Notes on: Kirby, V. (Ed) (2017) What
If Culture was Nature all Along?. New
materialisms. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
Dave Harris
Foreword
They have developed a critical reading group over
the years, initially criticising each other and
then reading with each other. They are focused on
biology's and naturalism, the tendency to replace
natural to cultural explanations. But there is a
[dialectic], where one is the other of the other.
What if nature itself is 'plastic, and agential
and inventive' (x)? This book has lots of
arguments to suggest that culture ['ideation,
agency, mobility'] is an inherent expression of
nature. Lots of problems remain — what if '"the
natural order" is essentially sociological,
errant, and always "out of place"'.
Evidence presented here requires some sort of
intra-disciplinary understanding. Content covers
allergic reactions, hormonal and neuronal
plasticities, climate, and the behaviour of simple
organisms [might be slime moulds. The argument is
that everything we have assumed to have been
cultural has 'always been in the nature of nature'
(xi) , even our essential humanity, with all its
dark sides. This is 'reconfigured vitalism', which
questions every truth.
There are 'muddled' 'implications of a "natural
sociology"', and the sequence of chapters an
attempt to bring coherence — beginning with
oppositional logic and its problems, three actual
large-scale issues, which also rework 'political
and ethical concerns about human exceptionalism'.
Then some chapters on the body, 'that reflexively
speaks of itself'. Descartes in particular is
'significantly displaced', especially by recent
discoveries about 'intelligent synaesthesia of
biology where, for example, the ear can see and
cognize' (xii). There are implications for
hormonal behaviours, race, and the slime mould.
Overall we want to 'revisit the complicity' that
makes it difficult to break with nature/culture
divisions without leaving nature and everything it
implies, including the feminine and the racialised
other 'a position of passivity, inherent threat,
original purity or brute animality'. The main
question here is to ask that there might be
nothing before the social, no given before
culture, and so no Fall. The very drive for change
might be itself natural.
Interesting bits:
'We were learning to read grammatologically…
Deconstruction is the methodology that eschews
methodology' (viii) and it has been seen as
reductionist or hermetic, which makes it
peripheral. Nevertheless other scholars argue that
it might have of value in debates about
post-humanism and deep ecology, and link the
humanities and the sciences. We are not applying
Derrida here, but 'many essays deploy
deconstructive strategies' (ix).
'The conventional reading of Derrida's well-known
axiom, "no outside text", is usually interpreted
to mean "no outside culture". However my own
revision of this apparent enclosure to read "no
outside nature" discovers a comprehensive
landscape when nature is literate, numerate and
social… We have not left the text ...nor
privileged nature… Because… There is no outside,
no remainder that is not already involved and
evolving as text'. Of course the idea of text
becomes questionable so matters of methodology
take centre stage. Fortunately this 'complicates
the triumphalism of negative critique and
dismissal' eg those easily attached to new
materialism as not [rigorously] epistemological.
We need to counter it with an 'ethics of
generosity'
Chapter 1 Kirby V. Matter out
of Place: 'New Materialism' in Review: 1--26
Scientific observation used to mean objectivity,
transparent perception, and mind and reason as
'incorporeal and transcendent over nature' (1),
and this is still the stereotype. However the real
issue is how symbolic systems connect to what they
supposedly represent.
This has already been understood as a problem in
science, for example a mathematician [Wigner]
asking how it was that mathematical models often
contain particular terms, such as pi,
implying that nature itself connects the
circumference of circles to other observations [a
good example is the imaginary number in the
Schrödinger wave equation]. There must be some
translative power here and also a capacity for
mathematics 'to conjure a material world' (2) [I
still think this happens because some mathematical
terms clearly do represent real objects or events,
but once we have mathematised them we can perform
much more abstract operations]. Most physicists
are quite happy with this 'riddle'.
In the humanities and social sciences it is not
just a pragmatic matter, because we already see
the world as 'inherently symbolic', but this is
still a problem. It might be that the world is
made meaningful through cross-referencing
different 'webs of significations' to 'induce a
"worlding" effect', a matter of realising the only
world we can know. This would be human
exceptionalism, and we would be the only species
that are unnatural.
The assumption is that there can be no escape from
representation, no 'extra linguistic or causal
origin' (3), and that culture produces second
nature. First nature might still exist but it can
never be perceived directly without
interpretation, it has no 'unmediated presence'
and is inaccessible and unknowable. Pragmatism in
science and maths normally stops us worrying, as
long as results can be reproduced.
But this depends on 'social rules of compliance…
normative structures of observation', and this
sits oddly with the attempt to control subjective
judgement and interpretation [not if you have this
'escalation' view that subjective judgments get
subjected to and regulated by 'objective' rules in
science -- even Foucault
sees this] . Nevertheless, constant replication of
results makes findings resemble 'the facticity of
the natural order' making the whole enterprise
self-evident.
Kirby says this is akin to the sleight of hand in
find the lady [she calls it the shell game] where
intense focus on a shell means we cannot observe
what is really happening. This technique can
produce replication even though observation is
'deceptive, subjective, and yet predictable' (4).
There is also pressure on those who would question
science rendering them as 'the know-nothing ninny
who fails to understand what seems perfectly
apparent to everyone else'.
There is clearly a theological element, and appeal
to just believe. It is like Althusser
and 'hailing', which is hard to trace because
there is no original moment for ideology, it is
'always/already' [so it was him!]. It is 'a
performative pragmatism' essential to being in the
world, and Althusser implies that constant
practice increases our belief.
So humanities and social sciences seem little
different to the sciences in that both demand a
belief in representation and reproducibility
'(often re-theorised as performativity in social
analysis)'. Yet there is incommensurability.
Scientific methodology involves a bridging
instrument to link the interpreter from the
interpreted [the real role of apparatus -- it
guarantees objectivity, almost the opposite of
Barad here]. And this renders human interference
'relatively inconsequential' (5), but for some
cultural theorists, the object is actually
produced by the representation process, and
depends on 'webs of subjective and cultural
significance'.
Butler is
exemplary [and Kirby has interviewed her]. For
her, the 'enduring truth of sex' becomes a matter
of locating it in language and discourse as the
only way to make it sensible. Thus it becomes a
specific artefact, lacking 'the thingness of an
object'. In a subsequent interview, Butler
explains that all data must be interpreted through
a cultural lens, but Kirby wants to ask where
these signs come from, and whether or not we might
find 'languages in nature', seeing life itself as
'creative encryption' as in biological codes.
Apparently bacteria can crack codes to decipher
antibiotic data, both reading [epistemology] and
re-engineering themselves [being, or ontology].
This is a 'collapse of epistemology with/in
ontology' (6). Butler's response shows the
powerful issues at stake — she worries that the
notion of biological codes simply conflates
natural and human linguistic activities, unless it
is a metaphor. The shift into biological ontology
is particularly difficult, especially if we
understand this through mechanistic models [— she
worries that something is causing language here?].
There may be a [tautology] in saying that life
defines life.
There might be politically motivated conceptions
of the difference in terms of illusion or fact or
whatever. However, we cannot defend human culture
by reducing the 'perceived insistence of the world
around us'. Some constructionism argues that
reality is experienced through the political to
produce our most intimate convictions or
compulsions or identities, and that these 'quite
specific cultural forces are intrinsic' to human
life. Even if this is an illusion, it clearly has
material effects. However, constructionists 'are
convinced that social and political forces are
comparatively mobile', precisely because they are
not natural — they can morph over time and change,
and this helps us challenge injustice. This has
been 'almost hegemonic'.
Recently, there has been a challenge, partly
driven by developments in technological and
medical research, and ecological degradation,
which themselves have become politically urgent.
Ironically, much of this depends on 'scientific
evidence for their political credibility and
gravitas' (7). Cultural constructionism has also
been accused of anthropocentrism, the domination
of the other and this 'feels increasingly bankrupt
and just plain wrong'. The general critique of
negative versions of otherness is undermining
human exceptionalism, because ecology can also be
seen as 'an intimate and involved sociology of
sorts', making the linguistic turn 'hermeticism'.
The politics and language of human beings look
like 'overreach' (8) and we should get back to
basics and new materialism.
New materialism has different strands, however.
