Notes
on: Deleuze, G. (2008) [1964] Proust
and Signs. Translated by Richard
Howard, London: Continuum
Dave Harris
[I have read the mighty Proust novel, and
summarized it here.
Since then, I have also read the early collection
Against Sainte-Beuve. However, I'm
not going to refer back to any of these in any
detail - apart from anything else, Deleuze refers
to the three volume French edition, whereas I read
the 12 volume translation. Both of Deleuze's
commentaries are included in this edition,
although they are separated by eight years].
Chapter
1 The Types of Signs
The novel is not just about recalling items and
exploring memory. The search is more of a
search for truth. Lost time refers to time
wasted, and memory is to assist in the
investigation of this lost time. The novel
does not just discuss things that happen to have
had a dramatic effect on memory such as the
madeleine or the cobblestones. Instead of
just describing involuntary memory, Proust talks
about undertaking the apprenticeship of a writer,
using the raw materials provided by the
descriptive matter. The search is not a
simple one, since the hero does not always know
things but has to learn them, and he encounters
illusion, disappointments as well as
revelations. The novel points to the future
and not the past.
Learning involves managing signs, considering
objects as if they were emitting signs, just as in
Egyptology. Professionals have to attend to
the signs emitted by the materials with which they
work. The signs teach us something.
What the novel is about is exploring different
worlds of signs that intersect. Examples are
the diplomatic code developed by Norpois, military
codes in Saint-Loup, Cottard diagnosing medical
symptoms [one example left out is Proust on the
absurd and highly allusive language spoken by
academics in the person of Professor
Brichot]. Skill in decoding one set of signs
does not guarantee wisdom in other areas.
The worlds of science are also kept separate, for
example, as are the different sorts of Parisian
salon or the different styles of speech by
characters like Swann or de Charlus. Worlds
are plural, yet they will also lead to some unity.
A welter of signs is produced first of all in the
worldly circles of Parisian life, and signs of
appropriate behaviour have to be learned in
salons. Mistaken interpretation leads to
embarrassment and exclusion. This seems to
operate without conscious thought. All the
characters are emitting deliberate signs, [posing,
presenting selves]. The point is not to
think but to act, but the whole system of signs
shows the need to learn the forms, and pleasure
awaits those who can master them. Secondly,
there is love. De C and Jupien indicate
their attraction to each other by exchanging
extraordinary signs. Individual characters
emerge from groups, like Albertine from the group
of girls, when we recognize their individual
signs, and this is what is involved in falling in
love - we see the soul expressed by the
beloved. Love is an effort to explicate the
world that remains hidden in the loved one [by
adding all sorts of other values to them: the
characters have to work hard to fall in
love!]. Women do not have to necessarily be
familiar, 'our type'. We can add values
implied by landscapes, country walks,
beaches. There is contradiction here in that
we know individuals best by linking them with
other worlds, and the loved one belongs to other
worlds all the time, inducing jealousy, for
example: this is how love and jealousy are
inextricably linked. Love looks as if it is purely
subjective at first, and already there is this
notion that the loved one is a proper subject,
with access to worlds that they do not share with
us.
This makes the signs of love different from
worldliness, in that they are deeply significant,
often deceptive, producing not only exaltation but
suffering: they are lies. In the case of
Albertine, there is the secret world of Gomorrah
[lesbianism], and this takes on the status of 'the
feminine possibility par excellence' (7), one that
clearly excludes male lovers, and that permits no
possible competition from males. This leads
to a general point that the truth of love is
homosexuality, with de C standing for male lovers
as such. Proust goes on to talk about the
hermaphrodite qualities that separate the sexes
originally, but that this separation is covered by
heterosexual love [he says some really interesting
things about homosexuals making the best husbands
except that they have to cover their homosexuality
by chasing women all the time]. The signs of
homosexuality are particularly dense and intense
[it is all a matter of glances or postures]
There are signs of impressions or qualities, and
these are particularly interesting because they
often exhibit quite different appearances which
require to be deciphered. Qualities are
partly concealed by objects, and we have to
particularly work to decipher them. This is
how the spectacular jogs to the memory like the
madeleine actually work. The first sign that
we're on to something is joy, then we need to make
an effort to recapture meaning, then the meaning
appears—the madeleine invokes Combray etc [the
example of the cobblestones quite late in the
story makes the sequence particularly
clear]. This is not just a simple
association of ideas, however, and an essence or
quality emerges. Simple associations lead to
disappointment, as does failure to grasp the
essence. The problem is that signs are not
adequate, but not empty and arbitrary
either. Nor are we driven on by
suffering. They are still material signs in
the sense that they initially make us think of
material objects like towns. It is a further
problem to ask why these particular images also
produce joy, and Proust waits until the end to
discuss the essences [I thought it was quite like Husserl or Schutz on the
through-and-through-interconnectedness of
subjective time, but not as systematic]. By
this time, Proust has realized that art is
required to decipher essences, to partially
dematerialize [an early version of
deterritorialize?] these signs. Once he
takes an artistic stance, everything makes sense,
signs are integrated, aesthetic meanings are
added, and we see that essences were implicit all
along. Overall then it is an apprenticeship
in art. Of all the types of signs discussed,
art is the key to transform them.
