of social and human bonds', and therefore a new
totalitarianism. Specific acts of terror
such as 9/11 were even seen as a punishment for
destroying the old symbolic order 'encapsulated in
homosexual marriage' (39). Market democracy
is boundless and imperialist. It led to the
extermination of the Jews as a source of
resistance based on the old loyalties.
French rioters were consumers who had got out of
hand [shades of that with the Tottenham
riots in the UK], and individualism made
them vulnerable to Islamist fanatics. The
critique of consumption therefore escalated into
'the crudest themes of the clash of civilisations
and the war on terror' (40).
Both left and right critiques can be seen as an
inversion of original [Marxist] criticism of
consumerism. [It was Hegel who] criticized
the French Revolution on the same lines, as
destroying collective institutions and social
bonds, as a result of excessive Enlightenment, and
protestant individualism. Marxism also drew from
this argument, however, in the critique of human
rights and bourgeois revolution posing as
democracy and destroying the social fabric.
In this way, right wing critics were able to
incorporate Marxist critique.
Social and cultural critique continues, but in an
inverted form. It returns to the notion of
modernity as excessive individualism, and
therefore reproduces the tensions between
modernity and social emancipation. That
tension has been solved by abandoning the notion
of emancipation! It is worth returning to
the notions of emancipation as 'emergence from a
state of minority' (42). The state of
minority meant an orderly community, however,
where everyone was in their place, doing what was
appropriate to their class, as in Plato.
This is the '" police distribution of the
sensible"' (42), where capacities are neatly
related to social forms. Originally,
emancipation meant breaking this link, disrupting
the categories, fashioning new kinds of working
bodies, not tied to specific occupation, and with
universal capacities.
This notion of emancipation was attacked by among
others the young Marx. Alienation had
developed in a shattered society, dominated
by wealth and power that had been abstracted
and concentrated. It followed that
emancipation meant a reappropriation of what had
been lost. That in turn required adequate
knowledge of the processes of separation.
Any attempts to emancipate in the old sense could
be seen as illusory and ignorant of what had gone
on. Emancipation now lay on the other side
of the social revolution. Emancipation
depended on the promise of science, although
science never finished with definitive
results—'the science of the total process whose
effect is endlessly to generate its own ignorance'
(44), endlessly unmasking new forms of illusion
and subjection. It lead to work like Mythologies
and Society of the Spectacle, aimed at
endlessly deciphering the deception of
images. But the same time, there was, among
intellectuals [including Barthes in the new
semiology], an 'assertion that there was no
longer any room for distinguishing between image
and reality'. Illusion was seen as
inevitable as a consequence of the functioning of
capitalism. In Society of the the
Spectacle, the point is not to see images as
concealing reality, but to see the generation of
spectacle as the goal of social activity, with
social wealth as a separate reality. Victims
are like the prisoners in Plato's cave, taking
image for reality, and remaining ignorant about
the generation of wealth and inequality.
However, it is the science used to denounce the
spectacle that also becomes impotent, with even
the notion of truth and critique becoming
recuperated. This led to
postmodernism. Modernist critique followed
the transition into a postmodern nihilism, which
offers the same readings. Critical science
drew from a belief that a secret remained at the
heart of social reproduction, but nihilism makes
this irrelevant [maybe, 45]. This was always
a danger with critical science, and it lies behind
the disconnection with emancipation discussed
above.
Further critical moves can not involve any more
inversions, but require a whole new reexamination
of concepts and their links with social
emancipation. In particular it is important
to criticize a central feature in the critique
'the poor cretin of an individual consumer',
only manipulated by consumerism. This figure
was strengthened by anti individualistic trends,
including those in 19th century physiology, where
the simplicity and unity of the soul was
challenged, and in psychology, where brains were
seen as offering '"a polyp of images"'(46).
This quantitative turn coincided with a new
quantitative conception involving 'the
multiplicity of those individuals without
qualities', seen as the new and worrying subject
of democracy. A panic arose, about
overstimulation of brains, excessive knowledge
distributed to people who could not use it,
excessive nervous energy and unknown appetites,
the dangers of providing any one with 'materials
liable to contribute to the reconfiguration of her
life world'(47). Unpredictable encounters
did lead to demands for emancipation in the
original sense, and elites were right to worry
about 'popular experimentation with new forms of
life: Emma Bovary and the International
Workingmen's Association'. Anxiety lead to
paternal solicitude, and dissatisfaction with
ordered society was seen as 'an inability to judge
situations'.
Such assumptions were built into the new social
sciences, and fitted well the anxieties about the
production of commodities and illusions. The
notion of incapacity was also reproduced.
Social critique has long been aimed at 'treating
the incapable'. It was in the interests of
social scientist to reproduce these incapacities,
and to extend them. At first, people could
not distinguish image from reality, and now they
have been educated to do so, and the 'imbeciles'
now cling to this old notion of in distinction
between image and reality, unlike sophisticated
intellectuals. This can be extended
unendingly, 'capitalizing on the impotence of the
critique that unveils the impotence of the
imbeciles' (48).
Instead of the endless reversals and inversions,
we need a new approach, one which separates
emancipatory logic and capacity from the notion of
recuperation. We need different
presuppositions and assumptions, even if these are
unreasonable, both to defenders of the system and
to critics. We should assume a general
capacity, with no hidden secret mechanisms to
reproduce social order or transform a reality into
image, and no 'lost community to be
restored'. What we are left with is 'simply
scenes of dissensus' which are everywhere.