Alaimo and Hekman criticised the linguistic turn
and its emphasis on epistemology, which has made
the real less important. They think we should add
ontology, but insist that, somehow, we should not
just see ontology as a matter of language [hence
all the stuff on feeling and affect, I imagine?].
Coole and Frost pursue this in a particular
'juggling act' suggesting that although material
lives are always culturally mediated, they are not
only cultural — the balance is restored by 'an
almost celebratory focus on science' (9) and a
demand to encounter objects, 'all things
ecological, geological, climatic' as well as
animals and plants. This is a complaint that we
have just grown tired of self absorption, and so
it is 'generous, more inclusive and outward
-looking, and certainly more self-critical about
the narcissistic self-congratulation of human
exceptionalism'.
Another contribution is from Dolphijn and van der
Tuin, a collection of commentary and interviews
with other scholars, 'a prism of diffracted
perspectives rather than a unified position'.
Commentators include DeLanda and Meillasoux, who
argue that the previous hegemonic focus looks like
solipsism, and that there is 'contingent being
independent of us'. However this still embraces
complex subjectivity for humans as exceptional,
that our ability to think and do philosophy proves
that we are independent, that 'our very biology is
in a contingent relationship to mind' -- and this
is what Descartes concluded.
Barad is even more puzzling in this collection,
because she does not offer conventional hard
science 'to clarify the ambiguity' (10), but
asserts that matter feels and desires and so on,
that it is subjective, that it can remember and
think. This 'unapologetic anthropomorphism' might
be 'a glaring mistake', endorsing the emphasis on
signification. Or it might be that 'certain affect
theory, a popular expression of new materialism'
is affirmed, 'because corporeal matter's
pre-symbolic behaviour is thoroughly and
differently agential' before it encounters our own
discursive regimes which comply with it [still a
problem that our agency is caused by matter's
agency].
Barad understands representation and language as
ontological, with human language as a particular
location of a more general ontology of the object.
This 'chiasmatic model' is not just
unidirectional, from human culture to nature, as
in simple anthropomorphism. If the object is also
'a subject '"who" interprets', this threatens
human exceptionalism and also implies that human
interpretations were already 'inherently
ontological'. There is no longer a gap in space or
time between humans and the natural world, no
mediation or (mis)representation as in Butler. Nor
is it just a matter of 'including matter and
objects into the mix' and acknowledging only
matter's 'agentic resistance and independence'.
Barad
apparently finds 'diffractive resonance' in Böhr
but also in Derrida, although the insistence
that there is nothing outside the text is bound
to be seen by new materialism as an error Kirby
just inverts it as in the Intro] As a
result, we have a 'cacophony of arguments',
confusion. Nevertheless, there has been useful
critique of conventional wisdom and a more
sympathetic approach to science.
Nevertheless problems of what language and
communication involve remain. Attempts to see
the nonhuman ecological '"socius"' as having a
'lingua franca' are just seen as too ambitious.
It would involve bringing a wide range of
materials from soil samples to climate data
'into one implicated concretion' or
condensation. Meillasoux suggests that maths
might help us bridge the gap between the realms
of subjectivity and objectivity in cultural
constructionism: he develops 'speculative
realism or object–oriented ontology' instead of
finding near correlations and reciprocal
relations [he also seems to imply that just
attaching the word 'co –' produces an illusory
philosophical principle].
Nevertheless, there is some shared understanding
that human beings are individual entities even
if among others. The reliance on maths in M runs
in the problem suggested earlier, that reality
must be itself mathematical, while some parts of
the world like subjectivity or culture seem to
be outside it [is that so though? They can also
be mathematised?]. Why should mathematics have
nothing to say about natural languages, affects,
subjectivity and cultural behaviour? Maths
itself seems to have a split between internal
objectivity and outside subjectivity. It is no
more difficult to argue that the differences
between nature and culture are [only] similar
than to argue that they are dissimilar [not just
correlated]. The problem remains of explaining
difference.
We might consider the example of machine
cryptography, say at Bletchley Park. At one
level, the Enigma Code seem to be one which only
involves 'pure reference: every sign conjures
another' and so on (13). However, in the middle
of all this sliding there is also 'at the same
time a punctum', where somehow different
languages come together. What looks originally
as a meaningless pattern, lacking coherence is
somehow also the pattern of a natural language,
even another one – German. Somehow, it still
preserves coherence, implying that an individual
language itself can 'have myriad manifestations
or translations within it'.. This looks like an
argument for mathematics as a universal cipher,
but the problem is only transferred — how can
mathematics be ubiquitous and so diverse that it
can include everything, even that which it is
not?
We might find Derrida on the 'general text'
helpful: 'it evokes a sort of dynamic tower of
Babel whose cross reference animates each and
every language' [something transcendental?]. We
see this with algebra which originally meant
'"the reunion of broken parts"'. It has no
foundation as referent. Derrida sees it
consisting of ideal objects produced by human
beings, a tool of access authored by a subject,
and not the mirror of an algebraic world. But
this implies a displaced humanist subject,
dispersed and fractured [across cultures and
history?]. This is a deconstructive reading
which breaks out of culture as much as does M,
but without some of the implications of a split
between culture and nature [I am not at all sure
why].
Certainly, it is no longer just maths that has
no foundational referent or centre. This is
important if we want to see new materialism as
progressive, moving away from earlier errors
without devaluing what went before [this seems
important, and it is possible, apparently,
because we have no longer a need to
'narrativise' that way — but doesn't the notion
of being progressive imply such a
narrative?] New materialism can feel
liberating by claiming to be given access at
last to material reality and all those things
that were once banned, from biology through
animals and plants. At the moment the respective
identities of these objects still remain
'intact' (14) [although they must surely have
some common ontological origin for
materialists?]. What if we could contest the
identity of terms and contents?
At this point we can turn to Mary Douglas and
her point about human societies and dirt: the
need to remove it seems common despite the
specifics. What underpins all the diversity is
'the need for clear structures and legible
borders' [sociological determinism or
transcendentalism — functional prerequisites?],
which persist even when they are transgressed.
This underpins conformity as 'the stuff of the
political', since a breach threatens collective
identity. [Weird this -- seems to be used only
to flesh out --sic -- Wilson below]
Apparently, we can learn from this and apply it
to the 'turf wars' between different
materialisms, linguistic turns, and so on. If
we 'identify materiality oppositionally',
that leads to all sorts of wrangles about what
are right and wrong adjudications, in
particular, we can get 'forms of critique [that]
can be more intent on managing a threat than
exploring a question' (15). It is better instead
to focus on confusions and paradoxes.
'My assumption is that matter and its cognates
are morphologically plastic and that these
transubstantiations are myriad, appearing as
words, as plants and objects, as blood and
belief' [badly needs the virtual unless it is
transcendental?]. To introduce divisions is to
misshape and make monstrous material. This
should not be seen as reductionism privileging
the cultural, because matter is also seen as
imbued with 'forces and capacities'. Braidotti
explicitly refers to the univocity of Being and
a notion of becoming that ensues [which is
explicitly deleuzian?]. Universal
differentiation can still produce apparent
oppositions, between physics and literature, the
biological and the social, however.
If the order of things is modelled, and things
are inseparable, we have to think again what we
mean by 'mediation and identity' (16). For Barad
it is '"intra-action"' to replace pre-existing
relations and mediations. This means that there
can be 'no "things" or givens' [but why do we
get apparent oppositions?]. This also implies
that we can have conjunction or aggregation
without posing inseparability. This is an
'apparent contradiction' and has led to much
misunderstanding of Barad even by her fans. The
problem is that any way forward will be
'counterintuitive and mindbendingly strange'.
Somebody called Jagger has misunderstood Barad
[praised her against Kirby, and Grosz], and not
understood the central point which is that
'matter is always "out of place" and its
agentive capacity ubiquitous' [this is not wrong
but merely 'unfortunate']. It preserves the
difference between culture and nature and reads
Barad's responsibility and accountability as
humanism [me too]. Jagger sees aggregate
identity but not 'the enigma of univocity',
where the discursive is the material, and there
is no outside nature.
Barad 'offers us a provocative invitation' in
her 2007
book — agential realism which denies all
mediation between culture and the real world.