Chapter 2 Signs and Truth
Proust searches for truth, and realizes that it
has got something to do with time. Truth is
far more important than pleasure, except when it
accompanies the discovery of the truth.
Proust thinks that humans desire the truth and
have a will towards it, but that this develops
only in concrete situations when we 'undergo a
kind of violence that impels us to such a search'
(11). Philosophers tend to think that we
just have a natural love of truth to be found in
benevolent abstractions, fuelled by our
intelligence and logical grasp, with no
requirement to be authentic or to solve a
dispute. Philosophical truths deployed
conventional signification, but Proust rejects
this stance [particularly explicitly in the very
first sentence is in Against Sainte Beuve].
We never get to profound or authentic meanings
that way.
Instead we rely on a combination of constraint and
chance. Chance encounters force us to think
and seek the truth. The more fortuitous they
are, the greater their authenticity, like
stumbling on the cobblestones. He describes
himself as being forced to restore meaning.
However, there are different sorts of truths to be
deciphered, for example some are lost in time and
some can be regained. There is also a
passing time and wasted time. Time regained
seems to be particularly absolute and original,
something eternal expressed in art.
Different sorts of sign refer to different sorts
of time. Some indicate that time annihilates
some meaning, some show the affects of time
itself, as in the aging faces at the end of the
novel. This particularly affects worldly
signs which alter and change, and Proust gets to
see that the world is always itself a matter of
change, an effect of lost time. This notion
of time is not the same as Bergson on duration
(13) but is 'a defection, or race to the
grave'. The signs of love also anticipate
change, because love always 'acts out its
dissolution', even subsequent loves repeat to some
extent earlier ones. Dissolution appears in
jealousy, a kind of anticipated and painful end of
love. Sensuous signs can also indicate
change and disappearance, as when the madeleine
reminds us of time lost, or we get painful
memories. But sensuous signs are ambivalent
and can also produce joy. Initially joyful
recollections can also produce regret. It is
because memory itself offers a contradiction -
something survives and something has also returned
to nothingness.
Generally, all the signs so far often lead to
disappointment, because they are not profound
enough. That includes the women.
Proust and the other [men] make greater efforts to
add profundity, but this only leads to truths of
the intelligence, which are not necessary, but
remain optional, express only abstract
possibilities. We have to turn to necessity
induced by the sign itself. And limited
persons [women in the original, 15] compensated by
emitting signs, but this is never adequately
managed and can sometimes betray lies. There
is an intoxication with the proliferation of
signs, with intellectuals who can proliferate
them. These have to be dealt with in our
apprenticeship, even if it is a waste of
time. After all, 'we never know how someone
learns' (15), but it is always by pursuing signs,
even if this is a waste of time.
Unpredictable results emerge, rather than from
more systematic attempts to work through
dictionaries, say. Similarly 'we never learn
by doing like someone, but by doing with
someone, who bears no resemblance to what we are
learning'. Talent, say in actual writing is
also unpredictable, and cannot be guaranteed by
things like academic education.
However, this sort of waste of time is
insufficient. It is really a problem with
the way intelligence works, by goodwill and
application, lacking necessity. Intelligence
is useful after initial insight, and helps
writers experiment. But 'we must first
experience the violent effect of a sign, and the
mind must be "forced" to seek the sign's meaning'
(16). Then intelligence can extract truth.
Who else would bother with frivolous worldly signs
or the painful business of interpreting the signs
of the loved one. 'Who would seek the truth
if he had not first suffered the agonies inflicted
by the beloved's lies?''Pain forces the
intelligence to seek', although pleasures can also
arise to set memory in motion. We have to
grasp in particular that worldliness and love
'refer to repetitions'. Then we can
understand signs as incarnations of themes,
discover 'worldly laws'. This discovery
itself can transfer pain into joy [when the hero
knows that he will love again, OR when he
distances, comforts and reassures himself with the
Bourdieuvian high aesthetic in my reading].
The chain of love affairs produces 'joyous
spectacle of intelligence', and we get to see that
we have not just wasted time, but served some kind
of apprenticeship.
Worldly signs implied time wasted, the signs of
love a time lost. The sensuous signs help us
regain time, but only the signs of art provide a
time regained fully, something original and
absolute 'that includes all the others'(17).
These dimensions overlap because signs are mixed,
and sequences of different sorts of time can
connect, especially in art which finds the truth
implicit in all the others. The lines of
apprenticeship interfere with each other.
Truth emerges from complex combinations.
Chapter 3 Apprenticeship
The work aims at the future, not the past, at the
process of learning to gain ultimate
revelation. Many disappointments and
illusions are encountered on the way.
Progress in deciphering some signs is countered by
regression in others. Motivation is a
problem. All this only makes sense if we
grasp 'the fundamental idea that time forms
different series and contains more dimensions than
space' (18).
Understanding all this is a gift [I can imagine
Bourdieu on this!], But we have to arrange
encounters and to challenge our existing 'stock
notions'. One of these is that objects are
important not signs. To get there, we must
overcome all our normal perceptions, passions and
intelligence, Proust tells us. This is
objectivism, and it is natural or habitual.