Dissensus involves a new organization of the
sensible, with no hidden reality or single
truthful regime agreed by all. 'Every
situation can be cracked open from the inside' and
reconfigured. Thus will emerge new
possibilities and capacities. Dissensus
challenges what seems obvious, and brings into
being political subjects. Emancipation
really involves not collective understanding of
the processes of subject shown, but 'the
collectivization of capacities invested in scenes
of dissensus'(49), energising the capacity of
'anyone whatsoever'. These seem
unreasonable, but we should do more to investigate
the power of subjectivation rather than endlessly
critique fetishes or demonstrate the omnipotence
of capitalism. [so we have moved from Marx's
critique to Foucaldian or discursive critique --
another intellectualizing trend, of course, easily
bolted on to the old processes described above --
gap between image and reality leads to no
difference between image and reality leads to new
model of discourse to explain both image and
reality, with intellectuals in the vanguard
arguing their interests are really everyone's
interests].
Chapter three Aesthetic Separation, Aesthetic
Community
[heavy going!]
We can offer three 'propositions about community
and separation'(51). The first [and
second—they are not clearly distinguished]
proposition is expressed in a poem by Mallarmé,
where the hero decides not to visit his lady after
all, in order to preserve her mystery and some
higher sense of being together by being apart
[prat] . It might be that only poets with
'refined sensations' are capable of such feelings,
although we can also see the same argument
displayed in paintings by Seurat [bathers etc] ,
and other collisions between high art and popular
leisure. The proposition takes on particular
force because of contemporary urban diversity
which alters every day of relations. A group
of modern French artists photographs people in the
riotous areas of Paris, and depicts solitude,
'solitary contemplation or meditation' (53), an
aesthetic place, a separation that accompanies
ordinary life. Inhabitants chose a sentence
to be printed on a T shirt and they were then
photographed. The sentences depict a wish to
be alone, or a wish to develop a particular
utterance [examples 53, 54]. These also tell
us something about the modern social crisis, how
even underdogs in poor suburbs can wish to be
separate and isolated, the reverse of the usual
formulation about how individualism has destroyed
social bonds.
The third proposition is derived from Deleuze and
Guattari What Is
Philosophy?, on how art attempts to
separate percepts from perceptions, and affects
from affections, sensations from opinions.
It is sensation that links individuals and
communities through artwork as 'a new sensory
fabric' which can act as a new form of expression
of the community. The sensory fabric is
responsible for the empirical sensations, and it
is the same as what R means by 'a certain
distribution of the sensible' (56).
Individual artworks can involve an intertwining of
sensations, just as a collective can. In
Deleuze and Guattari, the process involves the
generation of a 'vibration' from the artwork which
is transmitted to the community. Artwork and
social life itself involves 'seizing and rending:
suffering, resistance, cries'. Artworks can
be seen as a monument expressing the vibration,
but also taking on the identity of a person.
Nevertheless, it is the impersonal transmission
that relates to the community. Is this just
an analogy between the actualization of colours
and sounds in art, and the 'health' of the
community? Is it that art somehow expresses
some goal of weaving the community together?
Even an absent community? The artwork still
occupies an intermediary status between the drive
to community in harmony, and specific human
divisions and harmonies. If the artistic
voice of the people exists, it is 'the voice of a
people to come', an 'impossible' new community,
both representing people divided by protest and
collective harmony 'in tune with the very breath
of nature, be it of a chaotic or "chaosmatic"
nature'(57).
Together, these comments defined the aesthetic
community in general, not a specific community of
aesthetes, a 'sensus communis'. These exist
at three levels
- a combination of sense
data or, forms words and spaces, involving a
combination of different senses, the use of
metaphor, for example, or a political
statement like the inhabitants who printed
sentences on their T shirts. This level
offers 'a "dissensual figure"' (58), where two
specific sensoria appear [roughly, one actual
and one turning on particular artistic
combinations of sound and absence, 'two
sensory worlds' in conflict].
- Philosophers supply the
second level [by describing or discussing the
tension? As in Deleuze and
Guattari?]. Artists are happy to simply
conflict two regimes of sense, and to relate
this dissenting artistic community [I think
'assemblage' would be a better word to use
here] to the human community.
- The new sense of
community is supposed to be built by relating
artistic data and an artistic assemblage with
its contradictory relations to some
'democratic community', not found in actual
social engagements or crowds, but possessing
an abstract capacity to develop in the
future. The sentences on T shirts again
indicate both the new basis for social
relations and 'a new awareness of the capacity
of anyone and everyone'(59) aimed at the
future. [Philosophical] discussion
brings out this potential. This new
[human] community both arises from the
vibrations of artistic practice, and serves as
a potential development or 'expectation' of
the artistic monument. Art has to be
both apart from existing communities and aimed
at being together in some anticipated future
[maybe, 59]. Art also offers a tension
between acting as a means to produce an effect
and becoming the reality of that effect
itself. The aesthetic community [in the
first sense?] 'is a community structured by
disconnection'.
Understanding these connections and disconnections
is central to the politics of aesthetics.
Modernist views seen art as autonomous [from the
present community], and it is this autonomy that
connects it with a future community.
Postmodernism argues that any being apart is 'an
aristocratic illusion', and this can turn artwork
'into a radical heterogeneity', representing the
real human condition suppressed by the modernist
dream of community.
However, there is another sense of aesthetic
disconnection—'the aesthetic break'(60).
This is normally seen as a break with
representation or 'the mimetic regime'.
However, representation means something different,
'a regime of concordance between sense and
sense'[not art and reality]. In classic
theatre, for example the stage let spectators see
the characteristics of human beings in fictional
form, and this was supposed to change their minds,
to teach them something. 'Intellectual
recognition and appropriate emotion' assumed the
regime of concordance. Performance offered
unambiguous signs, following the grammar of nature
itself. This was called mimesis, a
concordance that permits artistic activity
[actually, poiesis]. The concordance
and activity together constituted aesthetics for
the Greeks—mimesis is what allows
correspondence 'between poiesis and aisthesis'(61).