This is echoed by Derrida. Neither sees
entanglement or différance as just active
participation by both sides [apparently like
Jagger does]. The unpublished seminar by Derrida
thinks about information transfer and the
language of genetics, and compares them with
human 'pedagogical instructions and rules' (17).
He asks if there is any discernible difference
and this leads to questions of segregating
nature from culture and human exceptionalism. It
will not do to argue that a model is not the
reality, recalling Butler on biological
cryptography. Derrida and Barad question the
whole notion of an in-between, a mediating third
term between subject and object — the text is a
complex product of life, and the result is not
exterior to the subject or the object, not a
third term but '"the very structure of the
living as shared structure of the biologist — as
living — of science as a production of life, and
the living itself"' [ludicrous mysticism really,
unless he's just repeating the old argument that
once you've written the text it takes on a life
of its own, and applying that to genetic code?].
Engaging this confusion helps us also understand
'the perverse agility of the political', of
differentiation. We will still find prohibitions
and censoring limits, but they will also appear
to be brittle and vulnerable [because
philosophers have questioned them!] There is no
universal answer in Barad or Derrida, because
their understandings themselves result from 'a
diffracted, nonlocal manifestation of the
world's Being' [relativism beckons again,
surely? --fascism is also a local manifestation
of the univocity of Being] [and how does
lead to political activism for both of them?]. This provides the uniqueness
of individuation [close to Deleuze again, on the
haecceity].
One implication is that we can learn lessons
from social enquiry, even for the realm of
objects. Social enquiry can also be regarded as
'intrinsically scientific and technologically
transformative'(18) although we would have to
alter these terms, just as we have revised the
subject. We will come across 'hidden
onto–epistemological transitivities' to 'pervert
and entangle' old divisions between thinkers and
other thinkers objects and other objects as well
as thinkers and objects. There will therefore be
a ' critique of critique', a new form of the
corrective will, moving away from error. Derrida
himself explains that authors of readings and
any reading or writing 'is life itself' [which
implies relativism in those readings], but
different perceptions of the world is not
forbidden. There is however 'life's seemingly
superior and transcendent overview' [so it all
turns out to be elan vital after all. The appeal
to life is itself a product of social and
political contexts]. This can also explain why
there appears to be different entities in the
world — it is 'a chiasmatic mangle of the
world's own individual perceptions of itself'
[so we should not worry about chiasm and
contradiction in our writings] . Human becoming
can be seen as 'processual
enquiring/perceiving', with 'life's self
reflexivity [as] a working science, a
dispositif' with a myriad of methodologies and
perceptions, which still place subjects within
objects, even in their will to 'be/other'.
How can we write from this position if we are
immersed? [what makes our writing so
wonderful?] There are suggestions. Wilson,
for example, refers in Gut Feminism, to
the complexity of the body, while retaining
something 'elusive, experimental and even
maddening' [so now mystical complexity is a sign
that we are on the right tracks?]. The problem
is to talk about the body's interior while we
are ourselves body, and must reject the
Cartesian division with its conservative
implications. We should not see biology as an
embarrassment to be removed from the political.
Wilson proceeds by 'getting down and dirty'
looking at the enteric system and how it has
been connected with 'words and images,
psychological states, glances and memories'.
This is to some extent a reworking of Freud on
conversion hysteria 'where cultural significance
is said to be somatised', and there is now
a new way 'to find value in "dirt"'.
Wilson is really asking what biology actually
involves, and this produces a 'frustratingly
banal and inescapable' riddle. How to understand
corporeal interiority just under the skin. How
to grasp the fragility of identity if a body
blow can damage it? This clearly opposes the
all-powerful humanist subject as a pilot. The
broader question is whether this 'discursive
analysis of the body is authored by that same
goop and spill' that seem to contradict most
notions of personhood. [Biological determinism
then]. These issues show how biology is
thoroughly political, and how it questions our
very identities. Wilson's conclusions are based
on scientific evidence [gosh] , but they are
baffling — for example how placebos work,
whether it is worth asking if some organs can be
'transferentially "alive" to each other's moods
and reasonings [sic]', whether the gut is itself
psychological and cognitive.
How can we make physics political if it is
always provisional, except by risking the idea
that 'nature, in essence, is "under
construction"'.
[Note 9 (22) is interesting in referring to a
big dispute in feminism turning on Ahmed's
criticism of the new materialism — Ahmed sees it
is misguided, rhetorical to prevent biophobia of
earlier feminisms. Kirby's response is that A
has homogenised different approaches into a
common set of commitments and decontextualised
citations. It is 'extremely difficult to find
common ground', and new materialists would agree
with some reservations. The common ground seems
to me here to argue that biology can appear both
as Cartesian separations, and different accounts
about itself, explaining the split between Ahmed
and Barad. This means we are all involved in
'materiality schizoid methodologies of self
enquiry, which includes disavowal, repression
and denial' so difference appears within
univocity. So we should not write 'corrective'
texts!]
Chapter 2 Barnwell, A. Method Matters: The
Ethics of Exclusion: 26 – 48
[A long overdue corrective]
There is often a 'generational rebellion' in
the growth of new intellectual movements,
indicated by terms like 'post' or the softer
'neo-'. However, it is hard to shake off the
commitments of the old schools of thought — for
example post-colonialism tries to understand the
effects of colonialism but is never entirely
'free of its legacy' (26). History is vital to
understanding new movements, producing a
particular 'agonism' when dealing with past
errors. There is a 'necessary contradiction'
involving exclusion of those practices that are
themselves accused of exclusion. This exclusion
is often ignored, and the issues covered by
referring to older traditions 'as stale and
static' (27) ignoring all the 'lively and
enduring complications'. In fact those
provocations and unresolved queries often inform
the present understanding, in an agonistic
'living dialectic'.
It may be that we can never dissociate ourselves
from past methods and ideologies, and indeed, it
might be necessary to pursue 'a troubled
identification with a previous "other"'.
Questions of reflexivity and method are implied.
It might be impossible to fully acknowledge an
error from our own past, or to account for our
own new exclusions [especially if we want to
claim a new and complete break — familiarity
often intrudes].
In the turn from humanism to post-humanism we
see all these features. The claim is to 'move
away from human centred to ecological models of
agency', and there is a claimed radical
inclusion of all forms of life as agents. But
what exactly is the relationship with humanism?
In particular, despite the claimed shift towards
ontology away from epistemology, questions about
the ethics of methodology persist. Why are the
new interventions somehow superior, unless we
are claiming some form of 'assumed progress' (27
– 8). By exploring new agency, there is also a
claim that existing ideologies have structured
the earlier terms [very marked in qualitative
inquiry with its ambivalence towards hegemonic
media] — so it might be possible to extend
rather than replace 'traditional sociological
questions' [we can certainly do a sociology of
knowledge of the new post-humanist approaches].
We can examining methodological claims of
several variants, especially Bennett's Vibrant
Matter… and Massumi's staff on affect.
Both are influential and both explicitly grapple
with the relation of their views to past
intellectual trends, so we can see how exclusion
is managed and leverage derived. There is of
course theoretical heterogeneity in
post-humanism and it is a 'dissonant' field [the
example given is that some insist on the
'sentience of matter' while affect theorists say
that 'bodily instinct is precognitive']. However
there is 'a generational or collective spirit'
especially an anxiety about human
exceptionalism. It seems more inclusive because
we recognise nonhuman animals and things as
agents. This overall reassessment affects many
different schools from ANT to eco-criticism.
What animates life? What is considered living?
We are familiar with Barad's notion of the
intra-action of life.
Yet the intellectual inheritance still has to be
excluded, especially methods and existing
concerns. After all the 'key critical movements'
(29) of the recent past were animated by studies
of 'subjectivity, language and structure.'
[Delightfully, we might include Denzin in this now
transcended tradition]. Ontology replaces
epistemology, above all 'the method of
critique', the scrutiny of ideology, how norms
are generated and get entrenched. This now seems
exclusionary, but some of these methods are
still used. The danger is that we will lose the
set of 'intellectual nuances and tensions' in
any general exclusion, especially if we move
away from 'critical modes of reading and
writing'.
The notion that critique is no longer suitable
is found across several arguments, including
Barad [citing the
2012 article], and Latour seems to have
been important. In his view, critique was once
useful in debunking prejudices, but this assumes
some true world of reality behind appearances.