However, the sign appears disguised in the
object. Signs designate objects but also
signify something different [they denote and
connote in other terms]. We experience
objects directly and this can give us pleasure,
but this involves a sacrifice of truth. 'We
recognize things, but we never know them'
(19). Encounters with objects or people look
simple, and we are content with recognition or the
admiration it leads to.
The hero explorers the possibilities by returning
to objects such as cups of tea or people, working
on assumed meanings, say of the Duchesse of
Guermantes before he has met her. He
initially assumes that signs are transparent, and
understood by those who emit them. He treats
his first loves as unique objects, leaving him
only with 'avowal'. Love seems to be an
objective [external] force as well. Art is a
matter of representing objects, through the
senses. Objectivism like this arises from a
'complex of tendencies' (20). It seems a
natural consequence of perception and
representation, but it is also the focus of
voluntary memory 'which recalls things and not
signs'. Intelligence also tends towards
objectivity, objective content or objective
significations. Perception naturally tends
towards apprehending the significations, supposing
reality can be seen or observed, while
'intelligence supposes that truth is to be spoken,
formulated'. The hero thinks initially the
truth needs to be spoken, contained in words, and
this leads him to initially ignore all sorts of
other signs. Intelligence also 'impels us to
conversation, in which we exchange and communicate
ideas. It incite us to friendship...
It invites us to philosophy, of voluntary and
premeditated exercise of thought' devoted to the
grasp of objective significations. Proust
sees that friends tend to develop [group
minds]. Philosophers presuppose benevolent
thought as the love of truth, and that truth is
'the explicit determination of what is naturally
worked out by thought'. [foreshadows his
later objections to conversations with other
philosophers in
Dialogues]. Instead, we need to
develop the relationship between love and art:
love is rich in signs and requires silent
interpretation, and is 'more profound' than
philosophy. Violence is more constructive
than good will and conscious work, and 'more
important than thought is "what is food for
thought"' (21). Carefully worked out
consensual intellectual truths end with banality,
as indicated in the hero's discussion of
actresses.
The hero assumes all these objectivist beliefs at
the start, and finds it hard to shrug them
off. However, he is not particularly
interested in friendship or in community [he does
like living with Saint-Loup and the other officers
for a while, though]. He finds 'superior men
teach him nothing'. Even a brief love affair
is as valuable. But in love, he finds
objectivism is stubborn, and he has to learn that
the emergence of love for Albertine is almost
accidental, and does not even really refer to her
specifically, but to 'ghosts, to Third Parties, to
Themes that are incarnated in himself'.
Objectivism is stubborn, however, and even
persists in art, which seems to be about working
with actual objects, analyzing them to get to the
truth.
However, the defects of objectivism also appear,
including in his critique of Sainte-Beuve and his
revelations developed from his causerie
[chats, almost a kind of early blog], where truth
arises from esoteric conversations with people, or
exotic truths are discovered, [it is biographical
details for authors]. This only ends with
'intelligible values, well defined significations,
major subjects'[and often reproduces stereotyped
or trivial views of other authors]. The
Verdurins offer a parody of this method, reporting
the surface of what is spoken, while missing the
less obvious - that Cottard is actually quite
stupid, or Mme Verdurin herself grotesque [I don't
know if I had picked this up - she's certainly a
laughable poser]. Proletarian art also
'takes the workers for fools'. If literature
just observes and describes the obvious, it is
disappointing, and it is no good flirting with
'pseudo - objective guarantees of evidence and
communication' (22). Hero is not entirely
sure about this, though because it might reflect
only his incapacities to observe and describe,
with disappointment produced by his own
incapacities, so he is always hoping to gain
'gifts of observation', but only as a consolation.
Disappointment is fundamental to apprenticeship,
and it is 'pluralist'. It often arises on
first encounter, even with the music of Venteuil,
nor does this disappear with repetition. The
first solution to it is when hero 'attempts to
find a subjective compensation' (23), through 'a
series of subjective associations' (24).
[Swann does this a lot trying to talk up
Odette]. Discussion of the theatre shows the
mechanism, with the performances of Berma—hero
tries really hard to find particular intonations,
for example. All this still depends on
intelligent work, however. The clue to a
deeper understanding begins with Bergotte showing
how the gestures of Berma recall Greek
statues. This swing from objectivism to
subjectivist understandings is frequent, but it is
still inadequate. The trouble is that
'everything is permitted in the exercise of
associations', so there are no higher pleasures,
say between a work of art and a madeleine.
This is the error of Swann who continually
associates paintings with real people.
Associations also remain entirely personal, stored
in 'our own private museum' (25).
Berma finally reveals the existence of something
else: the actress unites with a role, which is
neither objective or subjective, but more akin to
the occupation of 'a world, a spiritual milieu
populated by essences'. These essences lie
beyond association and are neither 'alogical or
supralogical'. Subjectivity is transcended and so
is the empirical object. The sign expresses
essences which give it its meaning. Hero
goes on to see this as a function of all art,
painting, music, and literature. The three
kinds of signs are incapable of generating this
notion of essence on their own, and only art can
reveal it. Once revealed, they help us see
that essences have been incarnated, from elements
that were already there in the earlier kinds of
signs.