The underlying natural language of signs combined
the action of the play and the effects on the
spectators, and their subsequent behaviour, so the
separation of the stage was still part of the
continuity between the signs, the community, and
human nature itself.
Much politics of art still involves this model, as
when we believe that critical artwork makes us
critical of the spectacle or of injustice.
However, Rousseau had long criticized this view,
pointing out that plays actually offered ambiguous
messages, with different characters to identify
with. Theatre was in no place to expose
hypocrisy, since it is fundamentally hypocritical
itself. Later work, in Schiller, denied the
continuity of human nature and representation,
since thoughts no longer appears as clear signs on
bodies, and nor did performances of bodies have
predictable effects on other bodies.
Aesthetics came to mean something different, based
on this 'rupture of the harmony that enabled
correspondence' (62).
This rupture led to two
responses.
- One was to replace
mimetic mediation with 'the immediate ethical
performance of a collective', without
separation between performers and spectators,
as in the Greek civic festivals, and the
choros, Plato's critique of the theatre and so
on. This option was taken up by Rousseau
and led to the modern critique of
representation, and new experiments to
reintroduce choros, and invite
audiences to take part in a general fusion of
the senses [example on 63].
- Hypertheatre like this
was easily recuperated as a spectacle, leading
to the critique of the spectacle, expecting
that art will offer a more than a
spectacle, some notion of an active
society.
However, there is another option—'aesthetic
efficacy itself', which emerges from the 'very
rupturing of any determinate link between cause
and effect'. This is what Kant meant by the
beautiful as being an object of universal delight
but with no concept. This was sometimes
taken to be equating beauty with harmony, as
opposed to the sublime, which is the real break
with representation, but it was already a radical
departure from representation by arguing that no
concept could grasp the beautiful, and therefore
no poetic concept is in harmony with the
aesthetic. Art entails concepts, but not the
beautiful, disconnecting artistic fabrication and
the enjoyment of the product.
An example of a classic statue makes the point,
taken as a masterpiece, but rejected by modernists
as nostalgic or romantic, offering a dubious
utopian community as a work of art which could
easily be turned into a total society.
Rancière wants to revive the paradox of seeing a
statue of a crippled man is the embodiment of
classical beauty, especially as it was allegedly a
statue of Hercules, but obviously Hercules after
his labour and strength:
Somehow, this depiction express the notion that
Hercules was meditating on his past actions, and
is an expression of liberty, although none of this
is directly depicted except in the particular
curves and waves of the stone. In other
words, it does not follow a representational
logic. It offers a sense of
displacement. Although the body is
mutilated, the claim is that the art is perfect.
This is taken up in modern dance which did not
express capacities in any functional sense.
The same might be said about Greek poetry, in
Homer, for example, whose songs express a time and
people before they could articulate fully concepts
in language. All this refers to what Kant
meant by the beautiful.
There might be a link with the body without organs
in Deleuze, something that speaks to the future,
offers potential including the potential of
political liberty, but Deleuze is still committed
to the notion that is the sublime that offers the
real break with representation, ignoring earlier
examples of dissensual art and beauty.
Dissensus of this kind is specific to aesthetic
work and beauty. It superimposes one form or
body into another one, an actual sculpture or
Greek poem into an ideal one. Modern
choreography does the same subtracting actual
qualities from bodies, even movement itself, in
order to 'release the potentialities of new, as
yet unseen bodies' (67). Mallarmé also
infers the mute language in dance, others have
taken Wagnerian characters and made them into
geometric modules and shadows.
This is 'the art of the mise-en-scène'(67)
which expresses this logic, transforming presence,
subtracting and disconnecting from actual context
and representational mediation. We're not
talking about modernist truth nor Deleuzian pure
sensations, but rather 'a fictional ontology, or
play of "aesthetic ideas"'(67), a possible new set
of relations. In this way, actual works can
be seen as substitutes for underlying [virtual]
works that express better the law of the medium or
the sensation.
Film can be seen in this way as 'the pure writing
of motion' (68). Godard really sees the
potential of film by using another medium, video,
to break with 'filmic identity' and
'cinematographic montage', and introduce
discontinuity, and more mobile forms of
superimposition, new relations to sound and
music. The Histories of Cinema show
how actual cinematic works relate to a fictional
cinema that oversteps them and is best depicted in
another medium.
Just as the work itself is an assemblage of
different sensations [still called, confusingly, a
"community of sense"], so is the human community
that is supposed to result from it. Though
the artist claims to address the community of the
future, the product must look really like
something that has disappeared already and is
separated. Mimetic efficacy and hypertheatre
made different claims to relate to community, but
things like the statue of Hercules do not speak,
do nothing, and offer no 'model for imitation'
(69). There is no social ritual to give it
meaning. In the museum—'which refers not
only to a specific building but also to a form of
apportioning the common space and a specific mode
of visibility'—exhibits are disconnected, and the
gaze of the spectator is indifferent. Works
are torn from context, and from their originating
relations to communities. There is a tension
between aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic
education, and the 'happy dream of a community
united and civilized by the contemplation of
eternal beauty'.
The creation of the museum, with its accompanying
construction of aesthetic experience, involves a
separation of art from its functions and
destinations in a separated 'aesthetic sensorium'
(70). The original social context context
offered an orderly relation between social order
and capacity, as argued above, so that 'forms of
domination were a matter of sensory
inequality'. The Platonic myth of the metals
is an example. Artisans did not have to
believe in these myths, 'it was enough that they
sensed it and that they used their arms, their
eyes and their minds as if it were true', although
a correspondence between the myth and the reality
of their condition helped. We are back to
the notion of emancipation as an aesthetic matter,
disrupting this original sensed reality. An
example of this happening arose in a French
revolutionary paper 1848, where a joiner was
laying a floor, and imagined that it was his home
and garden, that he could enjoy it even better
than the actual owners [this ludicrously idealist
example is used a lot, in other work. It
seems to imply that any imaginative exchange of
places is the same as the real exchange of
places. It seems to offer support for the
Fiske view of popular media after all, where
Madonna fans genuinely do create a grounded
aesthetic from her absurd videos. Rancière
wants to talk this up by talking about 'the
appropriation of the place of work and
exploitation as the site of the free gaze.