He uses the idea of a hammer to break down
things, but not repair or assemble them, and
stresses composition instead. However, it's not
so easy to split creative and destructive
capacities, as in 'the demolition of the Berlin
Wall', and we can use hammers to build homes or
repair cars.
The same arguments appear in the humanities, not
just the post-human offerings [feminism is a
driver here I think], but those that claim to be
able to turn towards '"real" experience' rather
than representations. Best and Marcus argue that
symptomatic readings should be replaced by a
claim that people can now see through ideology
and develop their own hermeneutics of suspicion
now that we know about Abu Graib, Hurricane
Katrina, and the lies of current politicians
[clearly written before the populist turns in
the US and UK which had liberals crying out for
ideology critique and journos doing their own
amateur versions]. There is no need to demystify
any more, says Felski [writing in 2008], so no
need for scholars to base their expertise on
critique, no need to preserve a gap between
scholar and social reality, suspicion about the
pleasures to be gained from 'revelation'.
So critique is clearly seen as outside and above
current experience, becoming an element of
hubris [or elitism]. We need to get back to 'the
real matter of life' (32). People like
Meillassoux [and some Baradians] insist we
cannot get out of ourselves, that representation
is always biographical. There is an appeal to
realism, and 'a renewed faith in material facts'
instead [citing Latour], that human perceptions
get in the way, that studies of [the material in
particular] are 'foolish and even pompous
anthropocentric concerns of a generation past'.
There is an implicit exclusion.
Bennett suggests that we include nonhuman
participants in politics, that we assume a
vitality in nonhuman bodies. Her case studies
turn on public health and environmental issues —
one of the suggestions is that we can
profitably rethink policy if we consider
electricity as an 'actant'. The force of the
argument is that humanist politics contain
'oversights'. Bennett proposes that we turn away
from our earlier focus on humanity and
subjectivity, and consider what has been
previously excluded from anthropocentric
politics — a classic combination of exclusion
and inclusion.
The project gained strength by critiquing the
past. Different traditions are elided if they
are human centred, and can now be 'given "short
shrift"' (33). This includes previous concerns
of politics such as speech acts, or the agency
of subjects, which were themselves
'foundational' for postcolonial methods and
historical relativism. Now they are barriers
offering inadequate representation and
"'fetishisation"', and we abandon epistemology
altogether in a turn to ontology. [Barad wants
to combine epistemology and ontology of course
with hyphens, although episto really collapses
into onto].
Specifically, Bennett wants to abandon the old
agency versus structure debate, because
structures are seen as acting only negatively,
as constraints, or possibly as a context. No
dynamism is discussed. Structures are not always
constraining but can be 'malleable and
responsive' and thus be seen as actant's
themselves 'in the ecology of political life'
[no examples are given here, but it might turn
on the notion of global agents as actants in the
work of Urry or Law?].
Bennett still seems a role for demystification
if used with caution, and if we can somehow
abandon its residual and implicit human agency
[but how can we do that?]. She seems to accept
different sorts of limitations that limit her
own radical inclusion, especially ignoring
'structural and ideological realities' (34) even
those which had a role in anthropocentric
political discourse. She pursues revelation
using critique. She has [rhetorically] seen
previous approaches as 'essentially un-dynamic
and thus inessential to an inclusive ecology'.
This is based on 'a certain faith' that if we
remove human constraints we will come to some
'natural, "freethinking" liberty or agency… as
it truly is' [definitely present in Barad too].
It gets more complex if we have to decide which
agencies are productive, and which methods and
questions are over constraining.
A general charge of anthropocentrism also
ignores the way in which new ecological
understandings might have evolved out of earlier
ones. Bennett seems to be suggesting that any
humanist topics will 'direct and disable the
unwitting scholar'. [Here we have
anthropocentrism as a kind of ideology, almost
an unconscious one]. Bennett proposes that we
just postpone humanist topics to avoid
anthropocentrism. This suggests a limit to human
agency, a notion of unconscious guidance,
implicit obstruction. It might be so powerful an
impulse that anthropocentrism might even be seen
as 'ecologically impelled rather than simply
erroneous' [unless we have some Hegelianism
notion of intellectual progress here]. If so, we
can't just postpone it.
We might look instead at Kirby, whose
'originality humanicity' denies these temporal
sequences and moves from seeing 'the anthro as a
modern parasite on an otherwise balanced, or
unhindered, ecos' (35) [apparently, the project
involves 'reorienting rather than ignoring the
insistence of questions about what constitutes
subjectivity'.. Apparently one implication is
that the system 'interpellates anthropocentrism'
— which is just detectable from the summary of
her chapter above].
Has critique failed to recognise the vitality of
things and their productive capacities? Not if
we consider 'language, faith, desire and
morality' themselves as things. Bennett openly
admits that she wants to change the reader's
political ideology, but this requires an
understanding of what it is that is driving 'the
ontological push and leverage' of present
systems. She wants to develop concern for all
the environment and to change human attitudes
and culture — by writing a book! By developing
'ethical and political discourses'! She has 'the
conviction that her hunch is right' which
apparently removes the need for any analysis of
assemblages or networks. Just listing the
material agents that might be involved,
apparently including the graphite in her pencil,
ignores the crucial question of what gives
particular 'interpretations, methods and values'
of events their weight [exactly-- there is no
attempt to prioritise among these different
agents or to consider human constraints that
give them priority]
If we can't see these arrangements
'omnisciently, as if outside and above them'
[the God's eye perspective] then we must see
ourselves as inherently 'involved apparatus that
cannot be pulled apart' [implying we can't
disentangle our earlier humanist concerns —
applies to Barad on the apparatuses as well: for
her, all that humans bring is cognitive
understanding, as in the brittlestar - no nasty
commercial or ideological inputs]. The
implication is indeed that human intentions
'will ultimately matter'. Bennett sees social
responsibility only for the human, specifically
the scholar — we must change and follow an
environmentalist project to see ourselves
differently. This is 'founded on a faith' (37)
[idealist politics]. So somehow humans are both
the main agents of destruction and a potential
solution — clearly 'the productive substance of
social norms and habits of thinking' will be
crucial, and we might even see them as actants.
Critique still has a major role in 'detecting
exposing and revising' those assumptions that
privileged humans as custodians of the
environment.
This turn to ontology is therefore inseparable
from 'the quixotic history and experience of
critical commentary and evaluation' turning on
'what it is to be human'. Epistemological
questions are inherent in making judgements.
Generally, values uncertainties motivations and
methodological struggles are not seen as a
material force. Ways of seeing the world are
important in some respects although they can be
simply postponed in others. Human traditions
cannot just be 'outgrown and shed like an old
skin' leaving an entirely different and innocent
perspective in its place focusing on 'a pure
dynamic manifestation of matter'. Method is not
just an external lens, but is implicated in the
whole of human life including self-importance
and hubris. We must include this intellectual
inheritance.
The material itself seems contesting [chiasmatic
for Kirby] — the same material promotes both
climate action and climate scepticism [example?
Or is this just saying that if concern for the
environment is materially produced as some
hidden voice of nature, so must be climate
scepticism?]
We might see the old traditions as 'a particular
perspective' produced by the same material
world, not just an external instrument. If this
is so, we should be far more careful in what we
choose to exclude. Why not rethink humanist
theory? Why not consider humanism 'not as an
error… But… As a provocation to trace out the
social body, in its complexity can and does
overlook, negate and misrecognise itself' (38).
[Rephrasing the next bit — how is it the
contradictory strands of materiality relate
together, sometimes conflicting]. These
questions are swept away in 'generational
progression positing liberation from the errors
of the past' [and also implies an autonomy for
the material, separate from methodology].
We have excluded 'epistemology critique and
structure', and assume that 'forces of potential
and intensity are essentially liberating'. A
certain Berlant has critiqued Sedgwick in her
proposal that we head from 'paranoid' to
'reparative' reading [apparently influential in
affect theory]. This will involve idealising the
new program, but how would we know that repair
'"is not another form of narcissism or
smothering will? Just because we sense it to be
so?"'. There is an 'unshaken faith in the acuity
of human discernment', and for Berlant [to whom
I am warming] this is an occupational hazard for
the scholar [and grounded in micropolitics, of
course] . We should be exploring different
perspectives not just excluding some.