Chapter 4 Essences and the Signs of Art
The signs of arts are superior, because the others
are still tied to the material, 'half sheathed in
the object bearing them' (26). Art can be
analyzed materially, as with the musical structure
of the Vinteuil phrase,, but the material keyboard
is but 'the spatial image of an entirely different
keyboard'[Proust gets quite Deleuzian here in
thinking of all the possible combinations of notes
of which the particular phrase is but one
actualization]. The same goes with Berma's
physical gestures and voice.
These material signs are also 'explicated'[the
forerunner of differenCiated?], as they are
associated with other signs and impressions: they
retain their material existence as separate,
although some are already more developed through
imagination rather than memory. Only art
'gives us the true unity: unity of an immaterial
sign and of an entirely spiritual meaning' (27),
the essence or Idea.
We are told that essence involves difference, that
it is the 'absolute and ultimate Difference'[this
is introduced simply enough by Proust when he says
that the true act of the artist is to unite things
that look as if they are completely different to
the ordinary gaze: only then can we get to see
what it is that unifies them beneath the surface
as it were]. 'Difference is what constitutes
being, what makes us conceive being', and this
search for difference is not provided by a mixed
social life or from travel, because it does not
exist empirically. Proust tells us the
essence is something found in a subject, some sort
of 'final quality at the heart of the subject', a
qualitative difference. Deleuze sees this as
'Leibnizian: the
essence is a veritable monad each defined by the
viewpoint to which it expresses the world', and
each monad clearly has a different
viewpoint. 'this is why friendship never
establishes anything but false communications,
based on misunderstandings, and frames only false
windows' (28) and it is why love must renounce
communication, accepted a spiritual level [this
apparently explains the occasional reference to
multiple selves in Proust as well. More
Leibniz? Deleuze reads it as another
argument for the fundamental importance of
difference as absolute].
So is essence always subjective [I read the last
volume as arguing that, or at least as
transcendentally subjective]. Proust also
seems to develop a platonic notion, however, with
essences as an independent reality which artists
only reveal. For Deleuze, this is to be read
in Leibniz's terms again, as indicating, the
independence of Being, only parts of which are
revealed to the subject. It is possible to
agree on some standardized limits shared by
different viewpoints, but this is only 'the
disappointing projection'[presumably also the one
studied by empirical sciences including social
sciences]. So essences are not psychological
states, and nor transcendentally subjective, but
of a different order altogether, and one that
'implicates, envelops, wraps itself up in the
subject... constitutes subjectivity...
individualises' (28-29). This independence
also explains why souls are immortal for Proust,
while in the secular world, essences imprison
themselves. This explains Proust's view that
art conveys immortality, specifically illustrated
in the regrets that the dying Bergotte expresses
when he wishes he had devoted his life to art [in
effect].
The implication is that we can move from essence
to 'the World in general' (29, the secret of
nature as a series of unstable oppositions, and
responsible for time itself. There is
ordinary empirical time, but we are interested
here in time as 'separate series in which it is
distributed according to different rhythms'.
This notion was identified as 'complication' which
precedes explication, something which 'affirms the
unity of the multiple' (30) [the view attributed
to 'certain neoplatonists', 29]. Time itself
was complicated, uniting contraries in unstable
opposition, and the universe was expressed
according to these different sorts of
complications which turned into 'an order of
descending explications'.
Thus de C is certainly complicated in the full
sense, and it is this that gives him his
'freshness' and novelty, and that requires
continuous deciphering or explication [used in a
personal sense here]. However, the best
illustration is not found in characters but in
sleep and dreaming [Proust argues that waking up
is always disappointing again]. Art can also
reveal this complication, and this is 'the true
sense of the expression "time regained"'. It
is not like recapturing associations through
memory. Art 'appeals to pure thought', not
memory. Only the signs of art point to 'a
primordial complication, a veritable eternity, an
absolute original time'.
Art communicates this essence by using
particularly 'ductile' substances (31) - colour,
sound, or words - which together 'form [or
express] a spiritualised substance' which reacts
back on those substances and arranges them.
It is not words or colours that are important, but
rather 'the unconscious themes, the involuntary
archetypes' which transmute the particular
material substances being used. 'This
treatment of substance is indissociable from
"style"'. Essence emerges when two different
objects are shown to have the same quality in the
particular medium being used, and this is what
style does [Deleuze then quotes the actual bit in
Proust about taking two different objects and
working out their relations]. This means
that 'style is essentially metaphor', but it is a
metaphor that changes objects, exchanging
qualities, sometimes even names. In
paintings by Elstir, sea becomes land, in
Vinteuil, motifs struggle against each
other. Style develops the birth of a new
essence, one which changes empirical
objects. 'Style is not the man, style is
essence itself' (32) [just in time to avoid any
lingering support for the subject].
Essence individualizes and 'determines the
substances in which it is incarnated', explaining
how the little phrase fits inside the sonata, or
how the themes come together in Wagner.
However, when essence diversifies itself, it
reveals a certain repetition [it keeps appearing
in different forms?]. Art can only be
repeated, replayed or reread 'because it is
irreplaceable and because nothing can be
substituted for it'. In this way,
'Difference and repetition are only apparently in
opposition'[there is also a hint that the same
themes appear in different specific works of art].