It does not involve an illusion but is a matter of
shaping a new body and a new sensorium for one's
self']. Labouring arms were no longer
diverted from aesthetic gaze: there was a 'new
configuration of the sensible'.
The publishers of this piece in a revolutionary
newspaper saw all the political implication in
developing the voice of the workers as something
separate from the conventions of the worker's
body. The relation between capacities and
incapacities join together in an ethos that was
being challenged. That same joiner also read
romantic literature rather than political material
[Rose's study of the reading habits of the English
working class make this point too] . Such
literature does not inform workers about their
condition, but rather 'triggers new passions'
further breaking the conventional relation.
The writers concerned did not particularly want to
encourage these passions among labourers, so the
break with convention was something emergent.
This is how aesthetic experience produces
political effects, through disruptions of
conventions about connections between bodies and
capacities. It does not just offer rhetoric
or persuasion, and nor does it construct
community. It offers new connections and
disconnections that disrupt. 'It is a
multiplicity of folds and gaps in the fabric of
common experience' that produces new cartographies
and political constructions. It works
because the original conventional link between
cause and effect has been disrupted.
Aesthetic experience dis-identifies, and produces
'a community of dis-identified persons'
(73). This is unpredictable and
incalculable, beyond artistic strategy. New
forms of individuation, as 'Deleuzian
haecceities', emerge, breaking with political
subjection. Reading romantic literature
helps people join this dis-identified community
despite the intentions of the authors.
Revolutionary joiners, and current protesters in
the suburbs, are looking for words to express
their own projects, and find them among unwilling
writers. Those writers and other artists have
tried to break this emergent link, by claiming
that their work is impersonal and infinite.
Deleuze and Guattari can be included here, seeing
artistic practice as representing some neutral [?
ontology?] effect, denying any immediate political
effects.
Much critical art faces the same tension.
The aim is to establish a straightforward relation
between political goals and artistic means, to
make people aware so that they mobilize.
This is often done by making art strange and
heterogeneous, to break with convention, but there
is still a cause/effect relationship, with
artistic strangeness as the cause. Brecht [Arturo
Ui] and Martha Rosler's montages are
examples. But othernon-radical effects are
possible from this strangeness, and even
understanding the world as strange and
contradictory does not necessarily lead to
political action. Instead, we have a shift
to different configurations of sense, different
capacities and incapacities, 'processes of
dissociation' (75). 'Such breaks can happen
anywhere and at any time. But they cannot be
calculated'.
Critical art depends for its effect on existing
critical sensibilities and political forms, and
when these go, critical procedures are
exposed. They still persist though, and have
become standard forms, as in now-widespread parody
or pastiche. Critical art is still valued in
galleries and museums on the assumption that it
helps us understand the power of the commodity or
power itself. However, 'nobody is unaware of
these things' (76), so critical art itself becomes
'undecidable' [less linked to action,unsure of its
status], even reflective and self critical.
The critical model depended on the production of
awareness and the growth of a new community, and
it failed. One conclusion was that critical
work should directly present another form of
community directly among artists themselves [in
Cuban examples of arts in the community, where
people's homes are turned into art objects and
this is videoed and so on—examples 77].
Large mosaics of the photographs of people become
art, so that physical unity anticipates social
unity. Curators are eager to point out that
this is a metaphor, but this again assumes an
eventual community brought together by art.
Instead, art can be seen as representing the
tension between the apart and the together,
questioning the ways in which community is
produced, or is present as a potential [more
examples 78 F. A video is made of an example
of community art, which 'artifies' {my word,sorry}
actual houses, and favourable comments are
contrasted with shots of unreformed slums and
indifferent passers-by. Another video
focuses on the lives of slum dwellers, to examine
the 'possibilities of life and art' in interesting
objects and in the efforts of the inhabitants to
tell their own story: there is no attempt to raise
the political awareness of the viewer, nor to
dissolve the difference between life and art, but
it does show the aesthetic capacities of the
characters.]
These are classic examples of 'what we can expect
from the cinema or popular art of the 20th
century' (81). Of course there are also
conservative forms of cinema, which do not display
equality in sensible terms, but persist with
social categories. Commercial multiplexes
'supply each sociologically determinate audience
[with] a type of art designed and formatted
to suit it' (81) [sounds like Adorno on the culture industry].
Experimental films are classified as suitable only
for film festivals and a film buff elite.
People who make radical films are well aware of
this, that they will scarcely be shown, but they
persist, with 'inner division'. In general,
cinema can never directly represent the
conventional sensible world; it must always be
split and thus offer the chance to display
artistic experiments, new figures, new
experiences. This exteriority gives it its
political effects and helps overcome the
'formatted distribution of thoughts and sensations
to formatted audiences' (82). Perceptions
can be reworked, new passages opened, but there
must always be 'the aesthetic cut that separates
outcomes from intentions'.
Chapter four The Intolerable Image
We normally think of an intolerable image is one
that causes of pain or indignation.
Politically, the issue is whether we should
display these images, of anorexics or
atrocities. Critical artists might say that
it is necessary to expose the reality behind the
appearances [as above], but other issues arise
[also as above]: is the reality displayed in
realistic images a problem, in that it is subject
to the same conventions to display reality, and
thus risks becoming 'a single spectacle'
(84)? There is no simple intolerable reality
to be contrasted with images
Photographs of war combined with domestic life
have been discussed above, and there has been a
transition to the sort of collage that sees
political protest as a kind of youth fashion,
deeply implicated in consumerism. This
reveals the tension in political photography
between intention and outcome. Why should
shocking contrasts lead to political action?