It is exclusionary [and equally godlike] to
claim to step outside an existing realm of what
matters, a reversion of anthropocentrism.
Assumptions of relevance are clear, and
decisions are involved which may not be very
'different from the arguments of the past'(39).
We all make exclusive decisions every day. It is
not just critique that features perspectivalism,
which affects all enquiry [he prefers to see it
not as an individual matter but as 'inevitably
socially authored'].
Some philosophers have seen the exclusions of
post-humanism as far more important than their
actual contribution to knowledge, despite their
intended inclusivity. Cole, for example says
that earlier philosophical histories have been
excluded [his particular beef seems to be
mediaeval views of vitalism which fully embraced
idealism and mysticism, and this leads to a plea
to fully include existing disciplinary
traditions, and even to consider 'structural
determination of values'].
We see this with affect theory, which has also
excluded 'myriad different theories' [and not
added much of positive value, the implication
is]. For example Massumi separates affect from
emotion, and this involves dividing language
from bodily impulse, and structure from
dynamism. Emotion is constrained [and
domesticated] affect, which reduces the
dynamism. We should consider instead intensity
as an aspect of affect rather than trying to pin
down emotions [as psychologists do?]. Language
does not have affective force, but serves as a
constraint and anchor, while affects operates
outside of structure [this also implies that
structures especially linguistic ones must be
oppressive and lacking in dynamism]. In search
of liberation or 'to invent something new'
effect also renders critique obsolete because it
cannot be owned or recognised, and that we
should attend instead to practices based on
'"affective connection and abductive
participation"' (41). In other words experience
rather than judgement, which renders critique
redundant if it leads to judgement, and
abstracting the vitality of life itself.
This simply writes out of existence all those
critical concerns and methods about language and
judgement, the 'semiotic, structural and
critical capacities or workings of affective
force', and especially their effects, maybe even
their causal effects on affect. As a result, the
main point of it is to exclude in order to
arrive at 'what is deemed properly corporeal or
vital', abandoning questions of humanity or
culture or intention, which is seen as too
rigid. For critics, this theorisation actually
is active in making judgements about priorities
in intellectual questions and narratives,
despite disowning judgement. Massumi's
objections to quantitative methods might be
appropriate, but to reject all interpretation is
to suggest that only '"philosophers can
imagine"' the characteristics of affect. In
particular, Hemmings argues that we would not be
able to engage affect in existing critical
projects.
We see the results of exclusion particularly in
the claims to be interested in engagement and
openness. Is it necessary to break with the old
concerns? Might the critical questions be read
differently? In particular, the new theorists
still use critique themselves even while
eschewing it, and the same might be said about
method [except we don't know what methods are
being proposed]. Can we just ignore questions of
ideology, even when discussing post-human
ethics? How well grounded is the post-humanist
faith in human responsibility? Even Barad wants
to revise scholarly ethics and methods. It is
not enough to try to get out of the constraints
of the old approaches, without thinking about
what they should be pursuing. We should not be
excluding issues [arbitrarily] on the grounds
that they do not or should not matter [Barad, of
course has such a general and abstract
definition that she offers no advice about what
to exclude or include, explicitly anyway]. 'All
intellectual interventions will privilege and
discount particular perspectives to some extent'
(43) [but why be so generational about it?].
Post-human arguments can be traced back to
conventional sociological questions anyway, and
practices of critique.
Focusing on anthropocentrism means that
speculative realism longs to be 'a "pre-–
critical" philosophy', but this is not just a
matter of being astonished by reality. We should
retain 'critical value and professional ethics',
and continue with 'critical authorship'. There
are detectable values in both Bennett and
Massumi about 'neoliberal regimes of
environmental looting and fear mongering
morality' [but whether valuing nonhuman agencies
will correct this is uncertain]. The shift of
perspective from epistemology to ontology, for
example already assumes a methodological shift.
The challenge is often to 'the social facts,
representations and structures' that preserve
the old stances.
Post-humanist ethics are therefore 'often
expressions of, investments in, and
pronouncements upon' humanist concerns' (44).
This should be acknowledged and included as a
contradiction — 'as Bennett does when she
explains that her elision of the human is driven
by a concern for humanity'. This will prevent us
drawing any easy divisions which are implied by
using the term 'post', even at the price of
making debates 'a little more mired'.
Chapter 8 Dalziell J Microbiology as
Sociology: The Strange Sociality of Slime:
153--78
[ I really like this one, although it is a
bit convoluted. Here's my take. The issue of how
human individuals are also social is one that
Sociology has investigated {long overdue}, via
Durkheim, for example, and it is mysterious. The
sociality of slime moulds is similarly
mysterious. The underlying assumption is that
human consciousness is always superior, and so
even scientists are inhibited in describing this
puzzling slime mould behaviour using terms like
'consciousness' or 'decision-making'. They use
inverted commas, or playful anthropomorphism to
evade the issue -- Barad
does too ;[/as we know. They have
professional standards to uphold! What if we
took the experimental results seriously, at
least in thinking that slime behaviour shows the
sort of proto-consciousness that evolved into
human consciousness? Of course, I want to
question the operationalisms in the experiments
where slime moulds 'solve' puzzles too, but I
think Dalziell is right to push this as an
issue].
Consciousness is seen as the prized end of
evolution and a distinctive human achievement.
It manifests itself in cognition language and
memory. If other species are considered to have
any of these, human manifestations are superior.
Animal studies and post-humanist studies have
not so much challenged this view is added to it
through 'the logic of supplementarity'
(153), 'adding or subtracting certain
abilities'. The logic of anthropocentrism is not
contested. There is a subsequent question about
why this is so. At the moment, we have a
tautology whereby we define consciousness in
terms of human cognition and the other way
around
We can use slime moulds to get into this issue.
We will end with asking whether there is
humanity in cells or sociological consciousness,
that human self enquiry and self reflection
might have a microbiological origin. This
particular slime mould (Physarum polycephalum)
shows a diversity of various forms, including a
macroscopic one. It appears to show 'cognitive
literacy' (154), and has been 'chosen as a
working model of decentralised modes of
organisation. Its ability to consistently
calculate and take the shortest path to any
destination' has led to claims that it can
'"learn", "memorise" events and routes, "make
decisions", "form preferences"' (155) and even
perform better than human engineers and
supercomputers, for example in designing
'transport network organisations'.
A number of ingenious forms of intelligence
testing have been devised to see if the mould
possesses intelligence. It turns out that it
'measures up rather well'. There is now quite a
body of research published in prestigious
journals, and focused in particular at different
schools in Sydney, Bristol and Hokudata.
It is now thought to be a 'protist', a new
taxonomic group, with a definite indeterminacy:
'unicellular and multicellular simultaneously'.
If you cut the group into two they would display
different behaviours, but when placed back
together they exist as one creature. The
individual cells 'oscillate' in response to both
neighbouring cells and environmental cues, and
this seem to be emergent movement and actions in
the macro form. It is still unclear how it
should be classified as individuals or as a
system; each part seems to be not a component
but somehow an expression of a larger whole.
Some scientists just stop worrying about this.
There is no standard way to refer to the
organism either. It doesn't seem to be described
as 'assemblage, interaction or admixture'(156).
These questions are found in sociological
thought to, in Durkheim, for example,
interrogating agency causality and determinism.
What makes an individual unique while still
belonging to a social fabric? He defines
sociology as having a particular set of distinct
objects — social facts external to the
individual and able to coerce them, existing
prior to and outliving individual consciousness,
even if individuals enact them. We find 'the
very equivocation of individual
forward/collective agency at play' (158), and
this led Durkheim to talk about social organisms
rather than systems, causal factors with both
individual and social behaviour, but also
collective currents. A thoroughgoing holism at
one level, displaying all the ambiguities of
sociology. There are understandable questions
and contradictions, like how this externality
actually imposes itself, if individuals have to
express it, did the socius come from anything
external and is there an original source of
agency? [Leading to all sorts of ideas
subsequently as we know, American functionalism
and Parsons in one direction, and various
Marxisms in the other --nice to see them back].