Indeed difference can be affirmed only through
repetition [actually 'autorepetition'] across
different media and in different objects. It
is this sort of repetition that accounts for
diversity. For that reason, 'difference and
repetition are the two inseparable and correlative
powers of essence'[definitely illustrated with
artists who repeat themes in this case, sometimes
producing 'repetitions that have become
mechanical because they are external', which can
account for the relative lack of innovation in
later works—essence tends to be reproduced 'only
on the lowest level, to the weakest degree'].
And so art is unique in that it spiritualizes or
dematerializes substances. Its signs are
fully immaterial and fully developed. They
express essences. Essence and material are
united, producing the sign as style. It
requires an apprenticeship, avoiding both
objectivist and subjectivist temptations.
'This is why art is the finality of the world'
(33). So is the value of all the other signs
just that they direct us to art, and what
implications follow for them once we have
developed art? How is essence incarnated not
just in immaterial signs but in other realms, in
ways that are more opaque and material,a 'descent
of essence into these increasingly rebellious
substances'. We need to discuss the 'laws of
the transformation of essence in relation to the
determinations of life'.
Chapter 5 The Secondary Role of Memory
The worldly signs are interpreted by intelligence,
which functions in that context.
Intelligence also deploys the resources of memory,
but in a voluntary way, and Proust shows that it
is impossible to record everything [in order to
check all of Albertine's lies]. Here, the
operation of memory 'comes too late' (34), showing
its limits. By contrast, involuntary memory
intervenes with sensuous signs that force a search
for meaning [as with the cobblestones].
However, this is still not systematic, providing
for example two types of sign in the reminiscence
and in the discovery, with an example of the
second one being the involuntary desires that
creep up on us rather by surprise if we see an
attractive woman. We are not sure if we can
trust our memories to distinguish between
imagination and reality. Sensuous signs are
particularly opaque, and often contradictory, as
with the remark about memory of a dead person
showing both survival and nothingness.
However they provide the beginning for art, more
so than the worldly signs or the signs of
love. They often not so much components for
art but 'conducting elements' (36), leading to
comprehension, working as metaphors and eventually
as 'reminiscences of art'. At least they put
us on the right lines to establish relations
between different objects, to establish a non
contingent relation, but they still tie art to
life too closely. Proper art depends on
'pure thought as a faculty of essences'.
Reminiscence appears first as a mere association
where the present and the past resemble each
other, although often there is no simple
resemblance [women resemble each other, but
madeleines do not resemble towns]. Later we
find a deeper connection, a notion of a
whole. This deeper meaning is revealed first
of all by the joy that we feel as a result of
certain reminiscences, one which is 'so powerful
that it suffices to make us indifferent to death'
(36-37). Things reappear in consciousness
with a particular 'splendour' or
truth. We still need to discover how this
actually works, however. With voluntary
memory, the present shapes the memory of the past
rather than apprehending it directly, 'it
recomposes it with different presents' (37),
proceeding by snapshots. What is lost is
'the past's being as past'[Barthes and Rancière
would want to see quite a different potential in
actual snapshots]. With involuntary memory,
we are constituting the past from the position of
the present, which implies we can only understand
the present once it is past: the proper past
coexists [there is a 'virtual coexistence'], and
it is only conscious perception and voluntary
memory that impose a succession. Proust,
like Bergson says we must place ourselves directly
in the past itself, as a coherent entity.
However, Proust wants to go further than Bergson,
to save the past [for art at least].
In involuntary memory we see identical qualities
for two sensations, one present one past, which
implies a certain 'volume of duration that
extends' (38) these qualities. However, the
relation between them is still based on
difference, which we need to grasp adequately:
ordinary perception notes the differences between
cakes and towns, but sees the relation as just
contingent. Involuntary memory 'internalizes
the context'(39) and transcends the contingent,
producing 'a more profound difference'. We
go beyond resemblance or identity to reach
'internalized difference, which becomes
immanent'. This is how resemblance offers an
'analogue of art', and involuntary memory offers
'the analogue of a metaphor'. Once
established, the past takes on a new form, and no
longer just relative to the present, something
that could not be experienced directly, but which
offers truth rather than [simple] reality.
We can therefore detect the past itself, deeper
than any empirical past. We get to the
'"Real without being present, ideal without being
abstract"'.
It is a matter of 'envelopment or involution'(40),
like art, but still not fully realized.
Artistic essences are capable of individualizing,
the 'quality of the singular viewpoint', while
involuntary memory may be localised, but it still
connects two moments. Artistic essences
focus more on the quality, and are not
'alienated'[dominated by any external purpose or
any empirical characteristics? Without
contingency is how Deleuze puts it]. In art,
we also have an original time, not just a
conventional series and dimensions of ordinary
time. It is a complication, 'identical to
eternity'. It is this time that is
regained. Involuntary memory helps us
recapture lost time, in a process of envelopment,
which presents an image of original time, but in a
brief and limited way, in a quick image [for fear
of producing bewilderment and uncertainty].
Reminiscence lasts longer, but it is still
ambiguous and tied to the present. Both
these operations can point to the pure past,
however. [involuntary memory also gives us a
sense of multiple selfhood, but this is still
'inferior to the Self of art' as far as essences
are concerned].
