NOTES ON
Bogue, R. (2003) Deleuze on Cinema.
London: Routledge.
[A very good clear read and commentary on
Deleuze's Cinema 1
and Cinema 2]
Introduction
Deleuze was particularly attached to cinema,
although he was better known for commentaries on
literature, theatre and painting. The point
in the cinema books is to develop specific
philosophical concepts proper to cinema.
There are specific analyses, but also 'a general
conception of cinema as a mode of thought'
(2). We need to think about time, space and
movement to get there. 'Deleuze is not
deliberately obscure, but his cinema texts are
often difficult, primarily because they are so
allusive and so highly condensed in their
references'. They assume existing knowledge
of films and film criticism. This book is an
attempt to read along with Deleuze, to draw out
implications, to explicate the condensed comments
and trace the broad outline of the argument and
its overall coherence.
We have to understand Bergson first, especially
the idea that 'the things we commonly call space
and time are merely extremes of the contraction
and dilation of a single duree, or duration'
(3). There is an 'open vibrational whole, a
flow of matter-movement'. This is to be
applied to the specific problems of the cinematic
image, time and movement, down to the level of
analysing frames, shots and montage. The
open whole is being demonstrated, 'indirectly
present' in individual frames and also in whole
montages. Montage is particularly explicit,
and Deleuze shows there are four basic approaches
in early film making—'organic unity... dialectical
totality...
mathematical infinite... and dynamic infinite made
up of clashing intensities' (4). Each bring
with them specific techniques of 'framing,
composition, lighting, camera movement and
montage'.
Deleuze also attempts a taxonomy of images of
cinema. Bergson's notion of image suggest
that everything is made up of images [an early
version of the claim that everything can be
grasped as phenomena]. Living entities are
special in that they can choose to some extent how
they will interact with other images, imposing
their own sense of space and time. Deleuze
derives from this general argument three
specialised images in every living image: 'the
perception-image, whereby the living image senses
the outside world; the action-image, which
structures the space surrounding the living image;
and the affection-image, which connects the living
image's outer perceptions, inner feelings, and
motor responses to other images' (4).
A more complex taxonomy emerges, via Peirce and
the notions of firstness, secondness and
thirdness. These suggest three types of
images in addition: 'the "impulse-image," the
"reflection-image," and the
"relation-image"'(5). The six categories can
be used in a taxonomy. The signs [of images]
are to be non linguistic. There are
basically three categories, 'one genetic, the
other two compositional'. Six images, and
three signs each gives 18 types of signs, 'each of
which is a specific kind of [specific
nonphilosophical?] image'[as I suspected, the term
image is being used with several meanings?].
In Cinema 1, the movement - image is
discussed—'all images that are regulated by the
sensory motor schema… [Which]…
Provides the commonsense temporal and spatial
coordinates of our everyday world'. The
signs of this image appearing classic cinema as
simple coordinates of the commonsense world.
In modern cinema, this schema is abandoned, and
new time-images appear, with new signs, which are
not common sense, especially "opsigns" and
"sonsigns" then '"mnemosigns"' [hereinafter M] of
flashback memories, and the "onirosigns" [O] of
dream landscapes; and finally in the "hyalosigns"
[H] of time crystals (5). The first two
allude to time outside measurable time, and
Italian neo realism is the first sign of 'this
shattered temporality'. M and O can be
recuperated within common sense time, but they can
also allude to a different sense, 'a bifurcating
time in the flashback, a floating time in dream
sequences, and the oniric dance world of Hollywood
musicals' (6). Only H suggests a full time
image.
Bergson suggest that memory consists of a doubling
between an actual present. and coexisting virtual
past, moments. There is a virtual past
extending from the present point in time, and this
suggests a non objective time. Cinema's time
crystals can bring to awareness this connection
between the virtual and the actual and how they
link together to become indiscernible. This
can be shown in a number of ways, for example the
mirror scene at the end of The Lady from
Shanghai [surely a cliche by now though?],
but an entire Fellini film can be seen as a time
crystal (And the Ship Sails On).
Different directors offer different '"states of
the crystal": in Ophuls the perfect crystal; in
Renoir, the split crystal; in Fellini, the crystal
information; and in Visconti, the crystal in
dissolution'.
H and time crystals can unsettle us by offering
into penetrated present and past.
'"Chronosigns" [C] offer additional images,
concerning both the order of time and time as a
series. The first depicts time as coexisting
sheets or simultaneous points of the present, as
in Resnais, and Robbe-Grillet respectively.
Time as a series 'is manifest in images that
incorporate a "before" and an "after" within a
"now"'. These reveal the 'power of the
false', a becoming which undermines fixed
identities and blurs the
true and false, as in 'Welles's Nietzschean tales
of deception and fakery… [and]…
Rouch's ethnofictions' (7). Godard in
particular shows how categories appear in series
'engaged in a perpetual metamorphosis, each series
disclosing a specific power of the false'.
C are signs of thought '"noosigns"', and signs
that must be read '"lectosigns"'. In classic
cinema, images and thoughts were simply in accord,
organized through the 'sensori-motor schema common
to film and viewer'. In modern cinema, the
image produces alien thoughts and this engages '"a
spiritual automaton", in the mind of the viewer
and also displayed on the screen as a 'brain
surface of a non human thought'. There is a
non naturalistic relation between images, a gap,
and in the gap 'the fissure of a pure outside is
made present', a split in objective time and
space. There can also be a gap between
images and sounds, again requiring an active
reading not a common sense understanding.
Audio visual signs can become autonomous, located
in a continuum, which might separate visual from
sonic and interrelate them in different
ways. 'The films of Straube/Huillet, for
example, reveal a stratigraphic space and an
aerial free indirect discourse, the visual images
and sound images communicating through a staggered
back-and-forth passage between the two domains'
(8), while Duras offers a flow of visual images
and the flow of words 'tending towards
inarticulate cries', which interacted but never
dissolve into each other.
This book also relates to other analyses of the
arts [and Bogue's other books]. It is
intended to be general not specialist. Other
useful studies of Deleuze on cinema are cited
(Rodowick, Kennedy, and Marks; Flaxman, Serrano,
Fahle and Engell).
Chapter One Bergson and Cinema
The two books on cinema are about taxonomies of
signs, but Deleuze also uses the concept of auteur
[a contradiction? see the excellent essay in
Boundas and Olkowski by Ropers-Wuillemier].
In the second book, time is seen as 'the
fundamental element of cinema'(12), which would
naturally involve Bergson for Deleuze.
Deleuze denies that Bergson is a dualist, despite
appearances, especially that there is no split
between consciousness and its operations, and the
processes going on between life and matter.
Deleuze wants to argue there is a higher monism
which generates apparent dualities.
Bergson develops the notion of duration in
his work. At first, it is directed towards
arguing that subjective feeling such as emotions
cannot be quantified, but come in qualitative
complexes. He went on to suggest that all
physical sensations are qualitative, and that
single changes always produce qualitative
involvement of different parts of the body.
Some are more abstract, and some more related to
physical sensations. Even numbers are a
quantitative reduction of qualitative
differences. Such reduction replaces changes
in time with dimensions in space [Deleuze has a
good section on this, which is rather like Adorno,
in Difference and
Repetition, I think, which says that
in order to be able to claim that you are
measuring different quantities, you have to assume
that they have not changed in any other
significant way over time, that events are
replicable, and so on]. Normally, we do
think of time as a form of space, some abstract
element proceeding from one point to
another. But we are also aware of duration,
of links between the past and the present pointing
to the future. Bergson's analogy here is of
musical melody, which can be seen as a sequence of
individual notes, but which is really 'an
indivisible multiplicity changing qualitatively in
an on going movement… The entire succession
of notes forming a single process… an
indivisible heterogeneity' (14): each note pushes
on into the next one producing qualitative change,
something new. This is one way in which
duration is always indeterminate [in the sense of
emergent]. In a deterministic causal
universe, time has no effect [as we have just
seen]. Succession considered as part of duration
becomes a matter of real movement.
The psychological emphasis is continued in the
early discussions of memory, which offers an
internal notion of duration 'a heterogeneous
qualitative multiplicity of indivisible, of
inseparable terms' (15) the very opposite of the
scientific objective conception of space. In
this early work there seems to be an opposition of
external space and internal duration, but Bergson
goes on to speak of duration in general, driven by
a whole virtual past. This can be linked
with élan vital as a vital impulse affecting all
living entities, driving evolution, life as
invention producing divergent lines. Here
there seems to be an other opposition between the
animate and the inanimate, but Deleuze argues that
there is a more general process again, the virtual
itself being actualized, with evolution as a
matter of actualization of the different degrees
[see the essays on Bergson in Deleuze's Desert Islands].
Both matter and living things are different
degrees of contraction and relaxation, with the
difference between the animate and inanimate as
simply an emerging form.
Deleuze focuses on the more general aspects of
Bergson, including his insistence that solid
matter itself is made of movement and flux, and
how this should even affect modern physics [and
Bogue credits him with some early insights into
physics on matter and energy here]. Matter
itself moves towards entropy, but life goes in the
opposite direction, towards creative
differentiation. This helps us see that
'entropic matter is simply a decrease in tension
in a field of energy, and creative life an
increase in tension in that same field' (17) [this
trope is finally starting to make sense, but why
call it 'tension' -- interconnection would be
better? Multiplicity?], hence the differences all
depends on the degree of relative contraction or
relaxation of duration.
[Another mysterious set of terms is now to be
explained]. 'There are different temporal
rhythms in the universe and... qualities and
quantities form a continuum, my most fleeting
perception of the quality of red [for example]
being a temporal contraction of trillions of
nearly identical oscillations into a single
moment' (17). At the subjective level, we
know that we can contract [here we go again --
simplify, disconnect, called relaxation above?]
our experiences into a present moment in order to
undertake an action, but we also know that in
dreams, there is a relaxation of will and memory
[but not of duration!] , and a loosened tie
between present and past [meaning lots more
duration]. Similarly, inert matter is
minimally contracted [the upside down feeling
again!], because it contains minimal connections
with the past. Our attempts to grasp
objective matter also contract [simplify] temporal
connections to the past, and things appear to be
connected so tightly to events in the past that
they can be seen as identical, and their emergence
as predictable. We also develop a notion of
external effects. [Back to the mysterious
upside down nature of the term loosening—duration
itself is infinitely loosened in such notions, so
that individual moments can spread out so to speak
into some sort of continuum. OK, but doesn't
our consciousness have to ignore duration first,
so that we can eventually substitute the notion of
xtension and spaces? This is called 'contraction'!
]
Yet duration can never be eliminated
entirely—inertia is a tendency towards elimination
of energetic duration, an ideal, as in Euclidean
geometry or Newtonian physics [where other things
have to remain equal, or processes reduced to the
laboratory, and so on. Similarly, pure
duration separated from consciousness also offers
an ideal. In particular, 'all our thoughts
and emotions are embodied and connected to the
physical world' (19). Relaxation and
contraction are relative to each other.
[Back to the mysterious terms of vibration and
speed...] The different forms can be seen as
'different rhythms in a vibrational whole'.
These are not vibrations in the usual sense [!],
Of something material. Instead 'movement is
inseparable from that which moves', amino now
there is a connection at the sub atomic level
between flows and vibrations and apparent
entities. In particular, something from the
past is always retained, 'a memory of some sort',
and there is always an 'impulse towards the future
(an élan or will)' (20). Using terms like
memory and impulse, we can argue that matter
itself has 'some form of consciousness, some
degree of dynamic contraction of the past into a
present towards the future', and 'conversely, the
most complex forms of consciousness are part of a
single continuum of rhythmic flows' (20) [really a
sleight of hand here, involving particular and
very general definitions of memory and
impulse?]. Only 'relative speeds and degrees
of contraction'differ between humans and other
matter, especially the intervals between events
and the amounts of the past that get contracted
into the present.
This reduction to vibrations makes Bergson a
monist [via Deleuze, for rather peculiar
philosophical reasons as we saw, mostly to be
consistent and avoid having to use different
concepts and so on]. This monism further
explains differentiation and distinctions, since
there is 'an irreducible multiplicity of
rhythms'[here, a matter of rhythms of contraction
and relaxation—the earlier example of red light
seemed to take ordinary human consciousness and
the capacity to perceive vibrations as the
standard, and it is science not philosophy that
has discovered the myriad of vibrations in what
looks like a simple unitary colour? There is this
constant rhetorical contrast between ordinary
consciousness and philosophy, but never science --
and social science-- and philosophy]. At the
limits of the range are inert matter and
extensionless mind [relaxations and contractions
respectively of duration]. Duration itself
is 'a qualitative multiplicity', constantly
differentiating itself. Deleuze therefore has
reconciled all the apparent contradictions by
seeing Bergson's thought as developing through
different stages—a critique of the conventional
false dualism slight mind and body, quality and
quantity; differentiation between duration and
external space, qualitative and quantitative
multiplicities respectively; seeing the difference
between duration and matter as produced by 'the
rhythmic contractions and relaxations of a
vibrational whole'; explaining how duration
actualizes itself through the élan vital,
producing apparently dual forms like inorganic and
organic.
Deleuze is particularly interested in Bergson's
notions of movement, which he derives from Creative
Evolution. First, it is an illusion to
see movement as a matter of moving through
space. Interestingly, Bergson sees this
illusion best represented in cinema, which links a
series of snapshots to produce the illusion of
movement. Much of our ordinary consciousness
invokes the same kind of illusion, where we sliced
time into static moments, 'or immobile cuts' (21),
and then link them back together again. What
we need to do instead is to see each moment as
connected to an indivisible multiplicity, with its
own duration as the source of movement.
However, Deleuze argues that this precisely gives
insight into how cinema develops movement -
images, and how we can use Bergson to talk about
immobile cuts and real movements depicted in
cinema.
Secondly, Bergson talks about the Greeks and their
notions of movement. One conception sees
movement between privileged moments, such as
infancy, boyhood and adulthood. Galileo was
able to reject this notion of periodic change and
replace it with 'the sequence of equidistant,
indifferent, and interchangeable
instants—... "any - instants - whatever"'
(22). For Bergson, this is still only a more
precise version of the cinematic error, but
Deleuze notes that the cinema actually provided
early knowledge of a different conception of
movement, as in the famous early films of
galloping horses. It is more than just
denying the notion of privileged moments, rather
that any singular instant is produced by from the
flow of any-instants-whatever. It follows
that privileged moments in films, 'images of
crisis, paroxysm and intensity' as in Eisenstein,
a also linked to any-instants whatsoever, that
these 'remarkable instance are immanent within
movement' (23). This is something genuinely
new emerging from cinema, an explanation of
novelty, 'the remarkable and the singular'as a
result of a flow of any-instants-whatever.
Deleuze sees this is nothing other than a suitable
metaphysics for modern science—and for cinema.
The third notion in Creative Evolution
pursues the notion of 'cuts' in [snapshots of]
duration. Instants are immobile cuts,
movements are mobile cuts. We can now see
movement as no longer 'the shifting of positions
of objects in space', but rather as transformation
of one qualitative whole into another [as above,
with the early work on the emotions].
Individual movements are best seen as parts of
qualitative changing wholes, and qualitative
changing is emergent. Bergson apparently has
a strange example about dissolving sugar in
water—our psychological experience of duration
helps us to grasp duration in general, a duration
that's also linking the sugar and the water.
[If we go on to philosophise], we can see that the
water, sugar, glass and the observer are all
abstractions from the universal vibration, and
that each one changes,albeit at different
speeds. Doubtless other changes also take
place, and we have only artificially restricted
the discussion to the one event. Even
natural science sees that dividing the universe
into closed systems is an abstraction. We
have a notion of a fully open whole, and a
critique of the reduction involved in determinism,
objectivity and causality. This whole is
'given'in every attempt to analyse parts of it,
including deterministic ones, and, in biology, in
finalist ones. The whole prevents any simple
determinism, since it guarantees new and
undetermined developments.
It can seem as if matter develops into isolated
systems and stable objects, but there is a
difference between the whole and ensembles: the
latter constitute isolated system or closed sets
within a whole. Individual items are
immobile cuts, like still photographs, and the
whole set can be seen as an immobile cut [immobile
ensemble would be better]. The sets are not
simply subsets of the whole, but 'insistent
illusions' (26). These are useful for
ordinary actions and common sense, but it leads to
a further illusion that movements within a set can
be seen as 'unchanging bodies shifting positions
within a space container'. Instead, such
movement is best seen as 'the specific local
manifestation of the vibrational flux of the
universe'.
How can we perceive the real actions of duration
through the portion that presents itself?
Deleuze has to extend Bergson by arguing that
duration is the whole of the relations, and
movement to an expression of it [these are only
implicit in Bergson, Deleuze argues]. [If we
know how to perceive it], mundane movement inside
closed sets can be seen as qualitative changes in
the whole as well, so that mundane movement is an
'intermediary between closed sets and the open
whole'. We have to see this movement as
simultaneously expressing duration— '"Movement
thus has two faces, in a way" says Deleuze.' The
issue is further discussed through the concept of expression in Spinoza,
especially the idea of two directions of
expression, explication where the one becomes
multiple, and implication, whereby each example of
the multiple implies the one. Together,
these two movements can be seen as
complication. Separately, explication is a
process of development of the one, and the one
[surely the entity expressed?] can be seen as a
sign that points beyond itself. Thus
entities in enclosed sets are signs of the process
of duration becoming actualised, and duration is
'immanent within each closed set' (27) [not really
an argument though, more a series of interlocking
assertions and definitions].