Durkheim himself varied between social
determinism, and an unsolvable ambiguity. There
is even a time dimension for the development of
the social. Boundaries surrounding individuals
are also binding collectively.
We can take a post-humanist line on this and
suggests that this is a central problem relating
individuals and the socius, how wholes appear in
parts inextricably, without determinism or free
will, how agency is dispersed, never focused in
one individual, the social origins of apparently
individual behaviour. We can see these
ambiguities in human culture, appearing as
'torrents of power and agency that are neither
local nor collective and yet both at the same
time' (160'.
We find the same riddles in biology, including
the same difficulty in pinning down a distinct
disciplinary object. Maybe there are no
sustainable disciplinary boundaries? Could we
use Durkheim to understand the slime mould, or
would this be 'a mistranslation'?
If we consider Durkheim [in biology], we get 'a
much more involved and convoluted notion of
social ecology', which would challenge
anthropocentrism. There might be biological
versions of social organisms or even conscience
collectives. The social organism would no longer
be seen as only human.
Back to the slime mould and the experiments
[which are marvellous]. One tried to look for
the existence of 'comparative valuation rules,
so far found only in humans, mammals and some
insects. This is how they judge values used in
choices — comparatively not absolutely. For
example if we have a choice between two options,
we can establish an agreed rational choice, but
when another option is added, 'many people will
change their initial value judgement and [choose
it]' (161), acknowledging a whole system of
value, like 'the Saussurian sign'.
The slime mould was offered a choice between two
food sources [actually quite a complicated one,
one was more nutritious but brightly lit, and
the beast is photophobic — so what is the
rational choice here? The beast was indecisive
{I think I would be} and chose each one 'with
equal frequency']. A third option — even less
nutritious although in shadow — forced a choice,
and the new middle option chosen [medium
nutrition, in shadow]. Thus 'the presence of the
1% option made the 3% option more appealing'
[but why complicate it by introducing light
variables as well?] The researchers conclude
that the beast can make "'trade-offs between
light exposure and food quality"', and balance
the values of high nutrition against light
exposure, showing that the beast 'must "rank
each attribute"' (162). Apparently there were
'consistent, transitive decisions' in this
behaviour.
Yet the creatures lack brains! How do they make
'"the same comparative decision-making processes
as do neurologically sophisticated organisms"'?
Despite this compelling experiment, though,
human centred notions of decision-making are not
problematised, and instead the choices made by
the mould will be seen as 'more apparent than
actual'.
Another experiment involved navigating
'intricate dynamic environments'. The creature
leaves behind a mat of slime as it moves, and
the experiment was designed to show what this
might do for navigational ability. Could the
beast do a maze or escape from a trap? They
designed a Y-shaped maze with food sources at
the top of each arm. If they put slime on one
arm, the beast travelled down the other one: if
both arms were covered in slime it would still
move over them. So it likes to avoid areas
covered in slime, but 'avoiding the slime is
overridden in the absence of choice — its
avoidance is preferential' 'the researchers
argue that this behaviour "is a choice"', (163).
But they put the word in quote marks. Why
indicate this doubt?
Then they created a U-shaped trap,
'traditionally used in robotics'. The point is
to see if the slime can escape. Robots require
'symbolic maps of their surroundings in their
hard drive and an ability to discern where
they've been in the past… [A]… Memory
system'. You put the trap in a petri dish
full of agar, and make a U-shape out of plastic
which the slime mould cannot travel over. On one
side of the U [inner side?] there is
[attractive, in the sense of providing an
'attractive chemical gradient'] glucose and
water but that dispels gradually through the
agar. You can lure the beast along the gradient
until it is trapped within the U. They compare
the behaviour with plain agar and with agar
including fresh slime. Where there is no slime,
the beast 'escaped the maze'[meaning entered the
inner side of the U with the nutritious food?
But this is also rendered as being trapped? ].
In '96% of cases it used slime trails'. It
followed a path 'very close to the optimal
length'. When the slime was added, its success
rate fell to 33%, and the length of time
increased 'almost tenfold'. The researchers say
that the beast can sense slime and also use its
presence to avoid areas it has already explored.
They render this as 'an "externalised
spatial memory system' [which is a bit of a talk
up — responding to different objects in the
environment is another way to put this?]. In
this way it can 'circumvent the trap' not just
navigating by trial and error. When it
encounters slime 'it recognises that it has
previously attempted that route and tests an
alternative' (164). It is like ants putting a
trail of pheromones to guide the rest of the
colony.
This is a way 'to inform collective decisions',
or even an ability to construct 'a map of its
environment before constructing a solution'.
Being able to avoid unproductive areas clearly
increases search efficiency, and is 'one of the
hallmarks of intelligent foraging behaviour'. It
must also involve a 'memory system'. This is not
to be understood just as 'a chemical reaction to
concentration gradients, or what is termed
"reactive navigation"' [I must say I can't see
why not]. Instead the slime mould
'preferentially explores before deciding where
to go' [what observable behaviour shows this?]
and there is 'quantifiable presence of this
ability'. Thus the slime mould is 'in the same
realm as insects and mammals that can do
symbolic mapping'.
This may be a first sign of memory, if even a
brainless organism can do this, replacing the
previous view that what was required was
'"learning or otherwise sophisticated"
abilities'. We can compare its behaviour
positively to that of robots. Some external ised
memory is a '"functional precursor"' to internal
memory. These are still apologetic for Dallziel,
though, and labelling this behaviour in this way
closes down any further elaboration or
investigation — for example what might be meant
by the term 'precursor'?.
This sort of evasion is 'thematic in this
research'. Researchers prefer to use terms such
as programming or signalling, instead of
cognition and language, and terms such as simple
or lower appear frequently. Terms are placed in
quotation marks, animals are referred to as
computers or programs. Even an expert claims
that the slime mould is no more intelligent than
a stone rolling down a hill and thus 'choosing'
the shortest path.
This diminishes the actual evidence, though [she
thinks, but I am not at all sure, I think the
scientists here are right]. Why these evasions
and euphemisms? What if we removed the quotation
marks? It may be that working assumptions are
much more 'open and nuanced' than published
work, and that there are disciplinary
constraints. Scientists themselves might police
the use of certain terms, via 'strong
disciplinary dictates' (166), and provocations
have to be managed. Publication criteria also
suggest avoiding controversial issues —
'policing... this question' of potential
intelligence (166). As a result,
'anthropocentrism is not only enabled, but
required'. Standards are set through what is
deemed to be publishable. It is the scientific
culture that is anthropocentric.
A particular scientist working on slime mould
was much less certain about microbiological
intelligence when interviewed, and this
uncertainty 'was provoked by intimate, close
work' with the animal (167). The main problem
seems to be that the organism has no brain or
nervous system, and even classifying the beast
is difficult. So the 'objective truths about the
scientific object' require that its parameters
are known and stable, but in this case, they
can't even describe the borders around one
individual. The beast looks particularly like a
lump of passive matter, yet it does seem to be
able to flexibly respond to conditions. There
doesn't seem to be any particular part doing the
thinking, because each part is identical. There
is no biological core or centre of intelligence,
nothing like a mind. It looks very much like
'"thinking cytoplasm"'. There are clear
implications for notions of mind and body in
humans.
Scientists have to manage 'cognitive dissonance'
between observation and how to describe what is
observed in an acceptable way. What looks like a
technical or semantic issue is instead
'symptomatic of all the ideological,
disciplinary and emotional complexity' in the
problem of sociality. It is the slime mould that
is the provocation, but humans still seem to
want some special authority in identifying it.
Scientists appear to avoid particular questions,
perhaps realising that there is a lot at stake.
It might be possible to extend the meaning of
existing concepts such as 'program and
algorithm' (169) to acknowledge complexity,
instead of grasping them in their existing
context of computing as 'predetermined and
comparatively inflexible'. If the slime mould
actually is processing information or making
decisions, why assume that the program it uses
is 'diminished and automatic when compared
against the human'. It might be a different sort
of programme — 'one that decides, mutates,
rewrites itself, and responds with agility'. The
movement of slime mould can apparently be
predicted using algorithms, but does this mean
that it behaves like a machine?