So essences are indeed incarnated in involuntary
memory, but they have to mix with substances that
are still not fully spiritualised or
dematerialized. These elements still
determine what appears as essences', and this
gives a role to experience, association,
subjectivism and contingency [there also seems to
be a hint that sciences like physics and
psychology can be brought to bear in a way which
strengthens mere associations, 41, and that these
lead to objectivism as well]. Subjectivism
is the real problem though, and that's why
reminiscences don't go far enough - 'essence
itself is no longer master of its own
incarnation'.
We are still dominated by life rather than art,
including conscious perceptions and voluntary
memories. This can help us to begin the
process of interpretation but only 'of certain
signs at privileged moments' (42). Sensuous signs
provide us with fewer clues than 'signs of desire,
of imagination or dreams' that escape contingency
and contiguity, but even these can only prepare us
for art and its revelations. Art does not
just explore involuntary memory. 'To learn
is to remember; but to remember is nothing more
than to learn, to have a presentiment'. We
must pass through the stages of an apprenticeship
to reach art, and if we do not 'we shall remain
incapable of understanding essence and even of
understanding that it was already there within
involuntary memory or within the joy of the
sensuous sign'. We will never be able to
properly examine causes [sic - in the sense of
necessary reason?]. Once we have finished
our apprenticeship we can reintegrate all the
other processes, as a series of 'successive
realizations' of essence.
Chapter 6 Series and Group
Difference and repetition appear in essences and
in the subjects experiencing them. Essences
appear unclearly in the signs because they have a
general form: Proust discusses this in terms of
things like discovering the laws of love.
However, 'An original difference presides over our
loves' (43), or possibly related to the image of
the mother or the father, but also appearing as an
image beyond experience, an archetype. It is
rich enough to be diversified and repeated, taking
different forms even in the same individual.
Love helps us both reminisce and discover, and
'memory and imagination relieve and correct each
other'. Successive loves offer differences,
but we also see how these are 'contained in a
primordial image' (44).
Love is particular but its image remains
unconscious, a discrepancy which is revealed by
repetition and the inadequacy of our consciousness
to grasp it. We can misunderstand experience
as something always new, disattending to
repetition. However, repetitions display a
series 'in which each term adds its minor
difference'. We see similarities, but also
contrasts, because we must 'take into account a
difference accumulated within the subject'.
Eventually, this converges on a law, but for
subjects, this tends to appear fully only after a
series of loves, another indication of an
apprenticeship.
There is a series of successive loves, but also a
serial form of each one, because the loved one is
complex and diverse. We undergo a process of
falling in love, in Proust's case punctuated by
bouts of jealousy. With Albertine, he begins
with 'undifferentiated perception', Albertine as
one of the group of girls, discovers more about
Albertine, especially when she's dead and no
longer interests him, and then finally imagines
what she would be like if she were still alive [as
a kind of resolution of his thoughts]. This
series also has the effect of transcending
experience and revealing 'the transubjective
reality'(45), for example when it is linked to the
stories of the loves of others such as
Swann. Swann is crucial in gaining access to
the processes for the hero. There is also
the infantile love for the mother, already
modified by Swann's visits [well--on one occasion
anyway, early in the book] : this also offers a
hint of a later anguish that the loved one gains
pleasure elsewhere: the hero's infantile grasp of
this means that the love for the mother is not a
simple origin, and enables a generalization,
ultimately to 'all humanity'.
The general and specific series of loves are
implicated in each other, suggesting ultimately
indices and laws. Imagination and memory
only go so far to help us here, relating mostly to
particular loves, to 'gather up' signs (46),
rather than interpreting them. Specific
loves are also forgotten, but they do help to
develop overall sensibility. Intelligence,
supported by sensibility, eventually becomes more
important than memory and imagination. This
is not to say that it is abstract truths which are
being pursued, for sensibility restricts
intelligence here, especially that which arises
from the pains of love and its ambiguity.
These force the intelligence to seek meanings [NB
- not the art itself]. This takes the form
of discovering laws, essences. [The argument
gets close to the idea of induction here, although
we are working with essential laws not empirical
ones]. Discovery produces joy out of
suffering and despair, and this also gets repeated
[Deleuze puts this as 'the phenomenon of
repetition forms a general joy' (47)]. We
realize that suffering can be transcended, and
arose from particular tricks or deceptions
[misrecognitions, one might say]. There is
even a comic element despite the tragic aspects of
repeated suffering: 'the humour of the Idea is to
manifest itself in despair'. More mundanely,
ideas can compensate for sorrows in Proustian
terms. Intelligence produces joy as it
discovers the general and reveals what was
unconscious, in the case of Proust that includes
the contributions the subject makes to the series
which love follows [rendered in the form of a
dramaturgical model].
The serial quality of love reveals general form,
and difference which leads to essence. In
love, this becomes unconscious, and gets
incarnated only if 'extrinsic conditions and
subjective contingencies' (48) permit, especially
with sensuous signs. Swann's tragedy is that
he never develops this insight, partly from a
different set of 'accidents of subjective
relations'. Again subjectivism has to be
rejected, although it seems plausible.