Bogue's homely example concerns an observation of
an interaction between a dog and a girl beneath
the tree. Each can be seen to move, but [a
skilled observer] can also see 'an ongoing
transformation of relations between them,
metamorphosing configurations of girl - dog -
tree', shifting over time. I can then
speculate about other elements, some of which may
be invisible, such as the wind touching the
leaves, or the patterns of light on the
scene. The cinematographic illusion of the
initial simple observation has opened on to an
idea of holism and duration [but only after
developing a series of special philosophical
concepts to guide the whole process. It's a
form of rhetoric really, allowing Deleuze to
persuade us to see the world his way].
Observing the scene through a frame adds to the
illusion of a closed set and immobile cut.
Given the right perception, the closed cut becomes
a mobile one, a slice of duration. As a result,
Deleuze says that Bergson thinks that there are
several images available to us: instant ones, in
the form of the immobile cuts; movement images
which are mobile cuts; time images which relate
directly to duration, change, relation beyond
movement. These are to be the categories
which analyse cinema.
First, Bergson needs to be explored further.
The notion of an image is used to deny both
idealism and realism. In common sense, we
use this term too—the object as it appears to us,
which seems neither in our minds, nor to have a
completely different nature. Objects are
seen as more or less as we perceive them, but as
images which exist in themselves. We can
avoid the reduction of either idealism or
realism. Deleuze notes the similarity
between this conception and phenomenology,
although phenomenology still begins with
consciousness: Bergson wants to deduce
consciousness as 'a particular kind of image'
(29). We can see the images act and react
among themselves according to the laws of nature,
producing a general predictability. However,
living beings introduce a certain in
determination, a gap between mechanical causes and
effects, or relay between movements from outside
and individual movements. Living images
perceive movements. Perception is always
linked in action, in a sensory motor schema.
We do not perceive abstractly, but always in order
to further action, control space, gained some
freedom for action. This in turn involves a
selective subtraction of the features of
surrounding objects according to our interests and
concerns. Living beings do not 'react
equally to all surrounding forces and bodies'
(30). In effect, we convert images into
representations, and this involves a preliminary
separation from other images, which Bergson
describes as 'a diminution of light, and darkening
of its contours'(31). However, this process
does not just
depend on consciousness, but on objects
themselves, who reflects and emit light enabling
us to perceive them, if we prioritize particular
emissions. Bergson goes on to introduce a
general conception where matter in its entirety
presents itself to be perceived as a kind of
'photograph of the whole', while individual human
perceptions offer different sorts of screen on
which parts of this image can be displayed [this
is to deny the usual notions of perception as a
kind of mental photograph—the photograph is
already there, so to speak, and perception does
not take place in individuals, since it involves
luminous points in the whole].
This means that perception is not special, but
another part of action, and there is no division
between the material world and the inner mental
reality. Indeed, images perceive each other,
and are best considered as part of the
whole. Objects are already images, while
perceived objects are subtractions—the qualities
remain with the object, and even the perception is
the result of an 'interaction of perceiver and
perceived' (32). Bergson goes on to say that
pure perception like this, without memory, is just
a convenient fiction, but it is already possible
to see that movement is integral—a flow of
interacting images, with living images as 'a
centre of indetermination', a perception as a form
of action involving selection and reduction of
possible interactions. This general notion
[far too general in my view -- can all objects
have a sensori-motor schema shaping their
perceptions?] of perception is not to be
restricted to human beings, since any image can
perform selective interaction—human perception 'is
simply a subtractive reduced version of the
perception of non living entities'.
We therefore have a 'primal cosmos of images as '"
a gaseous state"… universal rippling: there
are neither axes nor centre, neither right nor
left, high or low"' (33) [quoting Cinema 1].
Not only does the image exist in itself, as a
matter, but there is a connection between image
movements and the flow of matter. This
produces '" a source of plane of
immanence"'. We have temporarily left out
duration, so this can be seen as a mobile cut, a
block of space-time, one of an infinite series,
'"so many presentations of the plane"' (34, still
quoting Cinema 1). Deleuze wants to
go on to see this plane of immanence as featuring
the identity of matter as light, which further
explains the identity of the image and movement,
bringing in the ability to discuss visual
appearances specifically. This does raise
the issue of non visual modes of perception,
however, but it helps us move towards an analysis
of cinema. The visual images in cinema are
now the same as matter itself: the image in itself
is 'a virtual image, a given "block" of
light'(34), and it becomes visible to us through
the process of actualization of a portion of it
[the notion that there is an objective dimension
to perception again]. Thus visual perception
takes place both in the object, and when the
perceiver configures light. Consciousness
itself can be seen to depend on light. [This
sharing between the subjective and the objective,
their common nature as configurations of light
leads to the famous phrase]: 'we may ultimately
look on "the universe as cinema in itself, a
metacinema"'(35). [Includes the objective nature
of the camera as a non-human eye etc --
camerapersons select but they select from what is
already being presented as actualized].
Consciousness is immanent within matter [and
perception follows from the actions of the
metacinema]. What living images do is to
supply a certain indetermination, or gap in
universal interaction. The three kinds of
movement image relate in a different way to this
centre of indetermination. All living images
receive the movements of other things and convert
them into their own movements [still using the
term action, a deliberate blurring of the
difference with humans?]. [Ordinary human]
perception is geared towards action, and permits
an analysis and selection of received
movements. Living images therefore have two
sides, one to receive and one to act.
Perception images are movement-images related to
the receptive side, 'the selective registering of
incoming movements, a framing' (35). They
are things with aspects subtracted from
them. There is a second kind of
movement-image connected to action, however—here,
a perception is affected by expectations and
anticipations, just as the world is arranged for
us around ourselves as the centre [very like Schutz here, with
things arranged around us at the centre, according
to their proximity, and also their
concreteness/anonymity]. This leads to the
notion of an action-image, which locates
perceptions in our concentric worlds: Deleuze
wants to argue that this produces both the action
of things on us, and vice versa.
Affection-images are based on what Bergson says
about qualities. Categories of language,
adjectives, verbs and nouns, emerged from our
organization of transient impressions into
continuities, eventually into objects or bodies,
nouns, with qualities, adjectives, and subject to
repeatable action, hence verbs. Deleuze
notes parallels with perception-images and nouns,
action-images and verbs and affection-images and
adjectives. The link with the latter arises
because perceptions can produce internal
sensations, such as pain—affections which are
qualitatively different from perceptions, although
the two are always copresent. In complex
organisations like human bodies, registering gets
spread among specialized organs. In some
cases, the perception of the impact of an external
movement on the body itself, on the surface of its
organs, like intense light on the surface of the
eye, can have a separate effect, including bodily
reaction: here, perception and affection come
together, but they are usually mixed in different
combinations. We are both centres of
indetermination, and also 'extended bodies in an
interactive field of forces and movements'
(37). Our bodies themselves can encounter
directly external movements and there is no
indetermination or gap, and this possibility can
be constant when we are trying to calculate action
in a more distant way—hence the inevitable mixture
of perception and affection, the ability to
reflect, but the necessity to absorb external
movement and impacts.
Thus we can see affection as arising in the
interval between perceptions and actions,
registered by bodily sensations that accompany our
perceptions as things impact on us. We
understand that the sensations refer to our
qualities as living beings. It also helps us
distinguish between the outside and the
inside. In the interior, we absorb movements
and this produces motor effects [like a reflex
action]. Again we see a connection between
subjects and objects. Deleuze talks about a
'receptive plate' in the interior of our bodies,
and sees this as the same as the black screen
which intersects the virtual photograph in
perception as above. However, affection also
produces the transition between [perception of]
external movement and action, not as a physical
transition, but more as 'a "movement of
expression, that is quality, simple tendency
agitating an immobile element"'(38). This is
seen best of all in the human face, 'a relatively
immobile surface on which are registered motor
tendencies, expressions of pure qualities that
suggest the connections between incoming
perceptions and outgoing actions' [reminds me of
all the bleating about faciality in Thousand Plateaus].
All three kinds of movement images are found
whenever living beings with their centres of
indetermination interrupt flows of matter.
All are connected to the sensori-motor
schemas. Perception-images involve a
selective interpretation of the surrounding world,
action-images locate perceptions in a concentric
world based on the individual, affection-images
produce motor tendencies following the absorption
of external movements, and their representation as
qualities. Affection-images in particular
unite subject and objects, sensations and
perceptions, and produce movements of expression.
In Cinema 2, Deleuze offers a summary of
this material. He says there is both a
vertical and the horizontal axis in ' the "system
of the movement image"' (39). The vertical
axis includes 'the immobile cut, the mobile cut
and the open whole'. The horizontal axis relates
to the three movement images. On the
vertical axis, we see differentiation between the
open whole and a closed set of actual objects,
with its notion of movement as limited and
spatial. On the horizontal axis, we see a
process of specification—the development of three
species of movement images. Bogue says the
vertical axis also refers to the operation of
duration and its constant division and
differentiation, while the horizontal refers to
the processes of perception without
duration. Together, we have '"a plastic
mass, and a-signifying and a-syntactic matter, and
non-linguistically formed matter, though a matter
that is not amorphous but semiotically,
aesthetically and pragmatically formed"'.
This plastic mass can be seen as a plane of
consistency of the image, movement, matter and
duration. Initially, it is identified with
light, but here, it becomes 'all forms of
matter/flow', featuring modulations of all sorts,
sensorial, kinetic, affective, rhythmic as well as
verbal. Films are made from this stuff, and
so are we, as an ensemble of different images,
[perception, action and affection]. Film
directors can shape this material through the use
of frames, cuts, shots and montage (the vertical
processes), and 'long-shot perception-images,
medium-shot action-images, and close up
affection-images' on the horizontal dimension.
Chapter two. Frame, shot, and montage
So matter tends to form isolated systems yet they
still retain connections to duration.
Movement is the 'intermediary between closed sets
and the open whole', because of its mundane and
philosophical aspects, although some sets are more
closed and immobile than others—an 'ideal limit to
the space free of [duration]' (41). Even
here, we can still see an allusion to
duration. We can simplify by referring to
closed sets and open wholes, with closed sets
further subdivided into immobile cuts and mobile
cuts. We can then grasp the effects of
frames, shots and montages, which are present in
all films: frames close sets, the shot shows
endurance over time or a unit of movement, montage
displays even more clearly the open whole of
duration.
Cameras always frame a portion of the
world, and the results are projected on to a
screen, 'functioning as the "frame of frames"'
(42, quoting Cinema 1), since the screen always
limits the camera frame, whether this is a close
up or a long shot. Sometimes there can this
can lead to a disorienting heterogeneity, so in
cinematic images 'there is inherent… a
destabilising force… "A deterritorialization
of the image"'[that is, a non- naturalistic
image]. Framed images have additional
features:
- they are more or less
saturated with content or information;
- they can limit images
either 'geometrically or dynamically' (43),
with examples of the latter as iris shots
[vignettes], or even variable screens that
open and close;
- frames both separate
elements and unite them, and again this may
be geometric or dynamic—'German
expressionist configurations of diagonals
and triangles' on the one hand, and 'images
of fogs, fluids, shifting shadows, undulating shapes and
metamorphosing forms' on the other. In
both senses, we are illustrating
multiplicities, with the latter, qualitative
multiplicities 'not divisible or
indivisible, but "dividual", the closed set
of elements dividing itself in each moment
into a qualitatively different set of
elements' [incomprehensible to me—again, the
philosophical viewer does this dividing?];
- frames have angles or
framing, 'a position in space from which the
framed image is shot… [an]…
Implicit point of view', which may be
naturalistic or not—some can even be
unsettling, out of the narrative, involving
"deframing" [not Deleuze but someone called
Bonnitzer, 43], and they require reading or
interpreting;
- frames include, but
also suggest an "out of field", which,
according to Burch, may be 'above or below
the frame, to the right or left, in-depth
away from the camera [for example behind a
closed door] or toward the camera and beyond
it in the audience's direction [as in direct
addresses to camera?]'. Deleuze thinks
that we can even establish an absolute out
of field, relating to duration again: 'every
framed set of elements may be included
within a larger frame… Until an
ultimate frame of frames includes the entire
universe' (44) [reminds me of the last scene
in Men in Black] , although this
would still not actually represent duration
which can 'never be "given" as such', but
only manifested, often 'in a disquieting
way'. Normal or relative out of field
effects strengthen the conventional notion
of three dimensional space and an abstract
time, and great efforts are made to achieve
continuity between the immediate and its out
of field [realist editing]. However,
some images still suggest something beyond,
some absolute out of field.
Shots can do this. It is important to
realize that for the French the notion of a plan
or a plane incorporates both the English sense of
the shots and the take, spatial and time
relations. What we would call different
sorts of shots are called different sorts of plans
for them—for example 'plan d'ensemble (long
shot)'. In this way, for Deleuze a number
[multiplicity] of spatial determinations can
produce temporal perspectives [so it's all done by
linguistic sleight of hand again], and
quantitative multiplicities are seen as connected
with qualitative ones, especially if the entire
film can be seen 'as a single plan-sequence'
(45). Such shots can produce the two faces
of movement discussed above, [mundane and
philosophical as I have called them]—as the
elements alter, so qualitative change becomes
apparent [so the famous deep shot in Citizen
Kane which shows the suffering wife trying
to kill herself in the foreground changes meaning
as we see the manipulative Kane in the
background?]. This shot in this sense is
intermediary between the frame and the
montage. Deleuze cites the sequence in Frenzy,
where the camera follows a man and woman up a set
of stairs to a door, then backs away as they go in
only to climb the wall and look in through the
window [a marvelous technical achievement, down to
the crew]. This camera movement shows that
something is happening in the whole as various
modifications of the interaction take place: a
meeting turns into a murder. This particular
change is expressed as a narrative, but narrative
is not the only unifier: in general, the shot
decomposes and reunites elements into local
configurations and patterns, sometimes those of
contraction and expansion, sometimes following
some organising figure—a straight line in Rope,
a spiral in Vertigo.
[French] shots or plans are
movement-images, and mobile cuts of
duration. In cinema we see 'movements
disengaged from bodies' (46); it's the camera that
moves and movement takes place between shots and
in montage. Camera movements are themselves
mechanical [can be non-naturalistic again as in
crane shots], pointing to some general notion of
movement, 'the pure movement [abstracted] from
bodies, one that takes on an existence independent
of any specific character or point of view',
despite the efforts of realist directors.
Even realist editing produces an idea of movement
'that to some degree always escapes the bodies
from which it issues' (47). This is often
supplemented [and normalised] by mobile cameras,
which for Deleuze means that fixed shots in early
film illustrate pure movement best.
In the plan or the mobile cut, elements
and dimensions change and produce a [mathematical]
set, 'like a cubist painting'. There may be
no common denominator [although there usually is,
in realism]. Plans themselves may
offer incommensurable points of view. This
ceaseless variation is what makes the film
different from photography. Films show
modulation not just passive registration.
Such modulation is a temporal perspective for
Deleuze. In this way, cinema '"acts like a
consciousness"'(47), developing a nonhuman or
superhuman point of view [which usually matches
exactly the all-knowing narrator in
literature?]. This links with the insistence
that consciousness is in things, including the
initial 'prehensions of brute matter', and only
better actualized in living things. Again,
the universe is a metacinema so that cinema shows
us this consciousness in things in a version we
can recognize, a camera consciousness, autonomous
and able to develop non-human notions of movement
[it all depends on the slippery definitions
again].
Montage is already implied by the plan
[the example here is the extended tracking shots
of Magnificent Ambersons, where a long
tracking shot accompanies one couple as they move
to meet to another couple which we then follow—a
tracking shot replacing an actual montage.
The whole of Slackers is assembled like
this]. Montage deliberately composes the
whole from movement images. It is usual to
see montage as guided by an overall plot , theme
or concept, but for Deleuze it is the form of time
and type of continuity ('narrative, motivic
or discursive' (49)) that unifies. There are four
tendencies in early film making: 'American
organic, Soviet dialectic, French quantitative and
German intensive'(49).
The organic tendency is found in the films of DW
Griffith. His notion of an organism includes
distinct parts, binary pairs such as 'rich/poor,
male/female, North/South'. These appear as
parallels, alternating in the montage. These
parallels can converge, through accelerated
alternation. Close-ups indicate
particular aspects of wholes. Overall we
have '"the alteration of differentiated parts,
that of relative dimensions, that of convergent
actions"'. Deleuze argues that narrative
derives from this conception, and indeed
individual narratives themselves can be composed,
to depict time as a whole, a series of spirals
[the example is Intolerance, which
apparently involved narratives from different
civilisations, ancient and contemporary life—'such
as that of the Babylonian chariot chase and the
modern American automobile - train pursuit'
(50). There is also a depiction of time not
as contracting towards convergence, but as
dilating and generative, depicted by a bird's
flight or a rocking cradle.]