'The stock reaction to such images is to close
one's eyes or avert one's gaze' (85)[as also
opposed to seeking out new configurations of the
sensible] . The political effect works as
intended only with spectators who already
understand and sympathise with the critique, and
feel guilty about their own complicity in viewing
such images. Shocking contrasts presuppose
this complicity. DeBord's film of his book
shows the spectacle as the inversion of life,
embodied in any image alike, showing how all our
existence has been transformed into a series of
spectacles and images. Strictly, any image
therefore can be intolerable and aimed at
political effects. The only way to break the
system was to counterpose some sort of activity to
the passivity of viewing the spectacle.
DeBord also indicates the radical potential of any
image, even clips from Hollywood westerns or war
films, which not only condemn American
imperialism, but offer us a chance to ' adopt the
heroism of the battle for our own purposes' (87),
to attack the empire of the spectacle. Any
image can be turned upside down, including the
images of the young female bodies: they can be
seen as the denunciation of the images of women,
but they also 'appear as active images, images of
bodies involved in active relations of amorous
desire'. So images of action are
particularly important, in order to break with
merely being a spectator. Action answers
evil passive images and guilt.
Of course this is paradoxical and requires
spectators to look at these active images, and
there is still a tone of condemnation, accusing
spectators of never acting. Only
knowledgeable critics know why this is so,
expressed in 'the authority of the sovereign voice
that stigmatizes the false existence which it
knows is to be condemned to wallow in' (88).
Images are often accompanied by this authoritative
voice to remind us why they are intolerable.
[An example is given of four photographs taken in
Auschwitz, 88-90, accompanied by a long essay in
the installation, describing further the reality
they depict. The controversy broke out
subsequently, where some critics accused the
images of being too real, too involving,
preventing any critical distance. Other
critics suggested that the images alone did not
represent reality, but literally a snapshot of it:
the reality of the whole process of extermination
was unrepresentable. However, the four
photographs did not claim to represent the
totality of the process. They could be read
as offering 'attestation' rather than proof, but
why should testimony be a more virtuous form of
knowledge? The same problems affected the
textual commentary: that is also an inadequate
representation of the suffering and horror, also
unable to grasp the totality.]
It is common to think that images show the
totality, whereas accompanying speech or text is
insufficient. This requires us to see images
as merely duplicates, which can be criticized as
being inadequate depictions of reality themselves;
images can reassure us, we can look at photographs
whereas we could not tolerate the reality.
Some philosophers would criticize photographers
for wanting to record events in the first place,
wanting to witness: 'The true witness is one who
does not want to witness' (91), and it is common
for witnesses to claim a privilege on the grounds
that they have been obliged somehow to speak.
The film Shoah displays these
characteristics. It is based on
testimony. Sometimes witnesses are urged to
continue their testimony even if it is painful,
claiming some authority because the witness does
not want to speak, that he has some experience of
a genuinely horrible event which cannot be
represented. This inability to speak carries
more weight than the content of the speech.
The director is heard on screen urging a witness
to speak, and when he does so he represents the
symbolic order who must be obeyed. Speech is
more authentic than image, it is more authentic
because it is almost impossible, and it is speech
in response to some authoritative demand in the
name of some higher order. It is these
qualities that means speech can critique images.
There are still paradoxes. The very silence
that guarantees authenticity must itself be made
visible, in the emotions on the face of the
speaker. The suffering face is a further
level of evidence. This again requires some
interpretation of tearfulness, with intolerability
not be confused with mere sensitivity.
Involuntary testimony is more authentic.
This feeds back to the distinction between images
that are intended and ones that are not [as in the
'taken by surprise shot' or the apparent
neutrality of the documentary camera]. Of course,
apparent lack of intention can be misleading, and
actually intended by the filmmaker.
We now come to see how complex representation
is. It is not just producing a visible form,
but offering some equivalent which can also be
speech. All representations involve 'a
complex set of relations between the visible and
the invisible, the visible and speech, the said
and the unsaid'(93). There is always a chain
of images which can have effects. Voices are
never neutral complements to visible images, but
themselves construct images and transform one
event into another, trying to form
perceptions. There are therefore images in
language as well as in visual images --
'figures of rhetoric and poetics' in both,
and a whole 'process of figuration that is a
process of condensation and displacement'[yes
mate, and you need semiotics to go much further
with this!]. There are relations of
similarity and the similarity [metaphor and
metonym as well].
Perhaps the whole system of figuration is itself
intolerable because it creates spectacle, and
critical films come to look like 'episodes of a
romantic fiction'(94). We need to analyze
images instead of just accusing them of a
spectacular function: we must not just identify
them with 'idolatry, ignorance or passivity'
(95). Some new artwork raises some
possibilities [examples 95 -100]. A
particular installation consist of black boxes
containing an image of a murdered Tutsi, and the
text describes the concealed content in each
box. It looks as if the proof of the words
can be found in the images, but the words
themselves are visual elements: this subverts the
usual official connections between text and
images. The installation also challenges the
usual view that we are anaesthetised by a flood of
images of horror—in fact, the media carefully
select out such images and censor them, mostly
showing us experts and others who have commenting
on the images. We do see lots of nameless
bodies who cannot speak for themselves,
reinforcing the conventional view that we need
experts to explain what it is we are seeing.
The installation challenges this view because it
personalizes with the name and history those who
were massacred. Words are needed to do this
instead of photographs which could anonymize and
banalize. This is the reverse of the
conventional view. The words are themselves
acknowledged to be images or figures, and they
take on a political function in reversing the
usual position, where words generalize rather than
individualise. In this sort of political
reversal, 'the political figure par excellence is
metonymy which gives the effects for the cause or
the part for the whole' (97) [I'm not sure I
understand this. Is this saying that
conventional politics uses metonyms, or radical
politics?].