This gets to the vexed issue of what sort of
language mathematics is. Is the slime mould
practising mathematics? Is it mathematics
itself?, Some people think it is displaying
random thinking. What if nature has a whole
range of programs and patterns, including human
intellect? Perhaps 'the stuff of human
specificity is a chemical, biological,
algorithmic expression'. Reversing the
implication, perhaps our own decisions are also
like a stone rolling down a hill? This might
offend people — but why?
Scientists are not mistaken in their
terminology, but they are evading via a double
standard, anthropocentrism, by relegating slime
mould to biological determinism. But there is
always some biological determinism in any
behaviour, and it need not be simple. The same
might go for terms like programme or
computation, which are not necessarily
Cartesian. They should not just be rejected as
an exercise of intellectual authority. The issue
is why they attract such rejection. Perhaps the
whole vocabulary needs to be rethought because
it 'cursorily adjudicates difference' (170).
What follows for distinctions between mind and
body if matter can think? Do we need a cognitive
centre for intelligent thought, responding to
enactments. The slime mould seems to offer
direct 'somatic or corporeal reaction or
enactment'. It processes information
somatically, has a corporeal intelligence, a
'fully intelligent literate and articulate'
anatomy, consciousness as the body, intelligence
is material, a biological possibility, matter is
the capacity to think.
It is not just slime moulds who solve mazes —
drops of oil do as well [pick optimal paths] .
So are they able to think?. Scientists might
refuse to use these words because they might not
seem objective, but they still use human terms,
suggesting that we should research the issues
and not censor them. If they are uncertain about
intelligence in animals, perhaps they should
extend this uncertainty to human affairs as
well, and what human claims rest on.
This is the same problem as established by
Durkheim, and by sociologists since, [in the
form of reflexivity — we are ready implicated in
the objects we study]. Sociology has also been
content with differentiating between human and
natural worlds, however, maintaining
intellectual omnipotence for humans, and
objectivity dealing with objects. What if humans
are to be seen as 'an individuation of nature's
ecological system' (172), with no divide between
the natural world and human sociality. The same
problems of reflexivity would then applied to
claims of objectivity in science.
Maintaining the split between intelligent humans
and stupid animals actually involves 'an
objective third party, an externality, to make
this judgement' and this is where God might
creep back in — 'Cartesianism "fades into
Creationism"' in DeLanda's terms, a particularly
theological version of anthropocentrism.
The point of all this is not just to rethink
what counts as intelligence, or insist that we
should accommodate even slime moulds as having
agency [a 'Latourian gesture']. Rather we should
pursue a puzzle to thoroughly investigate the
traditional notion of the material, and of the
human as 'a corporeal shell containing a
cognising agent', of human identity that relies
on a notion of consciousness. We might be left
with a broader question about whether
consciousness is located in a much more extended
and diverse corporeality — 'what if Nature
thinks' (173).
Chapter 6. Davis, N. Material Culture:
Epigenetics and the Molecularisation of the
Social: 110 –33
In recent theorising, the role of biology has
become newly important, 'what bodies can do'
rather than as a passive substrate. Apparently,
Merlau-Ponty [MP] has been important in
criticising empiricism for not being able to
represent the complexities of experience, and
incorporating traditional views about linear
time, science as progressive accumulation of
knowledge, objects of science as discrete
entities and so on. And a split between mind and
body This is reductionist and atomistic, because
knowledge depends on 'the intricate involvement
of our embodied experience' (111), relationship
between parts and whole. We can register forces,
but never totally master them. At the same time,
we cannot assume that bodies or scientists 'do
not alter the world they study'. 'Sensory life
experiences' (112) are crucial, and 'we are
immersed with/in the dynamic energies that
circulate through the world' [still MP?], So
knowledge is always relational, and truth a
matter of immanence to contingencies.
Affect theories adopt a similar approach. Latour
says we should focus on what bodies can do
rather than what a body is. There has been a
special issue of Body and Society
devoted to affect, apparently (2010), where
again bodies of processes not entities,
'"entangled processes"', capable of affecting
and being affected, vibrant, resonating with
forces that impact them.
However, feminists are still reluctant to engage
with biology, and how these affective capacities
might have been developed 'biologically,
chemically, neuronally, hormonally and
metabolically realised' (113).
This anti-biologism sees biology as determinist,
apolitical. Biologists themselves have seen that
'their research could benefit from sociological
insights and input', but only a few social
scientists want to engage. Our understandings of
ourselves will be poorer if we do not follow
'interdisciplinary entanglements', and if we
preserve two cultures. Can we develop an enquiry
into the biology of bodies without reifying
them? Will existing biological research help us
challenge 'implicit empiricist underpinnings'
(114) while engaging in empirical research?
Epigenetic research might be a way forward, —
'dynamic gene–body–environment conversations',
'how context shapes the genome, or how an
organism's phenotype is materialised'.
Environment apparently includes diet, history,
cultural practices, climate and 'even feminist
theorising'. We can queer linearity by arguing
that there is no simple aggregation here, but
rather 'the materialisation of
differentiations', clearly illustrated by
epigenetics.
Bodies and their physiology are located in a
dynamic system, so we do not have to reduce them
to fixed entities with no agency. Nor do we just
refuse to explore the biological mechanisms
'through which matter expresses itself'. We will
gain even more respect for the body's
capabilities.
Barad and Kirby talk of an entangled world where
bodies and the world are formed by 'constitutive
cuts' determining what matters (115). This
explains particular entities as
materialisations. For Kirby there can be no
outside of Nature, because everything we see
shows that nature enacts itself differently,
including those things we normally ascribe to
culture. Barad provides more detail and can be
used to explain an initial entanglement of the
biological and the social rather than starting
with 'an originary disjuncture'. The issue
becomes one of tracing practices that constitute
differences that matter, 'active practices of
materialisation' rather than independent
characteristics.
'The agent of this performative production is a
material – discursive apparatus' for Barad (115
–6), working within an indeterminate system
through intra-action, both producing and
produced by boundary making practices. That
includes apparently abstract aspects of the
world like theories or concepts that should be
seen as 'physical arrangements embodied in and
through the apparatuses that produce, frame, and
give them meaning', so even the social and
conceptual are be seen as inseparable from
matter, in a double constitution, cutting
together apart. She manages to bring in
hauntology because past and future are also
entangled, providing what Kirby calls 'a
"mysterious clairvoyance"' where encounters are
structured before they happen, and receivers
prepare themselves before the message is sent
and so on — 'haunting by future possibility'
(117). It also appears in epigenetics.
Phenotypes are materialised in ways which
include the politics of race [citing Saldanha],
but he still seems to maintain a separation
between nature and culture. He argues that race
is never 'solely social', nor just a political
category, but there are biological dimensions,
which makes race a real phenomenon not just a
mental category. Race is understood as
phenotype, with the intention to reject older
biological determinist justifications. Bodies do
not just possess 'a fixed characteristic called
race', but are produced by 'animated practices
of rationalisation', but these include material
as well as social encounters. Racism is
therefore embodied, always specific to
particular environments, so we need to look at
how distinctive characteristics emerge in
specific contexts.
We can develop 'a material account of race (or
any other bodily materialisation of social
asymmetry)' (118), although Saldanha still
eschews biological and physiological
explorations. He wants to criticise Butler, who
sees bodies as outside of discourse, 'an inert
exteriority to language and signification'.
Bodies are productive in their own right. He
cites Fanon describing how the sight of a Negro
frightened a young boy and how he responded
himself — 'Fanon's phenotype'. This involved
social and physical factors, including genetic
endowments, diet and disease. We will not find
Fanon's phenotype constructed only by the boy's
exclamation. Language can affect possibilities
and possible responses from stigmatised people,
but 'it does not alter the biological expression
of a phenotype' (119).
Puzzles remain with this approach, including
wanting to just parallel culture and biology,
and describing overall effects as 'aggregative'.
Racial phenotype is an 'assemblage of
properties' which maintains boundaries between
nature and culture. For Davies, discriminatory
remarks can actually 'affect phenotype, as
epigenetic research shows — 'biology (in this
case phenotype) is discursive' and entangled
with the social.
Epigenetics does not concern itself with things
that go on on top of genetics. Epigenetic
mechanisms are integral to development rather
than just a supplement. They 'are the mechanism
by which cell differentiation takes place'
(120), the ways in which cells differentiate
into various organisms and tissues, producing
the phenotype — '(the patterning of genetic
expression specific to this organism)'.