Contingency shows best the external factors, seen
in the failed encounter with Mlle de Stermaria [a
lady of easy virtue recommended for a quick one by
Saint-Loup. The hero sets everything up, but
she calls it off at the last minute, having met
someone else. He is reduced to tears of
frustration]. The somewhat contingent
selection of Albertine from all the candidates in
the little group is another example: things might
have been so different had the hero pursued
another one, and he remains aware that it might
easily have been Andrée [and even tries her out
for a bit after Albertine dies]. This is an
example showing that groups and series can be
complementary.
Essences are manifested first as general laws - of
deception for example, which is integral to love,
and which produces 'a veritable "physics" of
deception'(50). This also shows us the
deceptive nature of details which can easily
belong to other systems. Details can also
accumulate to such an extent that lies are
revealed, but the liar themselves can be unaware
of this, and incapable of managing it anyway due
to the limits of memory. Love seems to
involve a necessary series of lies, and also
necessary constraint of the loved one [wives are
captives]. Women have to manage their
secrets, including their attachment to Gomorrah
[and men their attachment to Sodom].
Much is revealed by the discovery of these
homosexual series. Proust explains [and
rationalizes and forgives] male homosexuality in
the strange metaphor of vegetation and how it
reproduces, or how hermaphrodites are found in
nature. This reveals 'the essence of love'
(51), where an initial hermaphroditism produces
the series of different sexes, with the inevitable
hint of ambiguity [as in the extraordinary
descriptions of womanly men who like manly
women]. Homosexuality also makes deception
essential, and is thus 'the truth of love'.
Hence the way in which love continually engenders
'signs that are those of Sodom and Gomorrah'.
There are two kinds of generality - the law of the
series, or the character of the group. The
hero first notes the characteristics of the group
of girls, and members of sexual minorities also
emit collective signs, known only to them, and
which produce solidarity. Nevertheless, 'the
true generality of love is serial' (52).
Worldly signs are 'immediately incarnated in
societies', and display only a group generality,
the lowest sign of essence. We might be able
to uncover 'social, historical and political
forces' among worldly signs, but they are 'emitted
in a void'. We study them through telescopes
rather than microscopes, by examining 'major
generalities'. We see the operation of
social laws best with 'stupid beings'
[Proust not Deleuze] who express them
involuntarily. Great individuals and
singular geniuses, like de C [!] are
rejected by these beings. Mechanical
laws also permit a substantial convenient
forgetting, the power of which is revealed by the
Dreyfus case. Deleuze also notes the
connection with Lenin on how the old prejudices
are rapidly replaced by even more poisonous new
ones.
Worldly signs display 'vacuity, stupidity,
forgetfulness', and are useful only in making
apprenticeship necessary. The inadequacies
of studies of the worldly 'excite the
intelligence, in order to be interpreted'
(53). We can start with grasping the
qualities of groups, before investigating their
unconscious content. Participating in social
life helps us see 'the immediate influence of
milieux that are simply physical and real'.
Interpretation needs to reconstruct these groups
according to 'the mental families to which they
are attached' [hence Proust bleating on about the
Guermantes and their cultural traditions of
spikiness etc. Deleuze takes the example of
the peculiar speech of the group, which resembles
that of the petty bourgeoisie, the true class to
which they belong].
Chapter 7 Pluralism in the System of Signs
The system of signs is pluralistic, involving many
characteristics which can be classified in
different ways. For an apprentice, the issue
is to see the extent to which a sign prepares us
for final revelation. For the mature thinker
who has experienced revelation, in Art, we have to
put each sign in its place and find its ultimate
meaning. Seven criteria [for the final
adequacy of the sign?] ensue.
First, signs are embodied in substances which are
more or less opaque and dematerialized, with
worldly signs as the most material. Only art
finally dematerializes signs
Second, different signs run different risks of
being interpreted objectively or subjectively,
since signs refer to both objects and
subjects. In love, we must pay homage to the
object, avow it. Early attempts to place objective
values on the signs lead to disappointment and a
reversion to subjective associations.
Different signs show these patterns in different
ways.
Third, signs produce emotions including exaltation
in suffering and anguish, and finally joy.
Joy takes its purest form in art.
Fourth, worldly signs are 'empty' (55), seemingly
requiring no attempt to find meaning, action or
thought. The signs of love are deceptive and
require a grasp of their contradictions.
Sensuous signs are truthful but their meaning is
still material [somehow subsisting in 'the
opposition of survival and nothingness'].
Only in art does the relation between sign and
meaning become closer so that we end with 'the
splendid final unity of an immaterial sign and a
spiritual meaning'.
Fifth, intelligence explicate or interprets the
sign sufficiently in the case of worldly
signs. In signs of love it must be supported
by suffering and eventual exaltation. For
the sensuous signs, involuntary memory and
imagination 'generated by desire' is
required. In art, pure thought develops
essences in order to act as interpreter.
Sixth, different forms of time are implicated in
signs, producing a different sort of truth.
Signs have to be interpreted over time, to catch
their development. There is nothing to find
in worldly signs, however, and time leaves
them 'intact or identical'. However, this
can still help interpreters realise that they
themselves have not stayed the same [surely,
finding the familiar faces so aged on revisit is
what really did it for Proust's hero?] .