Soviet dialectic as in Eisenstein or Vertov [and
others I've never heard of] was discussed in
Eisenstein's own theoretical writings. He
admired Griffith but saw the formal alterations
between narratives as accepting social divisions
through the parallel structure, above all the
struggles between rich and poor. Instead we
need something more dialectic. For Deleuze
this is still organic, but it is now a matter of
organic growth, with the shots as cells.
However, they have to be juxtaposed in a form of
conflict or collision, the collision of opposites
to produce a higher synthesis. Eisenstein
thought that this process should be guided by a
notion of a 'Golden Section', an allegedly
classical ratio of parts to whole, 8:13,
deliberately unequal and unstable ratio. Battleship
Potempkin shows conflict in every level,
between shots, between sequences, to structure the
plot as a whole—five sections each with unequal
parts to follow the ratio. The overall
effect is meant to show the transition from
quantity to quality, an explosion following
culmination, like the one between water and
steam. Apparently, the moment of culmination
was called pathos, leading Deleuze to talk about a
pathetic jump, where the second instant still
incorporates the first one. The Golden
Section can be seen as a spiral, and pathetic
leads are straight lines that short circuit the
arc, like strings to a bow.
Thus we have continuous organic growth, yet
through discontinuities of forces that produce
qualitative changes. In opposition to
Griffith and his controlled montages [in
convergence and the like], Eisenstein offers
qualitative leaps. Close-ups can also be
used to indicate these leaps because of their
markedly contrasting size and their ability to
illustrate pathos in the sense above [the sudden
realization of the destructive intention of the
guard on the Odessa Steps registered in
close-ups? The sudden realization of their
political power on the faces of the
sailors?]. The spiral itself does not just
relate parallel montages, but generates a
synthesis of conflicting parts and qualitative
leaps. Deleuze says that in this structure
time appears differently, in the interval between
the shots as well as in the whole. The same
ideas are found in other early Soviet films,
despite stylistic differences [one example is
Pudovkin, who also shows dawning political and
class awareness of the subjects]. Vertov
makes a genuine contribution by adopting a more
radical affirmative notion of the dialectic of
matter, found in machines and landscapes and
buildings themselves. He particularly
develops the 'camera consciousness'(53), as in The
Man with the Movie Camera. This
depicts an alternative to organic composition, a
more mechanical one as the interrelation of
movements, captured in the eye of the camera. [see
also Kino
Eye]
There are French and German alternatives to
organic composition too [as usual, they include
lots of early directors whose work I do not know,
although I have come across Jean Renoir, Jean Vigo
and Jermaine Dulac for the first group, and Fritz
Lang for the German expressionists]. Deleuze
sees the difference as one of quantitative or
intensive approaches to movement respectively—when
considering the open whole, it is a matter of
'Kant's mathematical and dynamic sublime, the one
infinite in number, the other infinite in power'
(53). For the French tendency, the quantity
of movement and the metric relations between
movements produce a mechanical
composition of movement images [the examples are
obscure to me, but one turns on the depiction of a
Spanish cabaret dance scene by L'Herbier, where
the dancers lose their personal differentiations
to allude to dancer in general and dance in
general—'the dance becomes a machine' (54)].
Indeed, there is a centrality of machinery in the
French school, both the automaton and steam or
combustion engines, linking energy heterogeneity,
the mechanic and the force. In Vigo's L'Atalante,
the puppets'movements extend the patterns of
action beyond, with the camera looking from behind
the puppets to the pedestrians and to the puppets'
reflection in the shop window. There is no
dialectic unity as in Soviet cinema, rather the
engineer appears as a kind of '"soul" of the
machine', an expression of passions (55).
There is also 'a fascination with water', the
mechanics of fluids.
Apparently, the early directors were particularly
interested in what they called '"photogeny"',
things that look particularly good on film: they
decided the above all the issue was mobility, and
they conceived this again quantitatively, as a
combination of different factors. It might
be a rhythmic motion, it might be a matter of
optimal speed, which may be acceleration or slow
motion. The relevant factors include
'lighting, space, camera angle and distance, the
objects/events filmed, the interrelated movements
of objects and camera' (56). Montage was to
be decided by the optimal rhythm for a particular
configuration. We can understand this in terms of
the maximum quantity of movement relative to a
particular set of elements, but this relative
notion also alludes to the maximum movement in
duration, giving the movement image two faces or
two sides, one facing relative the other absolute
movement. This is like Kant's notion that
mathematical numbers do the same, alluding to
infinity, and sublime is linked to beauty in the
same way. There is even a mathematical
sublime 'something beyond measure of the senses
but graspable by reason' (56), and this was to be
the inspiration for the French school,
illustrating material movement, but the alluding
to 'a conceptual, mental whole' (57) [the
depiction of something emerging from the
interactions of individuals in the dance?].
The aim is to show 'simultaneous co-presence of
temporal movements', leading to a general interest
in French art in simultaneity, and resulting in
triple screens [at the time?] or
'superimpressions'—apparently, Gance shows
Napoleon's face over layered images of a schoolboy
snowball fight. Images are present at the
same time rather than linked in time, alluding to
a different time, 'spiritual simultaneities' (58).
With German expressionist cinema, Deleuze
acknowledges the usual features, like sharp
contrast of light and shadow, diagonals, oblique
angles, themes of madness, hallucination and so
on, but he argues that all these 'arise from a
single conception of movement and light', based on
some 'Gothic line of non organic life and Goethe's
theory of colour'. The break with organic
system leads not to mechanism but to 'gothic non -
organic vitalism', [almost an élan vital?], that
pervades all life and even animates objects—hence
the depiction of automata, or buildings that seem
to have a life of their own, or the nervous energy
that seems to be reflected in diagonals or
zigzags. This principle 'constructs space
rather than merely describing it'(59), and produce
a prolongation of normal limits and new
convergences, 'junctures of accumulation'.
This is seen best in the way in which light is
managed, a matter of particular interest for
Deleuze, as we saw above. In the French
school, there is an allusion to some luminous
matter, the luminous grey, around which light
oscillates, while in German cinema, light becomes
more intense, with light and shadow separate,
'infinite forces in perpetual conflict'. For
Goethe, light is invisible and can only be grasped
when it encounters shadows, so that all the
colours of the visible world should be seen in
terms of opacity. In German cinema, like
varies in its 'intensity in relation to
darkness'(60), with solid objects revealing it as
a presence. Beneath these contrasts, 'the
intensity of non organic life moves in zigzag
patterns, delineating trajectories that guide the
montage links between shots'. Light and
shadow are 'vectors that interconnect
objects… atmospheres, and people' which seem
to assume a life on their own. Again, it is
duration that is being expressed in the various
intensive movements or degrees, expressed in
particular in effects of light. Going back
to Goethe, colours like 'yellow and blue are
movements of intensification', a matter of adding
or subtracting shadow and light. The
midpoint is 'a reddish - purple', seen as some
essence of colour or brilliance, the most
excessive of the visible colours, so brilliant
that it provides excess sensations.
In German film, the effects of brilliance are
displayed as 'scintillation, glistening,
sparkling, fluorescence, phosphorescence,
shimmers, auras, halos' (61). [The only
example are recognized are the burning circles in
The Golem, but there are apparently
phosphorescent demons heads, blazing heads, or
silhouettes as in Nosferatu]. These depict
'"a terrible light...a flash of the infinite"',
and 'intimate the presence of an infinite non
organic force'[which apparently can also be
destructive].For Deleuze, this is an example of
the dynamic sublime produced through overwhelming
force, the same effect as witnessing volcanoes or
waterfalls, which both frighten and thrill,
because we can overcome our fear and realise that
we are superior to nature. We might also be
able to get some notion of spiritual destination,
where everything is consumed, but also we become
aware of nonhuman life, usually rendered as the
divine part in us [shades of Deleuze and
stoicism]. This is not the emergence from
mechanical movement as in the French, but an
notion of uncontrollable dynamic force emerging in
such a way as to disengage from all previous
degrees, culminating in a single point, detaching
itself from normal time as well.
Although Deleuze discusses different kinds of
montage and shocked in considerable detail, his
main point is always that montage refers to
duration, available in the present as a contracted
moment, but alluding to the infinite. This
may be an organic infinite built from an accretion
of parts, it might be a qualitative leap through
the dialectic, and numerical unity hinting at
infinity, or accelerating intensity. Deleuze
is specific discussions should be seen as leading
to 'the implicit conception of the whole that
informs them' (64) [as we saw best in the
discussion of the specifics of German
expressionism]. Intention is everything, and
this helps us distinguish differences even when
similar techniques are used. For the same
reason, the usual claimed differences between
shots' and montage are less relevant.
Overall, the shots' or plan is particularly
special, both offering specification by the
development of different images [perception action
and affection] and also alluding to the closed
se/t open whole relation on the vertical
axis. The next step is to see how particular
signs develop from these early analyses.
Chapter three. Eighteen Signs (more or
less).
The uncertainty arises because Deleuze means
different things by a sign [!]. Deleuze
admires Peirce as the one who classified images
best, particularly signs, although this is only a
general influence, and Bergson is more
central. Peirce at least develop some non
linguistic theory unlike Saussure, and instead of
signifier and signified, Peirce has 'a triad of
representamen - object - interpretant' (66) [and
we know that Deleuze wants to oppose linguistic
semiotics and its privileging narrative -- good
discussion in Cinema 2,
and part of the general rant against linguistic
imperialism in Dialogues].
Narrative depends on the common sense space time
based on effective human action, the pragmatic
world, the sensory motor schema. Deleuze
uses Lewin's term 'hodological space'
[interpersonal space as I recall]. Modern
cinema has abandoned the schema though.
Peirce still privileges the linguistic and the
cognitive, however, seeing signs as permitting
associations of one sign with another so that
knowledge can develop. Also, the triad is
not completely useful in explaining the three
kinds of image in Deleuze, which shows Bergson's
continued influence. Nor does Peirce referr
to images, but rather to '"phaneron" for "that
which appears"' (67). Deleuze discusses
Peirce's notions of firstness, secondness
and thirdness in terms of three kinds of
images—'"something that refers to nothing but
itself, quality or potential, or pure
possibility"… "Something that refers to
itself only through something else, existence,
action-reaction, effort-resistance"…
"Something that refers to itself only in relating
one thing to another thing, relation, law,
necessity"' (67, quoting Cinema 1).
However, these qualities are supposed to be
displayed by all phenomena and all things, and
they coexist in even the simplest perception for
Peirce [all perception includes perceiving
qualities, oppositions and 'a minimal degree of
abductive inference (Thirdness)'.
Nevertheless Peirce can be used to extend
Bergson's types of images, and Deleuze notes
parallels between the affection image and
firstness, the action image and secondness: to tie
up with thirdness, Deleuze has to construct the
notion of 'relation - image', while seeing
the perception - image as something outside of
Peirce's classification, '(a Zeroness)'(68) [as in
a basic starting point?]. We now have two
additional types of movement images as well: 'one
midway between the affection-image and the
action-image (the impulse-image…), the other
between the action-image and the relation-image
(the reflection-image…)'. So we now have six
types of movement images.
It seems that the insistence on perception as a
starting point would have helped Peirce in
deducing the three types of his images through an
analysis of perception, rather than just
announcing them. However, Bogue says the
point of the six images is to bring Bergson in
more centrally—the notion of consciousness as a
centre of indeterminacy leads to a notion of
perception in living images as a filter and a
selective response, compared to a notion of
universal perception, the action and reaction of
non living things. Thus perception images
arise from this field of universal perception, and
it also functions for living beings to provide an
interval or gap—thus it has two aspects or poles,
depending on whether we relate it to a universal
perception and relations, or to filtered ones.
The perception image actually has a triple
quality—a genesis, a composition and function in
consciousness as an interval, and the function in
relating to the whole. It is also more basic
than the other movement images, in a way because
we need to perceive affections actions and
relations as well. This involvement produces
the same kind of triple quality in all the other
movement images. This lies at the bottom of
Deleuze's notion of the sign, which is quite
different from Peirce's—signs relate to types of
images either in terms of their dual composition
or in terms of their genesis [the discussion on
p.69 is pretty dense, but still MUCH better than
the original]. So we can now tabulate the
six movement images and their related signs [and
two useful diagrams appear, PP. 70-71].
In classic cinema, perceptions
appear as subjective points of view, contrasted
with objective images, things viewed from the
inside and from the outside, with a pov inside the
action or outside. However objective images
often shift in and out of the setting, and thus
sometimes sub seemed entirely within subjective
pov. In this way, the cinematic image can be
semi subjective, representing an anonymous pov
[the classic all-seeing narrator]. Deleuze
wants to borrow this notion for his discussion of
free indirect discourse [apparently originating
with Pasolini]. This term is also used to
describe the insinuation of the narrative voice
into the reported or direct voice of the
characters. Deleuze follows Bakhtin in
seeing this as introducing heterogeneity [not a
hierarchy as MacCabe would argue?], producing an
assemblage of enunciation. [I recognized one example,
Antonioni and Red Desert where the
director immerses himself into the protagonist,
reproducing her world but also bringing in his own
aesthetics, even making the camera noticeable:
'characters enter and leave the frame but the shot
seems to continue too long… betraying an
insistent, obsessive camera consciousness'
(72). Similarly, the shift of perspectives
can reveal the action of the camera, especially if
the subject's pov is supplemented in some way, or
contradicted. In free indirect discourse, we
have the characters and a narrator, to represent
this subjective and obsessive camera pov, but they
are not strictly separated, and both can be
indicated by a single shot—there is no autonomous
pov, but rather '"a correlation between a
perception-image and a camera-consciousness that
transforms it"'(73, citing Cinema 1).
Where we have a perception in the frame of another
perception, we have a dicisign. Such
signs reveal the basis or structure of every
perception image, as perceptions of perceptions,
affections, actions and so on.
Deleuze alters terms to make subjective
perceptions those where 'images vary in relation
to a central and privileged image', as when living
images introduce indeterminacy, while objective
perceptions are ones 'in which images vary all in
relation to all', as in constant unmediated
interactions. This brings about the special
usage, so that what we normally think of the
subjective images, like dreams or hallucinations
are really to be seen as objective perceptions,
where we see 'undulations of a single vibratory
flux'. The dicisign therefore is reserved to
a perception image that belongs to a single living
image or centre of determinacy, while that which
perceives things themselves becomes a reume
(based on the Greek term which refers to that
which flows), one which is no longer confined to
the living image but which can show the flow of
matter—often depicted in French cinema as images
of water or fluids.
A third type of perception image, the gramme,
engramme or photogramme goes further,
developing the notion of the cinematic eye able to
perceive all the points in a space, all actions
and reactions. It is a 'gaseous
perception'(74). Showing how 'universal
matter flow' relates together all the molecular
images [specific objects]. Is therefore seen
as a genetic sign, compared to the sign of
composition in the dicisign [God this is dull OCD
type philosophy, Deleuze at his worst. Like R-W in
Boundas says --who has
ever actually botherd to try to apply any of this
stuff? The whole thing is ridiculously arbitrary
and unreplicable], and these are opposed in that
the first one is universal, and the second one
related to the subject. The reume lies
between, closer to the dicisign because it still
is a sign of composition, although it offers a
more free floating pov, but one which can still be
grasped by common sense: the gramme breaks with
common sense.
An example of the gramme is Vertov's kino-eye,
which intended to escape all commonsense notions
of time and space,and perceive without limits.[So
Vertov claimed himself, especially for TMMC].
Deleuze thinks significant the discovery of the
genetic element of the image, or the photogramme,
the single still image becomes 'a generative cell
of movement', especially when Vertov reanimates
stills, makes them run on, or combined slow motion
with normal speed or even reverses. It
represents 'movement compressed into a micro
interval'(75), and this is how the film can go
beyond human perception to the genetic, to focus
on the single element of energy, a molecular
perception, suggesting that molecules can interact
fully and freely—akin to the difference between
solid, liquid and gaseous states, with the
dicisign as the solid, reume as liquid, and gramme
as gaseous.
[Pause before going on to affection images...]
Affection images live in the interval between
perceptions and actions, often located in
specialised functions such as particular body
parts—in humans, the face. Deleuze borrows
Bergson in seeing affection as containing a motor
tendency following sensation, as in facial
movements of expression, produced by contrasting
the immobile surface and the active
features. In portraiture, it is possible to
emphasise either of these, and Deleuze goes on to
discuss a philosophical notions of 'the passions
of admiration... and desire' (77)—admiration
offers a maximum of expression with a minimum of
movements, while desire offers a series of small
movements which can escape the calm appearance of
the face, and threaten a qualitative shift.
Hence intensive desiring faces express the power
to change qualities, while reflective faces
display qualities common to several objects [this
tedious and waffling discussion culminates in
another table, page 77. I have not
reproduced it for fear of losing the will to
live].