Biochemical and bioelectric mechanisms are
involved that affect the receptiveness of the
gene and how it binds with various proteins.
These can 'attenuate or amplify the degree of a
gene's expression', so genes in themselves do
not give organic forms according to some
pre-given code. Instead phenotypes are
materialised in context, through 'a dynamic
crosstalk' between molecules, and bodies and the
environment.
There are critical periods in development where
epigenetic factors have most effect, but
'genetic expression is always open to
environmental modification', sometimes affected
by early exposures, but never determined.
Organisms always respond to specific contexts,
and phenotypes are always open to environmental
modifications. Bodies are not inert or static,
and we see 'somatic maintenance' following
'a constant gene–environment interrogation'.
Phenotypes continually re-materialise epigenetic
patterning.
[At this stage I looked up the concept of
phenotype, and found an interesting section in Wikipedia.
The definition of the phenotype is that it is
precisely a combination of genetics and
interactions with the environment, and a
population within the same species can have
different phenotypes as in different colour
patterns in the same species of dogs —
polymorphism. The Wikipedia entry notices that
there are some problems — is everything that is
dependent on the genotype phenotype? Do we have
to just take what is visible in the appearance
of an organism, which was what was intended in
the original definition in 1911, apparently.
There may also be processes involving the
metabolites which arise from 'chemical reactions
of enzymes'. Phenotypic variation is crucial to
the notion of evolution by natural selection.
I'm not at all sure if this is precisely what
Fanon is getting at].
There may be implications for sociological
research, for example asking when environmental
factors first affect development, and whether
they might explain intergenerational
transmission [apparently epigenetic
modifications can be transmitted across
generations]. Current views suggest that 'we are
always already in conversation with the
environment and with our inheritance' (121), and
that generational transmission is never cultural
alone. Different possibilities may be realised
in individuals drawing on the 'storehouse of
environmental experience and propensities', a
'gene environment entanglement'. This fits with
Baradian terminology or Kirby's clairvoyance
about being haunted by past and future
possibilities — genetic inheritances are
prepared to influence developmental pathways
before the actual individual even exists. [But
we only mystify this by giving it verbs that
have human meanings]. Any differences which
emerge between body and environment, biology and
the social 'are relations of externality within
us' (122). This means that our identity contains
already differences that may have an effect, so
[in a typical exaggeration] 'the very status of
the entity… is an enduringly tentative one whose
apparent finitude can't even be clarified
retrospectively, by the seemingly final cut of
death'.
Let's apply this to stigmatisation. The usual
understanding involves social labelling, 'in
short, words'. These can affect experience in
the form of 'psychic pain', and this can be
'manifested in biology', even in descendants.
This will correct Saldanha.
The evidence apparently turns on the repetition
of social mortality patterns across generations,
of people born out of wedlock — grandparental
illegitimacy increase the risk of heart disease
in the next two generations [in Sweden], while
unmarried mothers apparently 'increased disease
risks in the offspring' [in Denmark]. There are
associations with poverty, nutrition, lack of
social network, social class coping strategies
and 'highly psychosocial stress' but the
researchers saw social stigma and moral
condemnation itself as contributory factors,
because 'there are differences between the
experimental and control groups that cannot be
explained by the shortage of material resources'
(123) [pathetic search for simple material
factors]. It looks like 'values, attitudes and
moral condemnation' are 'passed on physically'.
Other researchers noted that differences in
health could not be explained by 'mental health
problems or socio-economic status' either. [We
really do have argument by residue here]. Other
studies also showed that the health of people
could not be explained by simple demographic
factors or material resources 'or other concrete
indicators' so that stigma itself 'must be
factored in' [did they go on to actually do
this, try to define it and measure it?].
Further studies of family dynamics suggest that
reactivity might be the mechanism, the
development of '"minority stress"', which the
stigmatised receive on top of the everyday
stresses. Quality of family life might release
stress hormones which can produce several
effects — 'activation of inflammatory pathways,
insulin resistance and hypertension… Diabetes
and heart disease' (124), and 'increased
hypothalamic–pituitary–adrenal function', which
also heighten stress reactivity. There might be
hypervigilance to guard against ever present
possibilities of stigmatisation. Apparently
these have been 'associated with a sustained
change in the expression of genes in regions
that mediate responses to stress'.
Stress produces behavioural disturbances with
which can produce a further cycle of abuse or
neglect and entrench the stigmatised still
further. This in turn can increase stress
reactivity. It is not just a matter of attitudes
because these behaviours 'are being made
chemical, hormonal, metabolic… materialising,
molecularised'. As a result 'the individual's
very being is thus an active performativity'.
A particular epigenetic researcher even talks
about anticipatory development in a stressful
environment, 'reminding us of Barad's
hauntology'. Individuals have an 'inheritance',
'messages from their environment...
signalling... life conditions'. They are
'epigenetically prepared to respond [only
negatively?] to a high stress environment'
So we have more than a linear progression.
Epigenetic mechanisms can be seen as Baradian
apparatuses materialising indeterminate genes
into determinate individuals with particular
characteristics, boundary making practices
differentiating organisms internally and from
their environment. Cause and effect are also
materialisations, specific configurations. We
can also see entanglement, as physical and
social factors are materialised in the body,
even at the molecular or chemical level. Past
and future also entangled in combinations of
'anticipation and inheritance' which appear in
'the now of this individual'. This is cutting
together apart. There is no identifiable author.
It is all one intra active movement constituting
the phenomenon. We have no absolute separation
but rather a systematicity that differentiates
itself, in Kirby's terms. Otherness and
heterogeneity are already in the system, as is
history and memory. All parts of bodies, both
physical and mental are reconfigured as
'dynamic, discursive, performative
re-materialisations of all their constitutive
conditions'. The social is materialised in
bodies, but in molecular and hormonal history we
also find 'a biology always already social'
(126).
So biology and politics are 'corporeality
enacted'. Stigmatisation is both a discursive
experience and a 'molecular biochemical
process', so it is no surprise it produces
considerable consequences. Simple empirical
research will only reify the components. There
is no simple cause and effect, but rather an
active performance, 'an enfolding of
past–present–future in one constitutive
movement'. We should not see it as a return to
determinacy.
So political problems of intervention in social
problems face a new challenge. There are
political issues relating to particular
contexts, but we have to see that 'biology is
political and politicised and internal to our
social concerns' (127). No simple interference
in a supposed causality will be effective.
Instead 'interventions must reconfigure the
embodied future potentials that are being made
possible by the past, anticipations'.
Words and language matter. Insults cannot be
brushed aside, but can 'physically wound',
across generations. Most of the studies hitherto
fall into the problems of empiricism, including
Saldanha's on the phenotype there are constant
materialisations of both the biological and the
social. Bodies are always implicated with
'cultural and discursive performativity'.
Notes include a fascinating study of the joys of
Jamaican dance hall scenes (note 3, 128).
Apparently there might be a vibrational account
of the excitement based on sound wave dynamics,
'visceral experience of the sound'. Better
epigenetic research might suggest that sound
frequencies can have physical effects, even
affecting 'gene expression' as well as the
strange metabolic states like rapture and
energy, which may themselves be 'biological
responsiveness. Note 4 says there is still a
problem explaining how biology actually affects
the social — residual empiricism, even found in
requests for interdisciplinary engagement. Davis
thinks she has cracked it by repeating the
formula that 'the biological is already social;
that is, the social is always already 'under'
the skin and we cannot ultimately disentangle
biology from culture', solving an ontological
problem by rearranging the words. Note 6
predicts even more epigenetic mechanisms being
discovered. Note 9 says that epigenetic
processes 'are not limited to the negative and
dysfunctional' although the dysfunctional ones
are more informative (130). Note 10 says that
stress reactivity 'is neither good nor bad in
itself but must be viewed in context' [as usual]
— it may produce high achievement, but perhaps
at the expense of a later propensity to disease
and mortality. This is reworked as 'the results
are not already determined for they remain open
to other forces, which nevertheless include this
inheritance', which is a much more sensible way
of rendering all this hauntology stuff.
|
|