In another example, the eyes of a woman are
photographed [on the cover of the book], and this
is a metonym— two eyes to represent the massacred
millions—but also a substitution of effect [in the
gaze] for cause [the suffering]. There is no claim
here that these eyes are unusually perceptive, but
they do show that the murderers have failed to
suppress the expression of a victim. The
individual depictions help us put in context, or
disrupt, the usual account of multiple
murders. An accompanying text gives the
specific history of the woman whose eyes we see.
What we have here is a discussion of the politics
of constructing victims in a particular
'distribution of the visible' (99). All
images are located in such systems, and these
affect the sort of attention that images
attracts. Another example [this time of
unintended attention] concerns a notorious
photograph taken of a starving girl being pursued
by a vulture. This photograph won a Pulitzer
prize, and was clearly intended to break with the
usual passive reception of photographs, but it
also attracted a great deal of 'indignation',
blaming the photographer for taking the picture as
opposed to helping the child. Apparently,
the photographer killed himself as a result.
Another example offers a different system of
visibility in an installation based on this event,
showing how this intolerable picture of a child
was located 'in a wider [opposing] history of
intolerance'. The photographer himself was
the victim of this intolerance, and the
installation made spectators watch a video
describing his life and his active struggles
against apartheid, as well as his reaction to the
public campaign of condemnation. Only then
does the original photograph appear, which puts it
in perspective rather than isolating it [and
letting it be attached to this wider system of
intolerance?].
In a film about the Cambodian genocide, the
extermination machine is depicted rather than the
victims, using the archives. Some survivors
were filmed as witnesses, and so were some former
guards. The guards were filmed reacting to
different sorts of archival material, including
minutes of interrogations, and photographs of
torture of prisoners. This showed the
effects of the extermination machine on the people
who were involved. Gestures and intonations
returned. One provided an 'hallucinatory'
detailed reliving of events (101). The
reconstruction is itself an intolerable spectacle,
but the film tries to 'redistribute the
intolerable' between the various representations
it deploys, such as reports of photographs as well
as reconstructions. It makes the former
torturers learn how to do it again, which reduces
them 'to the position of school pupils educated by
their former victims' [you hope!]. Past and
present are mixed to show how people feel about
events. The overall treatment is 'a matter
of dispositif of visibility' (102), with
all the elements combined in a system that creates
reality, even 'a certain common sense'.
The term common sense indicates that there can be
communities of data, where visibility is shared,
almost different constructions of reality [SIC] or
forms of common sense. The films and other
examples studied show how these communities are
created, by establishing relations between words
and visible forms, places and times. In this
sense, they are all fictions, and it is no longer
an issue of whether reality can or should be
represented in fiction. It is more a matter
of looking at who is being addressed, 'what kind
of gaze and consideration are created by this
fiction'.
We end with political implications. The path
traced above shows a line from depicting
intolerable spectacles in order to prompt
political action, but this link was always 'sheer
presupposition' (103). It required a group
of spectators who were able to interpret these
images and develop political movements. The
whole system was undermined, and images were seen
as powerful anaesthetics, taking away the
understanding and the capacity to act, as in the
critique of the spectacle. Any image could
be suspected of being political, and a general
skepticism was the result. Instead of
pursuing this disappointing line, we need to think
instead of our new role for artistic images: they
do not 'supply weapons for battles', but offer new
configurations of what can be seen, said and
thought, 'a new landscape of the possible'.
The final example shows a photograph where a pile
of stones appears in the distance in a
landscape. The whole set of photographs
helps us see additional meaning, however, in that
this pile of stones is an Israeli roadblock in
Palestine. The photographer uses the small
roadblocks, shot from a bird's eye view to make
them fit into the landscape, to show the scars
left on a territory. The intended effect is
not indignation, but rather 'curiosity, the desire
to see closer up' (104), to generate a new form of
attention. This disrupts the normal
perceptions and dispositions, and encourages 'the
different politics of the sensible—of politics
based on the variation of distance, the resistance
of the visible and the uncertainty of effects'
(105). This sort of image changes gazes and
alters landscapes, breaks with anticipations.
Chapter five The Pensive Image
[the main theme here is how images are polysemic,
and how artists have tried either to extend or
impose an authoritative meaning. Main people
criticised here are Barthes and Benjamin.
The themes about emancipated spectators are there
as well, but there is the usual slippage
betweenthe highly informed theoretically
sophisticated critic and the 'normal' spectator.
Workers in 1830s or 1970s France might experience
some 'pensiveness' but surely could nopt analyze
it as Ramcière does as intertwined regimes of
representation or whatever. More likely is the
conventional reading or the averted gaze noted
above?]
The term 'pensive' normally applies to individuals
who are thinking in a kind of passive way.
Images can be pensive as well with 'unthought
thought', or unintended thought and effects
(107). Active and passive does not quite
cover this indeterminacy. It is like the
tension between the image as a duplicate and the
image as an artistic operation, there is a 'zone
of indeterminacy between these two types of
image', and the different aspects are articulated
in different ways. Photography brings out
this articulation best.
Baudelaire saw photography as a threat to painting
and art, while Benjamin saw mechanical
reproduction as democratically disruptive,
breaking with the 'cult of the unique'.
Separating out the image meant that it could be
rearticulated with political problems.
Photographs can also serve as evidence for
historical events, although that required them to
be supplied with captions. Modern practice
in museums treat photographs as if they were
paintings [examples 109 including a portrait of a
slender Polish girl on the beach].
Photographs like this often contain distance and
mystery, rather like portraits of characters from
the past. However, theorists were arguing
that photography and art were actually opposed,
and that photographs had a particular power for
provoking thought while avoiding easy
conceptualisation.