The close up is the classic way to show the face
in cinema, and for Deleuze this reveals the face
in abstract, it 'deterritorializes the face' and
changes it from its conventional functions of
individuating, socialising and communicating
between two persons (78). The face becomes
autonomous, a communicating surface, and thus an
affection-image possessing both an expression [an
expressing capacity] and that which is
expressed. Faces become icons, and
each icon has both 'trait'and a 'contour'
pole. Icons of both types [limits
presumably] both indicate that they are signs of
composition, revealing intervals between one
quality and another on particular faces, or
between multiple elements on a reflective face as
above. Affection appear as in a pure form,
and this is what Peirce refers to as firstness,
pure qualities without context. Deleuze goes
on to distinguish the actualization of real
connections as opposed to 'virtual conjunctions',
beyond normal space and time. Although faces
are the most obvious examples, close ups of any
object can reveal its pure qualities, so once more
'affect… is not strictly human' (79), and we
can see, for example in a close up of the knife of
Jack the Ripper, qualities that are interacting
while impersonal.
Dreyer has developed a close up to become a
flowing close up [like a zoom out], still
displaying a lack of depth and perspective
coordinates, flat images. This is another
way of making affect visible for Deleuze, and he
also finds this in Bresson [Pickpocket,
which I have not seen]—apparently, a space is
depicted in a fragmented form, with incomplete
parts of objects and no common measure, which
disorients. This is the 'any - space -
whatever' (ASW)—a '" singular space"' which has
'"lost its homogeneity", opening the possibility
of an infinite number of linkages or connections,
a virtual conjunction (80). Affect appears
via the decontextualizing space and raising 'yet -
to - be - actualised possibilities' [delirious and
overheated, a kind of Stendhal reaction to film
instead of tourist sites].
ASWs have their own signs to express their
quality-power—the qualisign '(or
potisign)'(80). These correspond to the
gramme in making visible quality-powers in a
decontextualized space, but are fully beyond
common sense and the sensori-motor schema.
Again these are genetic, showing how local
configurations are actually composed. ASWs
can be constructed by using shadows to break the
contours of objects, through '"lyrical
abstraction"' (81) as in Dreyer and Bresson, or
where the goal is to contrast actual and virtual
to illustrate limits of the one and the
possibilities of the other. In Bresson, the
actual space is normally white, black represents
impotence and grey our indecision, but sometimes
the protagonist can '"choose to choose"' and the
colours become components of a new world [must
track this through Jeanne D'Arc]: this
spiritual decision constitutes affect.
Colour is the third possibility, and colour
qualities can absorb objects which can
decontextualise them—the deserted landscape as an
absorbent. This leads to two kinds of
qualisigns—'of disconnection and of vacuity',
although the one always implies the other.
However, overall, the ASW '"no longer has
coordinates, it is a pure potential, it exposes
only pure Powers and Qualities independently of
the states of things or milieus that actualise
them' (82).
[Pause for a while again, dear reader...I made a
cup of tea and let out the cat]
Between the virtual ASW and the actual milieu of
action, is another domain, one of impulses, drives
or instincts. Hence the impulse - image,
usually associated with naturalism and found in
films by Von Stroheim, Bunuel, and Joseph
Losey. It can be seen as if human beings are
being portrayed as animals driven by natural
instincts, but for Deleuze, these directors showed
that 'the primordial world of drives and forces'
is 'immanent to the real world of concrete
particularities', an originary world formed of
rough unfinished forms or fragments, or basic
energy dynamisms, 'a kind of primal swamp from
which the material world arises and an ultimate
garbage dump into which all matter eventually
passes' (83). Impulses develop entropically
[as in The Exterminating Angel—marvelous
film!], as a kind of law of gravity. That
originary world becomes apparent in swamps,
deserts, or bourgeois drawing rooms when they
can't escape. [As we might expect],
actualized spaces are both mundane and pointing to
the virtual, and films can depict these in a kind
of continuum as in the degradation of the drawing
room. Thus originary worlds mediate between
ASWs and actual milieus, tied to the actualised
world, but capable of showing how it is derived
[and the example is the surreal bits in
naturalistic films as in Bunuel]. Impulses
mediate between affects and actions, embedded in
real situations as 'protoactions'[the
example is the fetishized sex drive of the old guy
in Diary of the Chambermaid that manifests
itself in continually making the same proposition
about boots to the different maids]. Humans
can display animal qualities as a result of their
impulses, so can fetishism: these in turn can
become good or evil, either relics or '"vults
or voodoo objects"'(84, quoting from Cinema 1).
Thus impulse-images are represented as symptoms or
fetishes, both representing fragments, although
Deleuze goes on to argue that symptoms belong to
the originary world, while fetishes appear as
fragments tied to or found in the actualized
world. Whatever the actual specification,
the originary world becomes 'the genetic elements
from which the impulse-image arises' (85), just as
the ASW is for the affection-image.
[Another pedagogic pause before we move on to
action-images.. This is hard bloody yakka.]
The action image 'has the greatest affinity with
narrative' (85), but again narratives presuppose
'configurations of movement images'. Here,
we have not originary or virtual contexts, but
'determinate milieus and actual behaviour'.
The domain here is realism, actualised qualities
and powers, and affects and impulses actualised in
behaviours. Indeed, this is how Deleuze
defines realism—incarnated [sic] milieu and
behaviour, and the various relations between the
two. Actualised milieu also curve around
living images, just like their consciousness does,
so there he is in realism a notion of global
synthesis, all those forces configured together
that affect the living image and instigate actions
and reactions. This corresponds to Peirce's
secondness, where some things appear through
reactions with other things. Deleuze
preserves the notion that the actual therefore
implies two elements, 'dyads, oppositions,
reactions and resistances', between elements in
the milieu and with one's self.
The large form becomes the SAS [see my notes on Cinema 1]—the
structure of situation, action and modification of
the situation, an hourglass convergence of broad
situations narrowing into specific actions and
then expanding again. The milieu in question
is designated by a synsign, an ensemble of
forces ('qualities-powers') actualised in a
milieu. Actions are associated with the binomial
sign, to indicate the duel, oppositions and so on
within the self. Together these compose the
large form action image. Examples include
documentaries such as Nanook of the North
struggling with his hostile milieu, westerns where
the landscape is the milieu within which actions
take place, but there are several other examples
including King Vidor, Hawks and Huston.
There are five laws which describe the workings of
the large form:
- The depiction of the
milieu such as configuration of the landscape
as a series of impinging forces and settings,
and how this curves around particular
characters, the 'rhythms of the milieu's
"respiration''' (87, the alternation between interior and exterior,
'primary and secondary situations, panoramas
and close ups'
- The passage from milieu
to action, as synsigns become binomials, a
'climactic duel', often through 'an
alternating montage of interrelated actions'
[the example is the final hunt for the killer
in M]
- The '"forbidden
montage"', where convergent forces eventually
meet in a single shot, a scene where 'the
conflicting forces are simultaneously
present', the final shootout in the western
- The '"nesting"'of one
duel within another [my example would be the
series of conflicts their sherriff needs to
undergo in High Noon—with his neighbours, with
his wife—before he confronts the bad guys]
- The 'law of the "great
gap"', between the surrounding milieu and the
eventual action, as the hero gradually
realises that he has to do something.
There is [almost inevitably] an additional third
sign, the stamp or impression—the milieu
'impregnates' the character and this finally
explodes into action. The impregnation is
done through certain emotional objects, which can
be introduced in various sequences. Deleuze
admires Method acting which show this link between
internal emotions and the milieu, through a
'discovering an inner emotional analogue to an
external situation and establishing a link between
the two by manipulating and milieu object (or
glove, knife, ball, etc.)'(88).
As well as SAS there is also ASA, and this
produces the notion of the small form, as an
equivocal action clarifies the situation that
permits a new action. The differences can be
seen in the detective film as opposed to the crime
film, which starts with fragmented actions and
tries to explain them in terms of an underlying
situation [the example is The Maltese Falcon].
There are other reciprocal versions of the costume
drama, or some of the early documentaries say of
Grierson as opposed to Flaherty. Comedy also
depends on 'the equivocal nature of the characters
actions'[examples include misunderstandings based
on misleading identities, or ambiguous actions'
being revealed to be something different, not
shaking with grief, but shaking a cocktail in a
Chaplin example]. Such signs are called
indexes, following peirce—'a sign of the
existence of recurrence of some concrete singular
entity or state external to the signs—smoke, for
example by an index of fire' (89). Sometimes
what is indexed is a lack or a hole in the story,
something that needs to be gradually filled
in. There are also indices of equivocity,
which point to different directions as it were,
with shaking, above.
Both indexes of lack and equivocity are
the 'two signs of composition of the Small Form
action- image'. The genetic sign is the
vector, and we see this in the small form's
'skeleton space', the framework of elements, the
underlying wire form [to use a modern
notion]. The example, apparently is drawn
from Chinese painting [with which I am fully
familiar, of course]. The fragments and
appearances communicate with each other even now
they are heterogeneous. Deleuze obviously admires
the zigzags and indirect connections, which he
clearly wants to line up with all that tosh about
the line of the universe. The examples
include the construction of 'a skeleton - space'
(90) in Mizoguchi, with its slow pans and
tracking, through an across houses and
neighbourhoods, sometimes with a dissolve with a
flow across to a field of forest. The camera
movement is the 'line of the universe' joining
heterogeneous elements, constructing a series of
spaces each with their own dramatic intensity,
each affecting the character. One example
familiar to me is Ugetsu, where the camera
follows the bewitched potter and the demon
princess from a palace room into a forest, then
into a poor, then it tracks across rocks and over
open ground dissolving to a shot of the soil of
the garden, and this, apparently links three
spaces with different 'rhythms, trajectories and
moments of dramatic climax'(91) [not all how I
read it I must say! I could see some
connections being suggested, but I read these as
mundane episodes in an overall depiction of a
relationship. Left to their own devices, non
philosophical readers will always impose their own
naive common sense realism]
In the small form of the action image, actions
themselves are linked to situations but also to
themselves. We may experience this through
narrative and story, but some filmmakers avoid
smooth transitions [the example is the westerns
directed by Anthony Mann], and focus on the
intensity of present situations and follow 'the
shortest path'[not the straight line as we know]
to link two actions in ASA. Vectors usually
traverse skeletons spaces, but not always [there
is not always a spatial linked, but sometimes a
direct one between action in different local
spaces].
[Pause again before encountering the reflection
image]
The reflection image is also a transformation
image, between action images and relation images,
and allowing , for example the transition between
the large and small forms of the action
image. Reflection produces signs called figures
which show these transitions and
transformations. The reflection image can
offer an indirect link between large and small
forms, and can be considered as a subspecies of
the relation-image, although it remains tied to
action images, and thus takes on an intermediary
form between action and relation. Examples
are drawn from Eisenstein's Ivan the Terrible,
part 2—Ivan's bodyguards act as an
assassination as a pantomime, and this 'prefigures
a future action'(93), as a necessary link between
the situation, the real plot to assassinate Ivan,
and the subsequent action where Ivan tricks one of
the plotters into impersonating him. This
performance can be seen as an index of
equivocation, in the sense above. The whole
sequence links the large form SAS to the small
form, since the action in the middle indexes the
small form and introduces a small form into the
large. [Another Eisenstein example follows,
but I have not seen the film—again, a small action
acts as a kind of metaphor or index, so that the
small form produces a larger sequence, or an
action becomes an index in order to trigger off
subsequent action in the small form].) Deleuze
wants to discuss these possibilities as two kinds
of sign—'sculptural/plastic and
theatrical/scenographic', indicating these
two forms of relation as above, the jerk.
There are two additional reflection image signs—'figures
of inversion and discursive figures (or
figures of discourse)' (94). We thus have 4
signs which can be categorised, playfully, Bogue
assures us, by linking it to someone else's
taxonomy of figures. Thus the plastic figure
becomes the same as metaphor metonym in and
synechdoche; the theatrical figure is akin to
allegory, hyperbole and irony; inversion in
literature is often done for dramatic effect [the
example is 'to the battle he came'], and the same
goes for cinema; the figures of thought 'entail no
change in the words themselves, but a change in
the way one thinks about them' (94, with the
bizarre example of prosopopoeia, where dead or
imaginary people are represented as
speaking). In the second cinema book, these
four classifications becomes three, divided into 2
signs of composition, plastic and theatrical
become a figure of attraction, and the
inversion figure remains, and 1 genetic
sign, the discursive [for the purposes of
philosophical tidiness, no doubt].
Inversion is illustrated with reference to Hawks,
where landscapes cease to be englobing milieus and
become mere functional settings, non organic and
inactive, and where to disruptive challenge comes
from the interior. Outside and inside our
inverted. Other inversions include male
female, and adult child, high speech low speech,
and love and money. These are persistent
enough, Deleuze thinks, to take on the role of an
autonomous figure. The discursive figure is
illustrated through Chaplin's later comedies, or
where the burlesque of the small form, as in the
equivocal action discussed above persists in, say,
similar moustaches between the Jewish barber and
the dictator, but the barber's discourse at the
end of the film makes explicit that it is the
social worlds that are all important. As a
result, the situations in the film take on a new
dimension and significance, even small ones, such
as the twitching of the moustaches. In this
way, the small form of the burlesque takes on the
larger form explaining how social worlds are all
important in the creation of dictators or liberty.
The discursive figure is also genetic, because it
directly refers to or reflects its proper object,
even where this is the relation between action and
situation. The discursive figure makes
possibilities manifest.
The obsessive categorisation is less important [!]
Than the general processes of transformation
within action images, which can include a
transformation between the forms, but also of
internal transformations, sometimes in the form of
an emerging question that must be solved in order
to be able to act [the example is The Seven
Samurai, where the enduring question is what
is a samurai these days]. If the hero
doesn't recognise the question, but simply
response the immediate situation, he usually
perishes [Japanese Macbeth misinterpreting the
witches prediction]. If he does respond, he
can emerge into the larger milieu, becoming an
imprint, linking action and situation. The
question remains tied to the situation, however,
and Kurosawa specialises in showing how situations
develop into these big questions. An
alternative is to stretch the small form, as in
Mizoguchi, constructing skeletons spaces and using
the camera to link them in a way that suggests 'a
vision of an unlimited cosmos with a "very special
homogeneity"' (99), had joined by the line of the
universe. In his films, it is the women that
transgress and links the spaces, and often get
punished for that, and this is the limit of the
action image, when hierarchy reasserts itself and
breaks the line of the universe [although it seems
that Deleuze is arguing that order is never fully
restored, and some disorientation remains—if the
sensori-motor schema breaks down, movement images
can dissolve].
[A pause before the final bit on the
relation-image—bear with me, nearly there...]
The relation-image is akin to Pierce and
thirdness, 'the category of continuity,
regularity, habit, rule, law, interpretation,
representation, and thought,, where first and
second are related (99). In this way,
relations become intelligible, through a process
of the sign mediating between objects and
interpretant and this is the basis of all
intelligible relations, all notions of law or of
development. There is a universal tendency
to regularize relations, moving from indeterminacy
to regularity, of generality, a kind of 'habit
forming'(100). The origin of habit lies in
mind, so that matter is simply rigid habit that
seems to have escaped the ability to form and
reform. Scientific laws similarly are
'rigidifying habits', part of a general process of
generality or evolutionary development. This
generality requires connecting two things by a
third, for example some rule or formula. All
signs display these three part characteristics,
for Peirce, [and active semiosis develops them as
understanding?]. The sign itself is best
understood as a relation between objects and
interpreter, or actually between 'representamen
(the sign vehicle), an object and an interpretant
(that which interprets)'. Every interpretant
can become a sign itself, pointing to another
sign, leading to an open process of interpretation
or '"infinite semiosis"'. This open process
is guided by the generalising tendencies of habit,
however, signs help to establish these habits [by
being applied to different objects via analogy and
so on?]. There is therefore always a mental
element connecting actions, and that is what
thirdness is, the notion of a relation.
This helps Deleuze develop the notion of the
relation-image, as 'the mental image, a "figure of
thought" in which the mental is introduced into
the image'[at last, human consciousness is given a
proper role!] Mental activity is in place in the
other images as well, as in consciousness
[awareness?] in an affection-image, or the
intentions in action-images, but relation-images
directly refer to '"relations symbolic acts and
intellectual feelings"'(101). We can now
treat perceptions as interpretations, signs as
mediated by other signs in a whole chain, actions
as necessarily including symbolic elements, of law
for example. [And we come close at last to
the idea that this is what separates human action
from behaviour]. Even affections are
interpreted by using logical conjunctions, or
other intellectual notions of relation.
Hitchcock develops relation-images best, since
everything has to be interpreted or deciphered, as
signs 'force themselves on characters'. This
is registered on the faces of the characters,
where expressions disclose intellectual notions of
relations, such as 'the affects of "if", "hence",
"although" and so on'. All the action in
Hitchcock is structured around these mental
relations, what Hitchcock apparently called
postulates, sets of relations which then have to
unfold. This is what made Hitchcock refuse
the title of the whodunit, which plainly has an
author of the action. What is distinct to
Hitchcock therefore is a representation of
thirdness, where a criminal act emerges from a set
of relations, including accidental meetings on
trains, or young men in Rope trying to
impress their teacher, and accidental involvement
in a murder in Rear Window. The
characters can unravel these relations, but above
all, the camera does it for the audience—the
audience must be engaged, in the famous
'suspense'. The relation itself is indicated
in a relation-image, displayed by figures of
thought as signs.
There is a difference between 'natural relations
and abstract relations', however. Leading to
a new classifications of relation signs. Natural
signs emerged from habit, 'customary or
ordinary mental relations'. Abstract
signs involve non habitual connections, and
the deliberate construction of a whole rather than
a series. The signs of composition are 'the
mark and the demark'(103), the first one
being the natural relation, located in the
customary series so that they can be easily
interpreted by being members of a series [same old
objects, easily classified]. Demarks break
with series and unsettle habit—the crop duster
inexplicably turning to attack the hero.
However, the disruption depends on a series of
ordinary marks [doesn't seem very different from
the ambiguous object discussed above]. The
genetic sign of the relation image is the
symbol, 'the sign of an abstract relation
that constitutes a whole', as when a ring
symbolises a marriage [looks like a metonym to
me]. Terms are to be compared in a
nonhabitual natural way, and initially, any term
might be included: Deleuze argues that this
indicates the possibilities of all mental
relations, so the mark and demark become special
limiting cases.
Overall then, we have 14 signs of the movement
image, or possibly 23 [one difference is whether
you distinguish between icons, all the different
kinds of qualisigns or fetishes]. Whether or
not there are specific differences doesn't matter
[! forgiving Deleuze's OCD] , because the taxonomy
is supposed to just generate new terms for talking
about cinema and seeing. It is the
underlying concepts and logic that matter, the
mesh of dyadic and triadic relations, which
together form 'acentred, rhizomatic combinations'
(104). It is not the sign that interests
Deleuze primarily, but rather images, which are
not simply neatly divided into three types of
sign, but which possess a wider potential as
'"signaletic matter"' (105), that directors [only?
not crew, actors etc? Leads to seeing films as
over designed, containing only one readings etc?]
shape like sculptors: 'Deleuze's taxonomy is
merely a tool for inventing a language adequate to
those sculptures and the creative processes that
generate them'. We have seen that the main
movement images related to particular kinds of
signaletic matter—'gaseous perceptions,espaces
quelconques [ASW], originary worlds,
respiration -/skeleton-spaces, metaphysical
respiration -/skeleton-spaces, mental "relations
spaces"', and each involve new ways of
seeing. For example 'gaseous perception is
seeing from all perspectives at once'
[meaningless? All possible perspectives?], with
the other kinds of seeing it as more
limited. In ASWs, we see affective spaces,
qualities and powers. Originary worlds help
us see 'impulses and energies'. In
respiration spaces we see 'rhythmic contraction
and dilation of milieu and action'. In
skeleton spaces, we can see 'both an action world
and an Idea imminent within it', such as
situations and questions, or limited vectors and
unlimited lines of the universe. In mental
relation spaces we can see relations 'within a
concrete, tangible world'. The point is to
open possibilities to the imagination, to go
beyond what commonsense cannot see—'affects,
energies, rhythms, vectors, ideas, and mental
relations', and to illustrate that these can be
seen in film.
Chapter four Hyalosigns: crystals of time
Movement images relate to matter and its
'signaletic' qualities, and the signs express
these qualities. There is a conception of
time also offered, but cinema provides a different
notion as well in the form of the time
image. We see this first in 'pure optical
and sonic images that break the sensory motor
schema (what Deleuze calls opsigns and sonsigns)'
(107). We also have memory images and dream images
that connect these signs together— mnemosigns and
onirosigns. But there is also the time
crystal or crystal image and hyalosigns, which
reveals time directly. There are others too,
which are discussed in later chapters.
In classic Hollywood films, there is a notion of
'the seamless and continuous presentation of
action within a single time and space'
(108). After the war, the sensory motor
schema collapses, and we start to see films like Nashville,
with a much looser connection between actions and
milieus, gaps in the action with weak linkages and
connections [the examples are Cassavete's films],
'an aimless wandering'[Taxi Driver], and
the appearance of '"the stroll, the balade [ramble,
jaunt] and the continual round trip
journey"'. We also find the creation of
deliberate clichés and parody, or 'diffused
conspiracies anonymous plots and ubiquitous
technological surveillance'. In the absence
of the sensory motor scheme, integration is
provided either by 'a network of circulating
clichés or a conspiratorial system of
surveillance'. This is still only a negative
critique, however and the emergence of a positive
time image needs
more than critique and mockery.
The time image emerges in Italian neo realism,
with the depiction of optical situations, not
linked to action images, such as 'an every day
series of motor actions' which lead to the
characters suddenly seeing something, 'pure
seeing', unrelated to the action—the realities of
poverty and misery, or the lives of others in
postwar reconstruction. There is still a
narrative, but the characters almost become
spectators rather than active participants.
These are opsigns, found in Deleuze's favourite
Italian directors. Distinctions such as
those between objective and subjective, real or
imaginary are rendered indiscernible. For
example in Fellini there may be memories or
dreams, yet these contain 'a practical staging',
making the mental world like a rehearsal, while
the real world becomes a spectacle [8 ½ is
apparently the best example] this is how opsigns
can subvert conventions like narratives.
They represent something that exceeds our normal
capacities to manage. They are the opposite
of cliché. This links with Bergson's notion
of managing memories through selection, and this
can be disrupted when new associations for
objects, or ignored characteristics appear.
Opsigns have to be combined with '"growing
powers"' (111) that force the entire image to be
read, that appear as thought, that open them to
revelations. Opsigns can then develop into
chronosigns, lectosigns and noosigns.
Deleuze shows how opsigns appear in memories and
dreams, then crystals of time, then 'full fledged
chronosigns'(111). Opsigns are detached from
sensory motor schema and have to be connected
together differently. Memory helps us see
how this is done, and Deleuze relies on Bergson:
present objects are recognized by drawing upon
past memories, and this is often automatic,
appearing in an action, not necessarily a
representation. Such recognition is guided
by sensory motor patterns that are acted out
in ordinary life. Here, 'the perception
image and memory image occur in the same instant'
(112). We can attend more explicitly, to
summon up remembered images, through reflection,
and mould it to the present object. The
process here is akin to reading a text—assembling
meaning and anticipating [which incidentally
provides the '"the illusion of being there"', 112,
quoting Bergson]. It is the same when we
walk through familiar streets. When we pay
full attention, we add additional memory images
from wider zones of the past, forming larger
circuits to which present objects can be
connected. The same processes of automatic
and reflective perception apply in cinema, and
indicate that the sensory motor schema can be
engaged or relaxed respectively—in the 'pure
optical situation', (114) it is suspended
altogether, producing a virtual image.
We can see the circuits between the present and
memory as well, sometimes represented on the faces
of the characters. Sometimes the image of
the past is ambiguous, however, and can become
'strange and unreal, dreamlike,
hallucinatory'. This can produce confusion,
or, more generally, indiscernibilty.
We can see what goes on explicitly in the
flashback, say where every action is linked to a
flashback. Again this can be controlled by a
conventional narrative, but sometimes, flashbacks
become more genuine time images, with a non
realist logic, something inexorable, and destiny
that structures the past, something beyond
determinism and causality. The examples are
Mankiewicz's films, which illustrate for works of
time, temporal labyrinths. All About Eve
can be seen as a conventional narrative, but also
alludes to 'a bifurcating time', with memories
held by multiple narrators, and the depiction of
branching paths. The conventions of
Hollywood forbid that these paths should be
mutually contradictory, but at least they produce
'unpredictable breaks' (116) [There is a definite
sense that history repeats itself, I thought, in All
About Eve, but apparently, each of the
events in the narrative is an 'improvisatory
moment, a zigzag movement towards stardom', which
Deleuze saw as a break with causality—the
flashbacks are the only way we can understand
Eve's unpredictable [contingent] career
path. Again the conventional reading would
be that this is an ambitious, opportunist and
ingenious individual, like an entrepreneur].
There are conventional flashbacks, which stick to
normal chronology, and are selected for their
practical value, but we all have experience of
dreams, where our sensory motor scheme relaxes,
and our ability to access images expands.
It's not surprising that we find dream sequences
in films, conventionally indicated by special
effects [like dissolves]. Sometimes, the
world seems to become the personalised, acting in
ways that the subject themselves can no longer
do. Usually, however they are fully
integrated back to the normal time space—except in
musicals. In dance sequences, 'narrative
time is suspended, objects and people are
conjoined in improbable combinations and
configurations, and space is frequently
metamorphosed as one setting flows into another'
(117). The movements of the dancer become
parts of this the wider world, as if in a
dream. In the best musicals, for Deleuze
[those directed by Minnelli], normal and dream
worlds alternate, producing an indiscernibility
between the real and imaginary.
Usually, convention wins out with flashbacks and
dream sequences. However sometimes we see the
point of indiscernibility itself, time crystals,
which are represented by hyalosigns [apparently
from the Greek word for glass]. Bergson
discusses deja-vu as arising from time perception
and memory themselves. The usual view is
that memories are fainter versions of perceptions,
but Bergson suggest that in fact a memory image
coexists with each perception image, so the actual
existence is doubled by virtual existence—hence
the idea that the present produces one stream
which falls back towards the past and the other of
which aims at the future. We can see this
when we find ourselves suddenly unable to do
something that we used to do, so that we
experience ourselves as two individuals, one
performing, while the other one observes, as a
spectator. The performing self is often
experienced as being an automaton, playing a role,
and this is often associated with deja-vu.
Actually it is produced from the difference
between automatic perception, which is largely
unconscious, and our activities when we remember,
which is reflective, but also passive [experienced
as arising from somewhere else]. This also
shows us that memory is not just a matter of
personal subjectivity, that the past
'preserves itself by and in itself… as a
single domain, and hence as a kind of gigantic
memory… Each mind is inside memory, like a
fish in the ocean' (119). In Deleuze's
terms, '"time is the interiority in which we are,
in which we move, live and change"'.
The present is double, both 'an actual present
perception and a virtual memory of the present', a
coexistence. Usually, the difference is
indiscernible, producing an "'objective
illusion"'(119, quoting Cinema 2).
This is a real doubling, not something that just
goes on in consciousness. The same
combination of actual and virtual images can be
found in cinema, a process that Deleuze says is
like a photographic image coming to life and
becoming independent, even while it took its place
back in the photograph in '"a double movement of
liberation and capture"'(119-20). Robbe-Grillet
has noticed this double movement. It is a
break with the usual view that the object exists
independently of the description. Instead
'"crystalline"' descriptions refer to the '"purely
optical and sonorous situations, detatched from
their motor continuation"'. This sounds just
like the opsign, although there is a deliberate
bringing together of the virtual and the actual:
this is the genetic element of opsigns and their
composition, reflected in the more specific
opsigns.
Deleuze seems to confuse objective illusions like
mirror images, and the issue of
representation. However, representation only
takes place within sensori-motor schemas, and when
this collapses, there is no difference between
presentation and re-presentation, objects and
appearances—all become 'simply images'. It
is like the difference between a conventional
optical illusion and a deliberately artistic
illusion aiming to combine the virtual and the
actual. The effect is that we are not just
like actors but that we become actors, that once
the sensory motor schema collapses, all that is
left is theatre or spectacle, or play of
images. Thus crystal images in film are
reflections 'in the broader sense of the term'
(121), not just the usual actual mirror images of
photographic images or whatever. We find
crystal images in painting and theatre as well.
The simplest model is when we see an actress
looking at herself in the mirror and becoming the
actual image, playing a role that is actualized in
a film. The actress and her character are
co-present. The role being played its part
of 'a fictional world that reflects the real
world'. Although the fictional world
initially becomes a virtual in relation to the
actual real world, it becomes actual. All
this is normally understood from within a sensory
motor schema, but once that collapses, all these
distinctions become indiscernible, 'unassignable
in the sense that one can no longer determine
definitively the category to which a given image
belongs' (122). When directors deliberately
play with these relationships, they are
re-presenting reality, offering a world as 'the
proliferation of reflections', indicating
precisely the 'simultaneity of the virtual and the
actual'.
Usually, the directors simplify things by
sequencing the link between actual and virtual, so
we see a shot of the actress's face, and then the
mirror image. However, this convention can
be broken, so that both our images, and one
reflection leads to another, in a whole
'proliferation of reflection images', as in the
sequence in The Lady from Shanghai in the
hall of mirrors. This is what makes the
crystal image differ from a simple mirror
image. There are other differences, in that
the surface of the crystals can also be
transparent, or filter light, with 'varying
degrees of limpidity or opacity' (123), which are
affected by their surroundings.
We can also see a genetic process, of
crystallization itself, around a seed crystal,
perhaps. There may be different types of
crystallization. Again the seed serves as a
virtual that is actualized in a milieu of
potential crystallization. Overall then,
there is '"crystalline circuit"'involving
the actual and the virtual, the limpidity and the
opaque, the seed and the milieu. Deleuze
intends this to describe entire films, where
different facets are explored, and the process of
crystallization revealed in an overall 'giant
crystal image' (124). [ The example here is
Fellini And the Ship Sails On, where the
world of appearances on board appear as a
newsreel, and cameramen themselves appear in the
footage, opera soloists break into song and the
crown joins in, grey and sepia tones give way to
colour images, cooks and waiters on board dance,
while the diners synchronize, and correspondences
are established between aristocratic passengers
and proletarian crew, between dining room and
backstage kitchen, between opera singers in the
engine room, between performers and
audiences. The arrival of some rescued
refugees becomes a seed crystal for further socio
political connections between the ship and the
historical world, as a warship appears to demand
them back, 124-5]. Fellini uses all the techniques
of blending art and life—films within films, films
being made, the notion of the world as theatre or
as narrative, as a ritual or as dance.
Reflection and image change positions.
As well as the three figures mentioned above [the
actual/virtual, the limpid/opaque, the seed/the
milieu] producing three hyalosigns, as components
of all crystals, there are also several states of
the crystal, indicated by crystal images
themselves, again of several types just as real
crystals are. There are four crystalline
states in particular, and each refer to time, and
the processes of actualization of the virtual in
different ways. Each of these can be
indicated by looking at the whole oeuvre of a
director [suspiciously neat and showing the real
importance of classification based on auteurs]:
- The perfect crystal, and
Ophuls. The world is a spectacle or
theatre, and theatrical sets merge into
streets, narrator's play parts, scenes from
the past come to life, circular motifs appear,
including time as circular [the examples are La
Ronde and Lola Montès].
This is the perfect crystal because the actual
and virtual images coexist in the same overall
development.
- The cracked crystal in
Renoir. There is the same emphasis on
spectacle and the theatre [the example here is
The Golden Coach, where travelling
actors parallel the real world plot, and there
are several shots where theatres merge with
real sets. However, there is still some
life beyond, and divisions are restored,
producing 'a crack, a line of flight, in the
crystal of time' (128). The Rules of
the Game seems to offer a perfect self
contained crystal, where the amateur stage
links with the larger social stages, living
beings are reflected in automata and humans
and animals, the aristocrats parallel the
servants and vice versa: no escape seems
possible, and people cannot leave except by
dying. All are trapped by the rules of
the game, past conventions and customs.
In the Grand Illusion and The
River, however, some characters do
escape convention. For Deleuze, it is
the past that is crystallised, yet it is still
split, in the same sense that, for Bergson,
time splits into the past and the
future. Despite the fixity of the past,
sometimes characters are able to emerge into a
genuine life beyond the theatre, leaving the
crystal and escaping '"the eternal recurrence
of the actual and the virtual"' (129, quoting
Cinema 2).
- The growing crystal in
Fellini. There is the usual material on
the world is a carnival spectacle, tableaux
and clown shows, where each scene offers an
entry to a different world. The actual
entrance to different pavilions 'is the seed
crystal in the process of expanding into a
milieu', and the scenes themselves accumulate
into a larger crystal. Each film itself
shows this accumulation all formation.
In Fellini, it is the present not the past
that offers some compelling proportion, and
the virtual past offers an escape—childhood
memories, for example. Deleuze insists
that Fellini does this 'to create a dimension
of coexisting pasts' (130). So the
compulsive present and the conserving past
interfere with each other.
- The crystal in
dissolution in Visconti. Here we see the
self-enclosed aristocratic domains, which
include offering life or spectacle, dances,
the family dinner and theatricals and
ceremonies. The musical score emphasizes
the 'ceremonial nature of this rarefied world'
(131). However there is a process of
decomposition that undermines them, decline
and decadence indicated by events outside,
such as wars. There are suggestions that
these worlds might be reconnected to real
worlds, but this always happens, sometimes as
a moment of clarity, too late, and it is this
notion of too late that provides the dimension
of time. According to Deleuze, only art
can grasp this, just as in Proust.
Overall then, the sensory motor schema collapses,
at first in terms of clichés or conspiracies, and
then pure opsigns and sonsigns emerge, a first in
things like Italian neo realism. Normal
cinema tries to use flashbacks and dream sequences
as attempts to depict these signs, but only time
crystals fully illustrate the possibilities, and
only when they develop do points of
indiscernibility emerge fully, and the three
hyalosigns appear. Then various crystalline
states or crystal images also develop. The
films discussed are also conventional in some
ways, having coherent narratives, for example, but
Deleuze does not see narrative as important
compared to overall visions such as the world as
reflection, spectacle, theatrical and so on.