Barthes in Camera Lucida divided the
affects of photographs using the terms punctum
and studium [roughly, personal
unpredictable effects versus more informative and
informed, normal reading]. This implied that
photographs merely transported particular
qualities of things to viewing subjects,
irrespective of the intention of the photographer,
neglecting technical processes except chemical
ones, and seeing an optical relationship as a
tactile one. Viewers should 'repudiate all
knowledge' conveyed by the image in order to
experience its transporting effects. The
optical qualities of the photograph are almost
irrelevant, the gaze dominates.
It is not easy in practice to distinguish punctum
and studium, however. Barthes tries
to disattend to the content of a photograph of two
'abnormal' children, for example, and its
political message, and draws attention to the
unusual proportions of the work and the barely
perceptible artistic details, which are
'detachable'[classic elite taste, exactly like an
elite appreciation of the photograph of an old
woman's hands in Bourdieu's example]The interest
in details is apparently informed by 'the Lacanian
notion of the part object'. For him, the
collar of the small boy looks like a
'Danton'collar—Danton was executed, and a reminder
of death hits him as a punctum.
However, ironically, this always depends on
knowledge not contained in the image itself.
In another example, we see a young man in
handcuffs, and we can read it conventionally as a
portrait of a handsome youth, but then the punctum
hits us—he is about to be executed, since we can
identify him as a would-be assassin who was indeed
executed. Again Barthes links historical
knowledge and the texture of the photograph, as a
'short circuit'(112). Barthes understands
the photograph as an example of the imago,
the classic effigy of the dead. He also
alludes to an ancient controversy about what
statues were for—as images of ancestors or gods,
or just a beautiful object. Since this
controversy is no longer current, remembering it
acts as a punctum—another short circuit
between the past images of death and the
present.
It is possible to see the photograph differently,
as the result of forms of indeterminacy.
First the young man is seated in a classical form
of portraiture, but we do not know whether this is
accidental or intentional. We do not know if
the details of the background, which includes
'wedges and marks' have been included or
highlighted deliberately. Secondly, it's not
easy to date this photograph—the dress is
contemporary, although the event took place in the
past (1865). Thirdly, we cannot work out
'the attitude of the character', his motives or
his feelings.
This 'tangle' makes the image pensive, and it is a
complex relation between the subject, the
photographer and the spectator, 'the intended and
the unintended, the known and the unknown, the
expressed and unexpressed, the present and the
past' (115). It is not a matter of just two
readings coinciding. The image offers us signs of
an identity, an arrangement of bodies in space,
and some effects of mechanical imprint, each of
which may be intended or unintended.
Although this photograph may not claim to be art,
it can help us see how artistic photographs work,
as equally indeterminate [and then we return to
the photograph of the Polish girl on the
beach, noting that we can read it is an
issue of identity following the collapse of
communism, immediate presence, intentional or
unintentional expressions, and a mystery about
what explains the stance]. There are some
similarities with things we know, as in studium,
but there is also 'archi-similarity' (116) 'an
immediate presence and affect of the body'.
The image also shows 'a dis-appropriate
similarity', because we are invited to see this
girl as an ordinary being not a unique one, not
particularly offering an identity.
These effects might be specific to portraits,
which Benjamin suggests still have a religious
value. Photographs without human beings tend
to develop an 'expository value' instead.
This is still a problematic distinction,
however. A photograph of a wooden kitchen
wall in Alabama [page 118] was produced as part of
an investigation into the living conditions of
poor farmers in the 1930s, and has since been seen
as autonomous art. But the tension between
'art and social reportage' is present in the image
itself. It does represent the interiors of
poor houses, but it also displays some artistic
features—the wooden boards look like 'quasi
abstract decor' described in other art
photographs; the simple arrangement of the kitchen
towards on the wall evokes 'the ideology of
modernist architects and designers…
[opposing]… the horror of bourgeois
sideboards' (117); there is an 'aesthetic of the
asymmetrical'. It's not clear whether the
camera has just recorded these aspects, whether
they were deliberately arranged that way by the
inhabitants, or whether they have been consciously
framed and highlighted by the photographer.
The actual photographer is well known (Walker
Evans), and he has explicitly developed ideas on
photography and the arts, derived from Flaubert,
for example that 'the artist must be invisible in
his work, just as God is in nature'(118).
Art is deliberately rendered as impersonal.
The artist deletes from the objects, to produce 'a
certain indifference', rendering ambiguous social
identification. The banal in particular is
made into impersonal art, rather than being seen
as an expression of the situation or a
character.
Another example features the paintings of beggars
in the street by Murillo, which was discussed by
Hegel. Hegel's reading connected the
idleness of the beggars, and the virtue of
painting impersonally, without caring, expressing
'a [God-like] freedom from concern about external
things'(119) [only a philosopher could see beggary
as an aesthetic!]. This already assumes that
artists and gods themselves are indifferent, and
so is 'supreme beauty', and this depends on an
earlier tradition, including Winckelman on the
Belvedere torso [see above], seeing activity and
thought expressed in immobile motion of the
muscles of the abdomen, like the waves of the
sea. There is a serenity in these images.
What happens with these examples is the emergence
of a new relation between 'thought, art, action
and image'(120). Representation is left
behind, and images no longer simply express.
The composition of the image used to be a matter
of delivering a story, exemplifying action.
Actions were depicted in facial expressions and
body postures, although there was some work
depicting 'poetic' figures 'that substitute one
expression for another' to add dimensions to the
power of the image. Depicting actual humans
or animals helps this process, so eagles depicted
majesty and so on. The combination of the
literal and the figural 'specifically defines
classical mimesis' (121).