This is a whole way of seeing, and, for Deleuze,
it 'issues from a particular conception of time'
(133). A few directors have particularly
seen the possibilities, and depicted both
reflections and also particular ways that time
links the virtual and the actual in the
present. 'The narratives of their films
issue from this conception of time'.
Chapter five. Chronosigns: the order of
time and time as a series.
Hyalosigns show images of time, and its
differentiations into two streams. In
crystals, there are circuits of exchange between
the actual present and virtual past, rendering the
difference indiscernible. With chronosigns,
we find time images that combine 'past and
present, virtual and actual', but in order
to develop a commentary on the true and the false,
rather than on the real and imaginary. There
are two kinds, that depict the order of time and
time as a series, and in both cases the true and
the false are shown to be 'undecidable or
inextricable'(135), through showing that different
times can coexist, or showing a sense of becoming,
as a series of powers, respectively.
For Bergson, the virtual past is 'a single
dimension in which all past events coexist' (136),
and each actual present has a virtual
double. We can think of this as a cone,
remembering that 'each present moment is a
contraction of the past, the concentration of the
entire cone in the point of its apex'. We
locate ourselves in this virtual past and find
their different planes of consciousness, cross
sections of the cone or sheets of memories.
On those sheets, there are some points with
particular affective tones depicted with
particular brilliance. Deleuze refers to
sheets of the past as geological layers or strata,
each one with its '"tones,… aspects…
singularities… brilliant points ...
dominants"'(137). As a result, we find in
the virtual past notions of a non-chronological
time—the '"pre-existence of the past in general"
(the cone as a whole), "the coexistence of all the
sheets of the past" (the cross sections), and "the
existence of a most contracted degree" (the
apex)'. The virtual past therefore contains
all the aspects of time—the dilated past, the
contracted past, and the future projected past.
However, the present also has some interesting
dimensions, and apparently Deleuze refers to the
work of the phenomenologist, Groethuysen, who sees
the present as a meeting point of future actions
and past facts, 'a "dialectical nunc
[Latin for 'now]'"'. However, there is also
'an "intuitive nunc"', outside the notion
of succession, 'like a dramatic scene... an
indivisible whole'. This scene can take
place in a short period of time, as in a sudden
event, or a long one, including an entire
childhood, but it appears to us as having no
dimensions, but being a' unified lived
experience'(138). The discussion goes on to
say this is a bit like a narration when boring
bits can be skipped, an experience of time when
nothing happens. When we relive this experience
later as a personal memory, we have to disengage
from the present, or de-actualize it [in the sense
of standing back from the actuality]. This
again gives us a sense of empty or dead time when
nothing happens. Deleuze likes this idea of
deactualization, but not to describe how
consciousness works [Bogue suggests the
dialectical and intuitive nuncs can be better
understood as 'an actual present and a virtual
present', 138]. Instead, this temporary
suspension of time helps us see that the present
is a point on a timeline, integrated in a sensory
motor schema, which we become aware of when we are
acting pragmatically. We realize that we can
grasp the present from within, through an optical
vision, not in the usual horizontal or
chronological way, but rather vertically.
The event has variable dimensions, incorporating
an episode or a whole life, but it also shows
non-chronological time as well. For example,
single events in the present often allude to 'the
simultaneous coexistence of multiple presents'
(139), when we realise that past events are also
included [the example is the event of finding a
lost key, which can be considered as 'three
different present moments within the same
event… a "present of the past" (having the
key), a "present of the present" (losing the key)
and a "present of the future" (finding the lost
key)']. Each of these presents are
implicated or folded in the same event, and can be
seen as individual peaks or apexes.
However, in actuality each of them must be
compossible: in time as a whole, however, [in
fiction] there can be incompossibles, rendering
events inexplicable '(unexplainable in rational
terms)', and incapable of being unfolded.
This gives us two ways of looking at time, 'as
"the coexistence of sheets of the past," or as
"the simultaneity of peaks of the present"' (140)
This gives us two sorts of chronosigns, one
showing the aspects or layers of time, and the
second showing the accents or peaks.
Robbe-Grillet shows the accents. He produces
'generative fictions', where we see the process of
generating the story [there is a good example on Ubuweb],
variations of the same scene, or in other words so
that 'incompossibles abound' in the same
story. These are not just comments on the
fictional nature of the works for Deleuze, but
'evidence of a different conception and
presentation of time'. The various scenes
are the peaks of the present, the different sorts
of present as in the lost key example, all folded
up within the film as a whole which is 'a single
simultaneous present'.
In Last Year at Marienbad, we see these
peaks of the present, but also sheets of the past.
Robbe-Grillet himself says that the film is about
the reality which the hero himself is
constructing, and which he attempts to persuade
the lady is correct, with the different scenes
best understood as 'various story options'
(141). However, for Deleuze, the lady 'seems
to leap from peak to peak in a perpetual present,
whereas [the male] explores multiple sheets of the
past, seeking out the "brilliant points" of each
memory space', and these two conceptions have been
produced by the collaboration between
Robbe-Grillet [script] and Resnais. Robbe-Grillet
apparently agreed afterwards that Resnais imposed
more continuity, to please the audience by not
depicting abrupt shifts. Deleuze says two
conceptions of time were responsible for their
differences. We can see the differences in
the different reactions of the
male and female characters as well.
Resnais's continuities are not chronological but
depict a 'malleable, non personal virtual past'
where they interlock and overlap.
Conventionally, sheets of the past are taken to be
psychological variations of a chronological time
'(personal memories, fantasies, dreams, etc.)'
(142), and this is the basis of the conventional
reading of Welles's films. Deleuze again
sees something different. Citizen Kane
can be seen as a standard biography with
understandable variations in personal memory, but
Deleuze sees it as an 'extended search within a
transpersonal memory space for the elusive
Rosebud', which belongs to no individual, and is
revealed as a unity only by the camera shot at the
end [I think the shot imposes a meaning as well
privileging Kane's]. The stories of the past
of Mr. Arkadin can also be seen as partial
reminiscences of encounters on different sheets of
the past. The Trial could be either a
coherent narrative of a dream, but also 'a quest
within the past for the source of K's guilt, each
site a strange sheet of the past'. The deep
focus shots show characters in regions of time,
showing interaction without cuts, and forcing the
audience to interpret 'actions transpiring
simultaneously in the various planes of the image'
(143). Welles's deliberately makes
foreground middle ground and background
communicate and interpenetrate, in order,
according to Deleuze, 'to make time visible'[the
example is the suicide scene, where Kane in the
background indicates Susan's immediate past, and
the pills in the foreground Susan's future, in the
form of "an invitation to recollect"].
Deleuze sees in the deep shot Bergson's notion of
what happens when we remember: we leap from the
present into the dilated past of memory, and then
we explore specific planes on which specific
recollections are located. Welles's shows us
not memory images themselves, but the process of
summoning up memory by exploring these planes.
Welles anchors sheets of the past around a single
contracted point, but Resnais lets the present
itself floats and become uncertain and indistinct,
with no secure mooring for memory. Thus Marienbad
shows a 'memory world' for two possibly
incompatible memory spaces, while in Hiroshima,
the characters are struggling to 'construct a
hybrid… memory space'(144). [In other
examples, or group memory emerges showing
undecidaball alternatives, or the juxtaposition of
different "ages"]. Thus for Resnais, memory is not
just psychological and personal, but composed of
sheets of the past, 'a supra- personal memory cone
of past events' (145), traversed by planes of
variable integrity and flexibility.
Individual characters may have elaborate
biographies, and Resnais was in the habit of
drawing diagrams of the environs and movements
before shooting, but he was actually mapping and
combining these individual sheets, according to
Deleuze, using objects to indicate mental
relations, or rather mental worlds 'that are
apersonal' (156). This involves showing not
only multiple sheets of the past, but continuities
between them, not just parallels, but
perpendiculars and obliques. Resnais
apparently hoped that depicting the characters'
feelings and thoughts would indicate these
continuities [not just generating a
straightforward empathy from the audience].
Sometimes the music establishes a 'continuity of
mood', but also a disjunction with the visual
images [as a further distancing device?], and
there are sometimes voice overs. Resnais
apparently claimed that it was the feelings not
the characters that mattered, enabling him to
produce 'mental figures, elements available for a
thought that interconnects various sheets of the
past' (147). The technique can be seen as
'hypnotic dedramatisation', to reveal feelings and
then thoughts. The feelings map the sheets
of the past, and thought enables us to transverse
them: the feelings correspond to ages of the
world, while thoughts depict non- chronological
time, for Deleuze, a continuity across elements on
different planes [maybe]
Chronosigns blur the distinctions between the true
and the false. Conventional narratives
follow sensory motor schema and it is this that
helps them claim to be true [realistic]. If
we abandon common sense and the sensory motor
schema, however, 'time appears directly', in the
form of '" deactualized peaks of the
present… virtual sheets of the past"', and
normal conceptions of space and time are
'immediately subverted'. There has always
been a relation between [conventional
sequential] time and the notion of truth, as
where future events can come to falsify present
predictions [in philosophical hands, this shows
that 'either the impossible proceeds from the
possible (since what was possible yesterday
becomes impossible today) or the past is not
necessarily true (since yesterday the [event]
could not have taken place) [after all]'
(148). This is what leads Leibniz to develop
the idea of compossibility]. If we can
depict incompossibles in the form of coexistent
peaks of the present or sheets of the past, the
problem reappears [this time as art] , especially
in the form of '"not-necessarily true
pasts"'. In those cases, narrative can be
false [or a 'power of the false']. We can
describe the possibilities of each peak clearly,
unlike when we use hyalosigns which blur the real
and the imaginary, but 'the peaks cannot all be
true at the same time —and yet they are so
enfolded with one another that they cannot be
separated', and the same goes for interconnected
sheets of the past.
Narratives [that do not obey commonsense rules
about time] have a power of the false, and this
can appear in another kind of chronosign.
This one indicates the power of time, by
experiencing events from the inside, as
participants, where we experience the simultaneity
of past and present, for example [haven't we done
this above with the nuncs?] . In
these circumstances, the succession of moments
appear as 'a single becoming', and Deleuze says
this indicates not the sequence but a
series. In a series, the power of time flows
through empirical moments and transforms them in
turn [connects them as a series?]. This
power can appear in the chronosign that shows
becoming or series. Again, becoming can
transform events, removing their "true" identities
[from the point of view of common sense] and
showing the power of the false.
Again Welles's films show this power of the false
for Deleuze, through the construction of
'Nietzschean figures' (149)—'the man of truth, who
in the name of the ideal judges the world of
appearances guilty; the man of vengeance, who no
longer believes in the ideal but negates the world
of appearances out of self hatred; and the artist,
a joyous forger or falsifier who creates value by
affirming the becoming of the world'. For
Welles the man of truth 'is at best a naive dupe',
or 'an obsessed agent of the law'(150). The
man of vengeance has to adopt trickery and
deception and embrace 'the becoming of shifting,
metamorphic appearances', but does so negatively
out of self loathing [I didn't recognize any of
the characters in The Lady from Shanghai].
Only the artist fully embraces becoming [the
example here is a Welles film I have never heard
of F for Fake], about a real forger and
someone who faked a biography of Howard Hughes:
what these show for Deleuze is that art is not
just fraud, but rather 'the full expression of the
power of the false': while forgers are actually
limited by having to copy a particular form,
artists can depict real transformations. In
this way, 'the transforming metamorphic power of
the false produces truth'[I love it how philosophy
becomes so witty!]
Deleuze argues that
Welles's characters are not just
representations but 'forces in action, images
engaged in a process of becoming that
transforms them from mere sequences into
series' (151).
The same sort of transformation of
characters is found in the films of Rouch,
used by Deleuze to describe how the power of
the false gives us direct images of time.
Rouch's documentaries are
inseparable from his anthropology, and the
films are always produced after prolonged
ethnographic study. Rouch
knows that his presence is a disturbance, but
he also invites the people being studied to
explain what they're doing, 'as teachers
initiating the ignorant anthropologist into
the wisdom of their ways'. Apparently,
Flaherty
had shown rushes to Nanook, and Rouch did the
same [as in respondent validation], but then
went on to involve the people being filmed in
the process of filming itself. Sometimes,
people appearing in a film have proposed that
they make another film, and this is the origin
of 'the "ethnofiction" Jaguar',
depicting
the adventures of three young inhabitants of
Niger [Nigerians] as they migrate to Accra
[see a
clip
here].
The three involved play the leads but
they also helped 'plan and stage the action',
although the shooting was 'largely
improvisatory', taking advantage of chance
encounters.
Sound had to be recorded separately in
those days, so Rouch discussed the images with
the participants as a source for the
commentary.
Rouch had already done fieldwork on
Nigerien migration, and the performers enact
their own past, helping to invent 'a story
that sums up the truth of a group experience'
(152). Deleuze
discusses this as an example of 'the "function
of fabulation"'(152, quoting Cinema
2), neither fictional nor factual, but
rather a particular kind of becoming real,
which involves telling legends about one's
self and inventing one's people openly and
explicitly on camera. In Jaguar,
a fictional story combines with historical
experiences to form a 'new collectivity that
emerges through the process of making the
film'.
This
is also evident in Moi, un
Noir [clips here, with English subtitles
– Part
1, Part
2], again a suggestion from a research
assistant who had viewed Jaguar and
wanted to make a film about real migrants like
himself.
This time, the African players adopted
pseudonyms: 'Edward G. Robinson, Eddie
Constantine - Lemmy Caution, Tarzan, and
Dorothy Lamour'.
The performers watched the rushes and
developed free-form commentaries, combining
'narrative descriptions, reminiscences,
anecdotes and fictions'. Again
we have participatory ethnography,
collaborative effort, but not grounded in a
traditional past, so we can see clearly
a 'process of self - invention, melding
western cinematic personas and Nigerien roles
in a hybrid urban identity', echoed by the
soundtrack which shows the performers
constructing selves. [It is a welcome
counterpart to the view of African youth as
alien to ourselves. One thing though -- was it
really necessary for Dorothy Lamour to get her
tits out for the camera?]
For Deleuze, this is a
matter of '"becoming - other", a metamorphic
passage between identities' (153). This
is clearly depicted in Les
Maitres Fou [full film,another example,
and a short biography of Rouch here,
written English commentary here]. The
particular cult, Hauka, is based on past
rituals, but the Nigeriens who migrated to
Accra developed it. We
follow the mediums from their daily lives into
a compound of the high priest where they
become possessed. The
spirits are 'parodies of colonial authority',
and they mock the British. They
speak 'a mixture of pidgin English and broken
French'.
They end up back in Accra in their
apparently normal lives. Rouch
argues that he is not just recording or
representing activity, but provoking it,
provoking a new truth, outside of normal
reality.
'In front of the camera, people adopt
unnatural roles, become uncomfortable, lie,
and invent'.
Roche also says that he distorts time,
contracting or extending it, speeding things
up, distorting the people all the story, and
then makes the usual claim that this delivers
a deeper reality. In Maitres,
the camera provokes the becoming-other, in Jaguar
and Moi,
it encourages self invention.
Rouch admits that he also
becomes other, trying to leave behind his
western self.
He also tries to immerse himself in
shooting the film, trying to give the camera
itself some autonomy. 'In
this "cine-trance" the filmmaker is 'no longer
just himself but… a 'mechanical eye'
accompanied by an 'electronic ear'"'(154,
quoting Rouch in Principles
of Visual Anthropology, ed. Paul
Hocking, 1975.
The Hague: Mouton,
pp 83--102) [shades of Vertov discussed
earlier].
He deliberately employs native speakers
to record the sound, and together, this
produces 'a kind of machine-component of a
transcultural sight-and-sound apparatus,
immersed through a cine trance on the reality
he is provoking
and producing'.
More
blurring of the real and the fictive can be
found in improvisatory films, in Shirley
Clarke, and John Cassavetes. Clarke
combines drama, improvisation and
documentary film in The Connection,
and combines actors and real people in Portrait
of Jason [sounds a bit like Ken
Loach]. Cassavetes builds from
improvisation, or combines it with scripted
material [the examples are Shadows,
Faces and others]. Deleuze sees
this work as demonstrating another power of
the false, offering a corporeal image of
time, where the body itself forms a series
from gestures and attitudes combining before
and after an producing 'an entire "cinema of
the body"'(155), which includes work by a
number of experimental filmmakers including
French new wave and post new wave directors
[I'm afraid I have never heard of Akerman,
Eustache,Doillon or Garrel].
The body displays attitudes and gests
[Christ what an obscure discussion that is
in the original!] It is good at
depicting befores and afters, as the effects
of fatigue or anxiety, for example.
Ordinary bodies can be filmed to display
movements, and so can stylised bodies,
taking part in ceremonies, and displaying
'the gests, organising patterns, that
interconnect its various attitudes' (156).
The term gest comes from Brecht, and refers
to both gesture and gesticulations, which
convey character and sum up social relations
[the example is seeing a man chasing away a
dog as somehow conveying the idea of workers
escaping the employers' watchdogs].
Deleuze develops this to mean a tie or knot
of attitudes which are coordinated together
and show the development of attitudes
themselves, as '"a direct theatricalization
of bodies, which is often very discreet,
since it takes place independently of any
role"'(156).
Antonioni shows the ordinary body ['the
quotidian body'], usually fatigued,
disquieted or despairing. Bene [pass] shows
ceremonial bodies with parodic
movements. And it's possible to show
the transition between the two kinds, where
ordinary attitudes or postures become
gests. The example is Clarke's
depiction of the addict's body [in The
Connection], which clearly displays
past present and future behaviors and traces
of them to embody addiction, but then bodies
merge into body parts, 'the anonymous hands
of the addicts', and this develops into a
pattern or gest, to indicate 'an apersonal
junky' [a lot of fuss about the conventional
notion of symbolisation in film for my
money]. Cassavetes' films are semi
improvised into relations between the
actors, where spaces become less important:
the actors themselves generate the space
determined by their activities. Actors
construct themselves as well [I think this
is on about getting into role, and then
taking on some pedagogic function].
The interactions embody attitudes [which
just about says all you need] and also
changes in attitude and emotions. For
Bogue, the patterns that emerge become 'the
kind of "mega- gesture," or gest' (158), as
scenes become cohesive and emergent.
Godard shows the fourth power of the false,
to impose a series on any aspect of the
image, the characters, their states, their
positions, colours, categories and so
on. Godard first establishes the
categories then shows how they relate.
The categories are often based on classic
genres—war movie, B movie, musical comedy,
crime story. These genres are
sometimes subdivided or combined, and Godard
wants to draw attention to the conventions
and reflect on the genre [the example is the
strangely accidental and emergent dance in Une
Femme est une femme, which apparently
shows that dance images become a series that
point towards non dance and draw attention
to the moments before and after.
Goddard explores and reflect upon all the
categories in cinema that help us to locate
images. Sometimes the categories
appear as chapter headings, sometimes they
are implicit [Les carabiniers apparently
is about the categories of war , the ideas,
feelings and so on]. Multiple
categories might appear, and the audience is
then challenged to see what links them
together. Categories get new meaning
after insertion into series. To
reflect on images, we have to make these
categories visible or audible, and that's
what the series does, showing how
conventional depictions of fear, for example
turn into anger or excitement. The use
of colour is the same: it's not just a
symbol or theme, but we are to read them as
a series tending towards a limit.
Godard also offers a cinema of the
body, because all these categories get
grounded on the body and the way it moves in
space. Here, there is a particular
kind of gest linking categories of the body
and categories of the mind. The
example is Prenom Carmen.
Godard draws upon the original story, the
opera and the film musical to highlight
generic categories of fiction, opera and
musical and put them into a series.
Certain genres are parodied. The
notion of film itself, as a category, is
depicted by contrasting it with video, and
there are, apparently, allusions to notions
of life and death, language and
prelanguage. Yet we can also read that
film through the bodies of the characters
and how they link together and form patents,
including corporeal gests. Sounds and
music play a role here in including non
corporeal elements—we see performing
musicians where postures and movements
correspond to music but also postures and
movements of the other characters, producing
'a trans- personal corporeal - musical gest'
(162) which gets extended as additional
sounds are added, sometimes aligned with
visual images, sometimes not. The
mixture of sounds suggests a link between
the bodies and the category of music, and
encourages reflection on what music is as it
moves towards its limits of the non musical.
Overall, there are chronosigns that refer to
the order of time and those that refer to a
series, and this in turn relates to two
interpretations of time as a sheet of the
past or as simultaneous peaks of the
present. Directors vary in their
depictions, as we saw between Resnais and
Robbe-Grillet. Chronosigns invoke the
power of the false, which reveals the
potency or force of time as becoming.
Images become series, and series depict a
becoming. There are four different
kinds of manifestation of the power of the
false—characters in Welles, the process of
fabulation in Rouch, the becoming of the
body in Clarke and Cassavetes, especially
the passage from attitudes to gests, and
Godard who merges the cinema of the body
with a cinema of categories, whereby any
element can become part of a series, and
this '"introduces reflection into the image
itself"'(163, quoting Cinema 2).
This notion of reflection will lead into the
discussion of thought signs in the next
chapter, but all chronosigns are also
noosigns in that they call for thought, and
also lectosigns that require a non
commonsensical interpretation or reading.
Chapter six.
Noosigns and lectosigns: image and thoughts,
sight and sound
Chronosigns are also noosigns and lectosigns,
because the time images makes us think about
and actively read images. In this
section though, the questions are explicitly
raised about the relation between cinema and
thought, how images affect us and how our mind
affects images—and then what is thought, and
then how do we produce thinking images.
We also ask how time images should be read,
and how sight and sound relate in the cinema,
especially when their signs 'become
autonomous' [that is depart from
realism. Again I suppose all this was
really radical once, when we only had naive
realism and no-one had really criticised it,
at least on popular film courses?]
Faure had already seen that cinema can present
evolving images that head towards 'anonymous
and collective modes of production'(165-6),
because it seemed to offer a kind of
mechanical art, a nonhuman eye which went
beyond human perceptions. He [was among
many who] thought that these images would
directly affect our mind and present some
immediate union between the material and the
mental, displaying a new universe imposed on
'"our intellectual automatism"'(166, quoting a
French edition of the Faure's 1964 work) [so
Deleuze wasn't original here?]. The idea
was that generated moving images will directly
shock the mind and produce new ways of
thoughts, destroying the automatic nature of
our usual mental habits [Benjamin thought
something like this too—and Adorno was very
skeptical --see The Essential Frankfurt
Reader ]. For Deleuze, our own more
mundane automatism produces another kind—the
spiritual automaton. This is taken from
Spinoza who argued that the soul also has its
own laws of cause and effect and acts as a
kind of immaterial automaton: this is a
response to Descartes who argued that animals
are automata, mechanical bodies affected by
fixed physical laws, completely unlike human
beings. Spinoza thought that mind must
also display laws of causality equal to
physical laws. Deleuze stresses the
involuntary nature of thoughts in response to
images, as in the bit about not being able to
escape the shock that arouses thought when in
the cinema [Cinema 2] . There are
also suggestions that this thought aroused by
the image is alien, an other 'as remote from
our ordinary human world as a wandering mummy
or a robotic machine' (167) [which is
why most normal people simply reject the
encounter, as an affront to commonsense in
Bourdieu's terms, quite the opposite of being
forced to think]
We can see this effect in Eisenstein, where
montage shows collision and conflict between
and within shots, but something emerges as a
result—a concept, the organic totality.
Seeing these collisions shock us into becoming
aware of thought and also trying to think this
totality. There is also a movement from
thought to image, as in Eisenstein's pathos,
where we invest images with 'emotional and
sensual intensity', what Eisenstein calls
sensual thinking. This is some kind of
residual from myth but also an undisclosed
structure of logical thinking, 'a kind of
"inner monologue"' (167), depicted best in the
inner monologues of [Molly?] Bloom in Ulysses.
This thought has a logic of its own as it
works with the sensual images, including
'synechdochic, metonymic and metaphoric
substitutions of one image for another' (168)
[compare with Freud on the dream work?].
The sense of a whole has to emerge because it
'cannot be specified except through its
parts', although it can be felt and thought in
non-logical terms, including pathos. One
image associates with another as in the logic
specified above. In Eisenstein's Old
and New, 'an image of the gush of milk
is followed by an image of a fireworks
explosion', and the viewer is required to
experience the shock and also attempt to link
these two images, through unconscious
concepts, producing a secondary affective
shock. In this way, colliding images
'impels thought to form a concept of the
whole, some notion of the single entity of
which the individual shots are parts -- say
the concept "cosmic celebration of the workers
triumph"'(168-9—Bogue invents the quote
himself). [In practice,the culture indiustry
does these links really well and we mimic
that?] The audience has to see what
looks like arbitrary sequences as 'expressions
of some preexisting whole… as much felt
as thought, a kind of dreamlike, intuited
affective totality'(169), and this gives
pleasure to the film viewer [as we would say
these days]. So the films have a circuit that
go from sensory shock produced by images to
conscious thought, then thought that operates
through figures, which then produce an
additional emotional charge. Although
this is usually represented as a temporal
sequence, in fact the movements coexist.
Eisenstein actually wanted to create
revolutionary consciousness and for Deleuze
this arises when image and thoughts are
identical. Worker-viewers should be able
to experience some aesthetic relation between
humans and the world, and realize the
importance of their labour as part of the
natural world. In Potemkin, for
example, correspondences are established
between nature and humans, as in the shot of
the mist in Odessa Harbour which 'expresses
the collective mood of sorrow and
mourning'. Eventually, workers will see
themselves as collective subjects, and nature
'"the objective human relation"'(170, quoting
Cinema 2). Images of nature
produce notions of collective consciousness,
action in thought. The ordinary
sensori-motor schema, where individuals relate
to their environment, become elevated to 'the
utopian level of the collectivity's oneness
with nature as a whole'(170). Although
Eisenstein advocates a particular kind of
dialectical montage, these ideas can be found
in classic cinema generally, so the generation
of critical thinking is widespread: audiences
experience critical thoughts as they
experience the impact of images, and 'hypnotic
thoughts' going the other way: both merge to
produce an action thought. All this is
coexisting in the movement image [but isn't it
all acted out and thus domesticated in ASA and
SAS sequences that solve the puzzle for the
viewer by asserting that real men have to do
what they have to do? Deleuze only looks at
arthouse or radical films, of course -- the
Seventh Seal, not Bill and Ted].
When the unifying sensori-motor schema
collapses, the world becomes intolerable,
especially its '"quotidian banality"' (170,
quoting Cinema 2), that the world is
clichéd and hollow, that life is a parody [the
ennui of the philosopher between books] .
Opsigns and sonsigns appear and this represents
the unthinkable. Normally, in cinema, an
inner monologue links the images in a series of
figures [including the visual equivalents of
metaphor, metonym and synechdoche], but this
also depends on the organising power of the
sensori-motor schema. Now we become aware
of the gaps between images, where images end or
begin. The interstices are explicable by
the images in classic cinema, but not in modern
cinema.
Modern filmmakers deliberately start with an
image and then produce an interstice, not
associating but differentiating, establishing a
difference of potential in order to produce the
next one in the sequence. It is a process
of addition [the much admired 'and'
sequences]. The point is to select images
that are different then to produce a
generative gap.
Sometimes the interstice can be a black or white
screen, sometimes deliberate discontinuities
between sound and image, sometimes 'false
continuities..." Irrational cuts"'(172).
Irrational is used here in the sense that a
number can be irrational if it can cut a
rational number line in two 'without itself
being represented by a discrete point on that
line', hence Deleuze sometimes describing it
as "point-cut". Images joined by such a
cut are re-linkages 'subservient to the cut,
instead of cuts subservient to the
linkage'. Such discontinuities can exist
in classic cinema, but they are always subsumed
back into common sense coordinates. And not all
images in modern cinema are linked in this way,
as we saw with discussions of connections
establishing the various signs.
In classic cinema images are linked along a
horizontal axis, using association, resemblance,
contrast [and the general movements of classical
semiotics], separated by a rational cuts, 'a
coherent space time'. There is also a
vertical axis of integration and
differentiation, connecting parts to wholes—the
whole can unfold itself in a sequence of
different images '(differentiation)'(173), or be
expressed in those images (integration).
Here some 'unifying, internal self
consciousness' provides integration, and the
'coherent external world'provides
differentiation. We saw above that classically
[audience?] thought moves from image to concept
(critical thought) and then from concept back to
the image (hypnotic thought) ending in an
identity (action thought). In modern
cinema, images are independent, and not
expressed in a chain following a sensory motor
schema and are then linked 'according to their
differences from one another'. Normal self
consciousness cannot integrate them, and
although they conform to the differentiations of
the usual notion of the external world.
Any connection has to come 'from a pure
outside', and they 'instigate' thoughts beyond
common sense. In Deleuzian terms,
irrational cuts replace the conventional
horizontal axis, while the vertical axis now
includes an outside beyond experience, and an
inside deeper than usual thought.
The pure outside reveals itself in the
interstices between images, offering a non
commonsensical notion of 'and' or of
constitution. The interstice expresses
both horizontal and vertical axes,
therefore. The open whole that is alluded
to in classical cinema becomes powerful outside
'passing into the intgerstice'[and see two
helpful diagrams below, PP. 174, 175].
This power of the outside 'has a direct effect
on thought'. In classic cinema, the
shock of the images can force us to think of the
whole, but eventually, we can recuperate the
shock through the sensory motor schema, as in
the action thought. This is not possible
in modern cinema because logical rational
thought itself is rejected and we become aware
of a new power, one that now has to be grasped
with 'genuine thinking'(176). We have to
think of the outside as a fissure or crack
[Deleuze likes those], something distant and so
far ungraspable by normal thought—there is
'"unthought inside thought"'[silly philosophical
way of saying what we normally think of as
thought is insufficient], and we must develop 'a
"thought outside itself"'(177). As a
result, we lose the sense of ourself as a
monologic thinking self.
All this suggests some alien apersonal thought,
'the thought of a spiritual automaton'
(177). We could represent the spiritual
automaton is a robot or computer, or but Deleuze
chooses the mummy, as in films by Dreyer [Gertrud].
What counts is what the spiritual automaton
actually does, though. Apparently in Deleuze's
examples, [Dreyer, Rohmer's Perceval,
Bresson] characters can sometimes recite their
own lines of flatly, as if in the third person,
'enunciating a kind of free indirect discourse'
instead of their own particular speech.
More generally, modern cinema aims at a visual
equivalent, '"free indirect vision"'.
Normal monologue is disconnected and so is the
vision which breaks from the normal points of
view and can become 'a nonhuman seeing—a
floating eye, a prismatic eye, multiple
eyes'. Different ways of seeing are also
represented in framing or composition of
images. These are
the activities of the spiritual automaton.
The spiritual automaton is inside the
viewer, but also in the images, depicted on the
screen with these various multiple points of
view and so on. What we see depicted is
some notion of mind imainent within images, a
new 'topological space like that of a Klein
bottle… [Or]… a Moebius strip'
(178). Deleuze wants to draw on 'some
recent brain research' to suggest that neural
circuits also form a topological space,
connecting the surfaces of the brain's folds,
but it would be a mistake to see the spiritual
automaton as an individual, rather we need to
think of 'a topological brain world… A
single "noosphere"'. This is the sense in
which the brain is the screen, made 'patent' by
Deleuze's discussion of the image as '"the point
cut, the relinkage, the white or black
screen"'. The point cut is a manifestation
of the outside, appearing in the interstice, the
relinkage is the new connection, the 'and',
unpredictable, and non commonsensical.
Sequences can be seen as 'a Markov chain, a
sequence of chemical reactions in which each
reaction is a probabilistic event that affects
the next reaction without specifying which one
of a limited set of possible reactions it will
induce' (179). The black or white screen
makes the interstice visible, and it is
topological because it is a space in which the
outside and inside merge [and there are some
blather about how it merges the opposites of
conventional cinema as well, the negative and
the positive, the full and the void, the past
and the future, the inside and the outside, and
'"the brain and the cosmos"'].
When sensori-motor schemas collapse, the normal
relation between humans and the world also
collapses. In the Eisenstein action
thought, a new relation is established, but
otherwise the world seems alien,
unbelievable. The task for modern cinema
is 'to make possible a belief in the world'(179)
[that is the world as philosophers, and great
directors who are also philosophers, see
it]. This introduces a notion of beliefs
into the new kind of thought that is required,
and Deleuze goes on to discuss beliefs as a
matter of problem and choice. Thus some of
devices already examined, such as chronosigns of
sheets of the past or the powers of the false
can be seen as 'a kind of problem…
[not]… a theorem ... [which is]... a
closed set of elements capable of an axiomatic
systematization… [But]… an event
that intervenes from the outside and thereby
constitutes the terms of a subsequent analysis'
(180) [that is not a mathematical problem but an
empirical one?]. Deleuze gives as an
example explaining the passage of a plane
through a cone, which we can do so by describing
in terms of geometrical figures, although he
prefers to see it as an event, creating various
figures as it passes. This is how we get
choices—which figures should we generate to
explain this passage?
Beliefs involves choosing to choose, living as
one who can choose, and exercise freedom, and
this can be experienced as a risk. It
involves a leap of faith, but also a stoical
acceptance of the results [we choose whatever
fate provides us with, which Bogue sees as
Nietzschean] (180). Chronosigns often
depict events which appear as problems, and they
imply a choice 'and the affirmation of that
choice is an act of belief'. These events
are interventions of the outside, the irruption
of non rational thought [although obeying the
rules of deeper thought]. This is how they
establish belief in this world, although we have
to see this world in non rational terms in the
first place, as 'the free indirect vision of the
spiritual automaton'. Thus:
- Classic
cinema leads us from image to thought and
then to a concept of the unifying whole,
still seen as inner monologue or
sensori-motor schema. Modern cinema,
however proposes new relations to thought,
linking to an outside
that inserts itself between images, and
replaces interior monologue by free indirect
discourse and vision. This breaks the
normal unity between humans and the world
and must be replaced with a set of beliefs
[in the ultimate external world as really
beyond rational control, but which we can
choose to accept as a kind of stoical
freedom, so, by sleight of hand, necessity
becomes freedom].