Then dis-appropriate similarities appeared as a
sign of a break with this regime. There are
two accounts of artistic modernity. In the
first, art becomes autonomous, artistic ideas take
on material forms, without going through mediating
images. In the second, 'the tragic model of
the " sublime"', there is no obvious relation
between idea and materiality. There is also
a third approach, involving not breaking with
immediate representation in images, but developing
a new 'emancipation from the unifying logic of
action'[sounds rather like Deleuze on breaking
with the sensori-motor system in cinema?].
Classically, figures offered a normal 'sensible
present'and also a way of alluding to
expressions. In modernity, the figure
doesn't just express something else—it's not that
motions of waves or abdominal muscles directly
expressed thoughts via analogy. Now,
opposites are connected—dynamic muscle and 'the
endless passive repetition of the motion' (122).
Pensiveness is not just punctum or aura,
nor ignorance of the author's intentions, nor the
difficulties in interpreting images
themselves. Instead, it is a matter of the
conjunction of 'two regimes of expression, without
homogenizing them'. Barthes in S/Z discusses
pensiveness in the mind of the characters, but
this also makes us question the status of the
text. We are left in a state of pensiveness
after the narrative has finished, suggesting we
move on to pursue 'an indeterminate expressive
logic' after having followed the logic of the
narrative. In this sense, classical texts
have meanings in reserve, 'plenitude' (123).
Pensiveness breaks with the logic of the action
and extends it, but also makes us rethink
it. The same goes with painting: its
function is inverted, not just as a supplement to
action, but as a way of questioning it.
Flaubert offers another example, where paintings
punctuate the action and trigger events, as a
narrative. They do not literally represent
or follow an analogy with the actions of the
characters, however, but serve as an impersonal
elements, or Deleuzian 'heterogenesis' (123) [an
assemblage between the visual and the
literary]. This provides us with another
narrative, which conflicts with the logic of the
normal one, as a mere 'chain of micro
events… which is randomly dispersed without
beginning or end' (124), an intertwining of
logics, 'the presence of one art in another'.
Walker Evans picks up this technique, intertwining
two arts, reporting but also offering an
excess. This latent excess is what makes the
image pensive. [Another example follows,
which consists of series of photographs of roads,
with a conventional narrative but also depicting
'a trail of abstract lines or spirals'(125), and
there was a film made of these photographs
resulting in 'unique combinations of exchange,
fusion and distance'. It is not silence that
makes an image pensive, but rather a latent and
different different kind of figurativeness.
This tension between different kinds of expression
can even be found in unpromising examples like
video images. Artists originally imagined
video would offer a better way to express their
thoughts, without the intervention of the film
apparatuses. They thought that spectators
would also be released from passivity.
Others regretted the 'loss of cinematographic
pensiveness'(126), with its breaks, frames,
divisions between on and off screen and so on, all
of which produced an 'affective economy'.
Video by contrast offered 'an infinite circularity
of the metamorphoses of docile matter'.
However, video should be better read as
heterogeneous, a form in tension, like
photography. An example is a video by
Vasulka 'Art of Memory'.
The artist thought he was just manipulating
images, and yet he generated pensiveness, from the
emergence of 'several
differentiations'(127). There were two types
of images, both presenting landscapes and
characters as if they had been photographed or
painted, deliberately non realistic (with
electronic colours for example) but nevertheless
'the analogue of a real landscape'. Various
other things like 'soft sculptures' also appear,
although these are electronic artefacts.
They can undergo changes, turning into screens for
example or mushroom clouds, mountain paths, making
up 'a theatre of memory', turning what is
represented into something representative,
documents into monuments. The video does not
reduce everything to a mere metamorphic image,
however. Two regimes of image are still
presented, such as grey archival, and colored
Western landscapes. These resist the
temptation to over-control. Classic imagery
of war and horrors are located in electronic
shapes, and this sidesteps all the debates about
how and whether these events should be depicted
realistically. However, the events
themselves stop this from being mere clever art,
and the images are autonomous, 'overcharged with
reality', outside art. However, the
spectator alone can judge the effects of these
relationships, and decide on what is reality.
Godard's Histories of Cinema provides
another example of video. There is no
attempt to construct a sequence based on memory,
however, but to allow our images to slide into one
another. The images he chooses express
[metonymically] attitudes or gestures, and these
can trigger another story, and be combined with
the others in a 'fraternity of metaphors' (129)
[Godard's phrase]. Images condense
multiplicities from their own time, and can be
combined with others—images of civil life in
France in 1940 are combined with the impact of
Nazi Germany depicted by a clip from M.
Newsreel footage is combined with films that were
already predicting what was to come [apparently,
this is further analysed in Rancière's piece in Film
Fables, 2006, and The Future of the
Image, 2007]. So Godard develops a
radical notion of the figure, controlled both by
narratives and metaphor, depicted in different
ways by different arts and media. In this
way, 'one art serves to constitute the imaginary
of another' (130). Cinema's radical impulse
is restored after it focused exclusively on
stories rather than metaphors. Video montage
enables Godard to assemble these metaphors and
thus 'he constructs the cinema that has never
existed'
This shows us what pensiveness in the image might
be, and how it resists immediate intentions of
artists and spectators. It is not the image
itself, but rather a collection of 'several image
functions' (131) which coexist on the same
surface. These distances are important,
explaining why 'art escapes itself'. Kant
had already noticed one form of distance, between
artistic form, controlled by intentions, and
aesthetic form, which is 'perceived without a
concept and declines any idea of intentional
purpose'. In his terms, these are the
'aesthetic ideas' produced by art. Rancière
wants to preserve this idea in the concept of the
figure as representing intertwined regimes of
expression, and, these days, several arts and
several media. Images have not been
domesticated by electronics, any more than they
were by photography. Artists always like to
play with the possibilities and blend effects, to
create new figures, and the new technology offers
'unprecedented possibilities. The image is
not about to stop being pensive' (132).
back to Rancière page
more social theorists
home
|