- There
are horizontal and vertical axes that link
together images in rational sequence and
integrate them into a whole, in classical
thought. We thus have two classic
noosigns, indicating rational linkage and
rational integration and
differentiation. These are different
in modern cinema, we now have a direct a
time image showing irrational cuts between
non linked images and how they are relinked,
and on the vertical axis, or contacts
between an outside and inside which is
asymmetrical and not grasped by common
sense.
- Modern
noosigns form a single noosphere, 'a brain
world with three cerebral components: the
point cut, the relinkage, and the black or
white screen' (181). Cuts or irrational
relinkage are probabilistic, and the screen
is topological.
- Chronosigns
are also noosigns. Vertically, they
depict general problems in the form of the
time image—'the inexplicable and undecidable
problem of peaks of the present, or of
sheets of the past, or of a particular power
of the false'. Horizontally, time
relations indicate 'leaps from present to
present, or sliding from sheet to folding
sheet, or becomings within series that
combine before and after in a single event'
(182). The two axes are combined in
modern cinema in a way which represents the
inadequacies of common sense conceptions—the
power of the outside appears in the
interstice as '"the direct presentation of
time or continuity"'; and this agrees with
the irrational linkages between images which
appear as '"the continuity of simultaneous
presence, coexisting pasts, or metamorphic
becomings"'. Both together show that
we are looking from a point outside or
beyond the external world, 'a vertical
irrational point of the problem of a
particular kind of non chronological
time'. This appears in film or as
something inexplicable (Robbe-Grillet),
undecidable (Resnais), or incommensurable
(Godard) [the amusing series of objects in Six
Fois Deux indicates a {Marxist} point
of view outside the normal world?].
[So to vulgarise], the gaps between images
show the eruption of an inexplicable problem
from the outside, while the relinkages try
to explain this in terms of 'paradoxical
continuities' in order
to force us into thinking, or offer are some
theoretical take to help us break with
ideology.
All chronosigns are also lectosigns.
Deleuze here 'is somewhat elusive' (182). Lekton
in Greek apparently means something
expressible and incorporeal—expressions can be
independent of objects, images when they cease
to relate to a clear external object.
First we have to see it as an opsign,
disconnected from the sensory motor schema, but
we also have to understand the internal
relations between the elements, including sonic
and visual. These relations endow the
lectosign with power [the power to have an
effect that is]. Reading the relations
requires a pedagogy [film directors learn how to
do this? Critics do? What about viewers
though?]. There is more than just interpretation
or coding at stake: we have to grasp the
relations between the elements. There is also a
broader sense referring to relations between
sight and sound in general. So even the
classic cinema had lectosigns, even in the
silent era, where sounds were indicated through
visual signs like steam escaping from a whistle
or through intertitles. However, this
remains within a naturalistic frame of
reference, even if this is 'an implicit indirect
speech' (183), [which we reconstruct from seeing
the characters talking and interacting].
When sound arrives, speech can take on a
dimension of its own, and this denaturalizes and
can even demote vision: 'a dimension of
"sociability" and "human interaction" [becomes]
a distinctive feature of discourse, and this
dimension is what sound films articulate aurally
and render visible' (184). We can arrive
at phatic communication—'speech meant only to
confirm that speech is going on'. This
also helps discourse emerge relatively
autonomously from its contexts and situations.
The model here is the open-ended conversation,
'taking turns, initiating topics,… Ending
exchanges… Free form succession of topics,
now logically related to one another, now
without any apparent
connection'[ethnomethodology!]. These are
now directly presented, compromising the visual
images dominance, and introducing an unnatural
element, which takes on a life of its own.
The rumour is perhaps the best example, as in
the film M, where we see how rumours
develop and are taken up by different media and
different speakers. Freewheeling
conversation like this also appears in 'the
great comedies of the classic cinema…
Especially Hawks' (185). We can now also
see that the visuals of interaction can become
ambiguous, as distortions or lies, or
hints. Nonverbal expression now becomes
potentially artificial and deceptive.
Dialogue can also dominate camera angles,
montage and so on following the glances of the
partners, or extending the visual space as off
camera voice or ambient noise—clearly relating
to the notion of the out of field world.
We have narrative voices, not clearly connected
to visual images, by developing 'the voice-over
consciousness'.
Music has a particular affect because it can
express the open whole, through a sonic
continuum, which might include 'dialogue, sound
effects and music in both the relative and
absolute out - of - field' (186). Music
also appears as an autonomous element or power,
perhaps with a musical performance on screen
which continues off screen and develops into the
film score. In silent films, the score is
external and acts as 'a kind of running
programme - music commentary on the images', but
in sound films, it can be more autonomous.
It can still be connected, for example through
Eisenstein' s pervading rhythm between visual
images and music, while other directors, like
Brecht aimed at deliberate non
correspondence. Of particular importance
is the way in music can relate 'the open whole
and the individual images'(186). Music
indeed can directly present the open whole,
better than the visual image [and Deleuze is
apparently impressed by those who see the world
as embodied music]. Music as an
'"immediate image"'can then interact with visual
images, not always reinforcing them, expressing
'"the living concept which goes beyond…
The visual image, without being able to dispense
with it"' (187, quoting Cinema 2).
The last bit of this phrase shows that music is
still tied to the visual images in classic
cinema, still dominated by the sensory motor
scheme. In modern cinema, sight and sound
become fully autonomous, and thus have to be
read, and discourse can become not indirect but
'free indirect'. We have discussed some
other techniques, ritualizing conversation,
making speech distanced, or engaging in
fabulation in ethnofiction. In all these
cases, the act of speech itself gets framed,
becomes a pure act, disconnected from visual
image and standard usage. This also leaves
us with an autonomous visual image, are not
explained by speech or other linguistic
categories [and the example is the ASW, in
Bresson, the empty deserts in Antonioni and
Pasolini]. In particular, we can now get
visual images of '"the strata, those mute
powers… of the before or after of speech,
of the before or after of humans"'(188,
Cinema 2). This produces what
Deleuze calls archaeological or stratigraphic
images.
Thus we can see images that are non
commonsensical, that can even seem '"badly
joined"', like 180° cuts in Ozu or Straub [or,
irritatingly, modern coverage of sports] which
seems to turn round the image and break the
usual ways of connecting images, indicating
reverses of perception. These factors are
most apparent in Straub and Huillet—long slow
pans of exterior landscapes, often with a buried
past, attempts to show the forces at work, 'to
materialise sensation in the .landscape' (189),
which becomes 'the fundamental aesthetic of the
modern visual image'. Again this liberates
landscape from the sensory motor schema
and reveals an inner power. In his work on
Bacon, Deleuze argues that forces are similarly
visible in paintings which break the standard
visual codes [fair enough], but also engage in
'bypassing the brain and working directly on the
senses through images that define assimilation'
[highly debatable] (189). [You can break
with visual clichés but it's debatable whether
these directors 'thereby manage to materialise
sensation'.
So modern visual images archaeological,
stratified and capable of various links with
other images, each of which is ' forcing'
the viewer to read the image (190). Such
visual images interact with speech and with
other images [an example is Straub/Huillet Fortini/Cani,
where a poet reads his own work, on camera and
off, and reveals his own relative distance from
it, while 'slow pans of various countryside
landscapes intervene', including a shot of a
village identified with Nazi
brutalities—although the poem is actually about
the Six -Day War]. We have discussed
irrational cuts, and sound can also be involved,
an act of speech or a sound effect breaks of
visual continuity, or lyrical music appears
together with a shocking image. Sometimes
this is done to reinforce irrational cuts, as
when music appears between scenes.
Marguerite Duras is hailed as the best example
here [La femme du Gange], where we
have in effect two films, one of images
and one of voices, both of which are autonomous
although related. [Apparently, the film
'juxtaposes a fluid, oceanographic vision and
words of love and desire', alluding to the
eternal which is what links the strata, and
which acts as the limit or point of dissolution
of both visual and voice, as it moves towards
speech and noise]. [There are You Tube
clips of India Song here,
which gives the idea.] This tending towards a
limit is found 'always' with modern visual
images (191). In the same way, free
indirect discourse points to the limit of
conventional codes: fabulation is 'a metamorphic
movement beyond the limit, offering new
variations between 'all components of language,
phonic, syntactic, and semantic'. At least
we should read these sounds and visuals as
metamorphic.
There is also a movement towards the limit which
differs seeing and speaking, and a grasp of new
relations. In modern cinema, these limits
are what we see in the visuals. [The
actual bit of Deleuze refers to the vision of "a
blind man, of Tiresias", and the speech of"an
aphasic or amnesic"]. The visual can
indicate what is unstable, and the speech what
can only be grasped through clairvoyance—this is
the non arbitrary but also irrational link
between the two. These links emerged in
modern films because they centre on sets of
problems which call into question the
conventional links. It might be political
problems as in Fortini/Cani [the links
between an Italian communist poet supporting
Israel, while being reminded of 'buried Nazi
bloodshed' (193), where the visuals note what is
unspoken in the poetry and vice versa [there is
another example 193, where we see current images
of festivity, while voices tell of past
festivities and future abandonment]. The
examples of strangeness or inarticulateness of
speech show a relation between voice and
music. Godard draws from sonic material in
general (Prenom Carmen). In fact
most modern cinema separates speech and visual
image, and also includes non linguistic sounds,
and thus faces the challenge of re-chaining in a
non arbitrary way [always a terrible problem,
since we often get private languages, or rather
elite dialects].
Deleuze also discusses the relations between
cinema, theatre and television. Contrary
to the usual view, film is not close to the
theatre, since it can capture something emergent
in the form of '"conversation for itself"'
(194). Open-ended discourses show
rudimentary sociability. Given the greater
possibilities of depicting the visible in
cinema, this sort of conversation can become
important in structuring events. Theatres
have to work with stable spaces, with the 'no
out of field'[surely there offstage
activities?—Bogue insists that 'they never
suggest a prolongation of the stage world into a
surrounding space']. Film also 'fuses
voices music and sounds in away the theatre can
not', constructing 'the seamless sonic/visual
space [extending] from the shock to the out of
field and into the absolute out of field of
music and/or voice over commentary' (194-5).
Television has a different relation.
Deleuze thinks that modern cinema would not have
developed without television which is where we
first find separation of audio and visual
constituents. The electronic images of
television also depict time [apparently as noted
by Nam June Paik], a constant electronic
scanning as 'fundamentally a type of time image'
(195). And digitalisation introduced much
more mutability. Electronic images can be
seen as 'transformable emissions of "immedia",
without clear origin or final destination'(195,
not quoting Deleuze this time, obviously, but a
certain Edmund Couchot]. This changes the
notion of out of field, and replaces it with '"a
perpetual reorganisation, whereby a new image
may arise from any point whatever of the
preceding image"'(195, this time quoting Cinema
2). So digital television anticipates
cinematic reversals of perception
andrelinking. [And then the usual
excess—'the video screen is the brain screen,
and in this sense a version of the modern
cinema's noosphere', or in Deleuze's terms, 'the
video screen becomes "a table of information, an
opaque surface on which <data> are
inscribed, information replacing Nature, and the
city - brain, the third eye, replacing the eyes
of Nature"'].
However, cinematic innovation has not just been
caused by television, since an additional
'"powerful will to art"'is also required to use
technological innovation (196). Thus
information technology generally only provide a
possibility for creativity, and cinematic
concerns are what counts, an aesthetic, an
interest in time images already—and we might
cite Duras or Resnais here as not just imitating
television. In fact, the potential of
television has not been exploited, for Deleuze,
except in the direction of social control [why
should that be,Gilles?], and cinema is actually
the more creative—and film critics have done
more to understand the nature of images,
including televisual ones.
Conclusion [actually an excellent summary]
Plato and the Greeks thought of movement as 'a
passage from one ideal pose to
another'(197). Bergson argued that in the
Renaissance, motion was seen in 'terms of
a uniform space and a metrical time in
which no moment is privileged over another', yet
this still did not grasp motion
adequately. For Bergson, 'movement must be
grasped as the transformation of a whole, in
which any given moving entity, its motion and
all surrounding entities form an open,
constantly changing totality'. Bergson
went on to suggest this could be grasped as a
universe of images, flows of matter-movement,
interrupted by specialist living images.
This provides Deleuze with the terms that can be
used to analyze movement image. In classic
cinema, there is a vertical axis of
differentiation, where the frame, shots and
montage indicate elements of the open whole
through individual images. On the
horizontal axis of specification, there are
various kinds of movement images, starting with
the Bergsonian trio of perception-, action- and
affection-image, then weaving in bits of Peirce
to get at the relation image, the impulse image
and the reflection image. Each of these
has two signs of composition and one genetic
sign. In classic cinema, these signs are
displayed and regulated by the sensory motor
schema.
When we analyze the perception image we start to
see how perception works, and we find it
grounded either in a fixed perspective or a
floating liquid one, or even a gaseous
one. Affection images appear in the form
of facial signs, where the face reflects
qualities and registers the passage of these
qualities. [Somehow that leads to] the
ASW. Impulse images point to an originary
world of drives, and its signs are symptoms or
fetishes. Action images can be large or
small forms, appearing in sequences like SAS or
ASA. Reflection images turn these two
forms into one another, appearing in the signs
of various figures, including metaphors,
inversion and figures of discourse. These
can be marks of natural relations, or demarks of
disrupted natural relations or symbols of
conventional relations 'formed by law or habit'
(199). Although this is a better model of
movement and time, movement still
dominates.
In modern cinema, movements appear that are no
longer linked within a unified time - space, but
are aberrant or uncentred. We see these
developments in the form of opsigns and sonsigns
not regulated by a sensory motor scheme: these
can appear first in the form of flashbacks or
dream worlds. Finally, hyalosigns depict
time in its own right, in the form of time
crystals, where time is split 'into an actual
present and coexisting virtual past' (199), and
we see fragments reassembled in new circuits of
images. Chronosigns depict time as sheets
or peaks. The powers of the false develop
to produce linkages beyond common sense,
including 'incompossible combinations of
coexisting past times' (200), or coexisting
presents. Paradoxical forms mean that the
division between true and false can no longer
remain. In Welles's cinema, the powers of
the false are personalized as characters like
truth seekers or betrayers, while in Rouch it is
a matter of deliberate fabulation [then a bit on
Clarke and Cassavetes], and in Godard,
classifications are metamorphosed and series are
created from 'incommensurable yet interrelated
categories'.
The sensori-motor schema collapses, and time is
prioritised over movement. Relations of
image to sound change, and conventional thought
is forced to change too. Classic cinema
offers image shock leading to a concept of the
whole, which then explains the inner monologue
as the characters organise their thoughts
through the sensori-motor schema. In
modern cinema the images shock us into grasping
a new thought of the outside, and inner
monologue gives way to free indirect
discourse. [Bogue argues even more clearly
here that the Deleuzian notion of encouraging
belief in the world is not to be read in terms
of some Baudrillardian anxiety about reality
leaching away, as I had read it, but more in
terms of making believable the philosophical
picture of the world depicted in modern cinema.
This is the challenge, of course -- to disrupt
commonsense but not to let people see the result
as just incomprehensible]. The normal
vertical and horizontal dimensions above are
replaced by a notion of the outside appearing in
interstices, and deliberate disjunctive
differences on the horizontal axis [as in the
diagrams]. The interstices becomes
important in modern thought, as do the splits in
the modern lectosign. Visual and sonic
images become autonomous and indicate their
limits, and we are required to read them as they
are linked together in unconventional ways.
The distinction between movement image and time
image can be blurred in practice, since all
cinema tries to indicate movements and processes
of thought, forming them from a plastic mass
[signaletic matter]. The possibilities
have always been indicated even in classic
cinema, especially the images depicting the
impact of time. Now these images have been
particularly foregrounded, in the 'brain world
of the spiritual automaton' (201-2). This
automaton appearing in the cinema requires
viewers to develop new modes of reading and
thinking, but in the form of actualization, by
filmmakers.
Deleuze insists that he is not imposing these
philosophical concepts on cinema. Standard
structuralist approaches based on Saussurian
linguistics are inadequate, so is psychoanalytic
terminology. Filmmakers working with
cinema or and its potentials become philosophers
or theorists, even when they despise philosophy
or theory [as did Hawks and Godard].
Filmmaking produces 'the concepts that belong to
film', and watching film pushes us into
philosophy as we work with those concepts [as
philosophers work with those concepts].
Philosophers might make these concepts into 'a
coherent cinematic theory' (202). Thus
Deleuze [denies authorship of his taxonomy, and
pretends to almost be compelled to adopt it]
sees his work as like a classification of living
forms, or the development of the logic of the
cinema, and sees the work as an example of a
positive relation between philosophy and non
philosophy, philosophy and the arts. This
relation becomes the identity between the
questions 'what is cinema?' And 'what is
philosophy?'
What a tour de force!
back to Deleuze page
|
|