With signs of love, we experience time lost, that
alters people and things, but we grasp this only
when things have ceased to interest us, when we
are no longer in love, for example. Sensuous
signs help us see that we can rediscover meaning
inside lost time, because they awaken our desire
and imagination, or help us become once again the
self that 'corresponds to their meaning'
(56). Art offers time regained, 'an absolute
primordial time, a veritable eternity that unites
sign and meaning'. However, these lines of
time can intersect in signs and their
combinations, as when art recaptures the lost time
which affects the other signs. Time lost can
also contaminate the worldly signs and the
sensuous signs and produce 'a sense of nothingness
even in the joys of sensibility'. Only when
we have regained time can we see the truth and
place of the other kinds. We can see the lines of
time as parallel series, or even arranged in a
hierarchy, as meanings become more complete and
profound. The higher lines help us recover
what is lost in the lower ones. In this way,
overall time is serial, and primordial time
'imbricates' (57) or encompasses the others.
[By extension?] 'The absolute Self of art
encompasses all the different kinds of
Self'. [Just looks like an elaboration of
the series of points already made]
Seventh, there seems to be an increasingly unity
between the sign and its meaning as we ascend the
hierarchy [implication], until essence is
revealed, and art discloses the relation between
essence and its variations. Then we can
'redescend the steps' [showing how essences are
explicated]. We do this not by falling in
love again or reliving our lives but by
discovering the truth 'appropriate' to each line
of time. We see the essence already there in
the lower steps, and how it has affected the
meaning of the sign, how it has been incarnated
but 'with more necessity and individuality' at the
lower levels, and with 'greater generality
and...more contingent data' at the higher.
When we do this, we have individualized the
subject and also 'absolutely' determined the
objects [as in sufficient reason]. Necessity
and the other qualities vary in the different
signs, however, with a minimum of generality in
the sensuous signs, a kind of empirical generality
in the signs of love and the worldly signs, 'the
generality of series or a generality of group',
based on either 'extrinsic objective
determinations', or subjective associations.
These offer a confused inability to see the
presence of essence. Once we have grasped
the essential, we can see it at work elsewhere,
and this will help us 'recover all the truths of
time, and all the kinds of signs'. We are
discussing 'implication and explication, in
development and development'. Meaning is
implicated in signs, 'wrapped' in them, a form of
involution as in the captive: 'the objects hold a
captive soul'. Signs also explicate or
develop, uncoil themselves in interpretation, as
when a jealous person reconstructs the world of
the other, or a sensitive person 'liberates the
souls implicated in things'. This is also a
process of meaning. Essence therefore must
be some 'third term that dominates the other
two'(58), which complicates the sign and the
meaning, or rather 'holds them in complication'[as
in the book on Leibniz
I think]. Signs are not reduced to objects,
and nor is meaning reduced to subjects, but they
are both combined with them. Essence becomes
'the sufficient reason for the other two terms and
for their relation'[thought so]. Proust's
hero's search is not dominated by memory and time,
but by signs and truth. Memory only
intervenes sporadically, time has an explanatory
meaning relative to particular signs and their
'truth'. Understanding is a matter of
apprenticeship and abrupt revelation, as in the
shock discovery of homosexuality in de C
[telegraphed long before though surely? This
is where the notion of the search as a realist
form becomes relevant?]. In the Search, the
hero does not know at first but comes to
understand later, and also loses interest once he
ceases to learn. The characters are not
important in themselves, but only insofar as they
emit signs, which can teach us things, including
things about time.
The 'Proustian vision of the world' initially
excludes 'crude matter, mental deliberation,
physics, philosophy', with philosophy standing for
'direct declaration and explicit signification,
proceeding from a mind seeking the truth'
(58-59). In particular, 'We are wrong to
believe in facts: there are only signs. We
are wrong to believe in truth; there are only
interpretations' (59) [still Proust not Deleuze
himself?] . It is the sign that unites
particular elements of sense data. We will
not understand it by pursuing 'the laws of matter
and the categories of mind. We are not
physicists or metaphysicians; we must be
Egyptologists. For there are no mechanical
laws between things or voluntary communications
between minds. Everything is implicated,
everything is complicated, everything is sign,
meaning, essence' (59). Not only that…
'Neither things nor minds exist, there are only
bodies: astral bodies, vegetal bodies'[Proust says
that homosexuals emit astral signs, and we have
already discussed the vegetal theory about the
origin of homosexuality]. Biology has not
realized that bodies 'are already a language',
while linguists would do well to remember that
'language is always the language of bodies'.
Symptoms are expressed in words, but more
importantly, 'every word is a symptom'.
People like hysterics use their bodies to speak in
a primary language… 'His body is an Egypt'
[all this extraordinary stuff is grounded in the
account of Mme Verdurin's strange physical
gestures which can only be understood as signs,
'an alphabet for the initiated'.
Conclusion to Part 1 The Image of Thought
The search for truth is what gives a philosophical
flavor to Proust, but this is not normal
philosophy, not 'classical philosophy of the
rationalist type' (60). That approach sees
that independent thinkers love or desire and
naturally seek the truth, assuming the 'goodwill
of thinking', basing investigation on a
premeditated decision. Method simply has to
overcome external influences that distract the
mind, while ideas have to be discovered and then
organized. The results will 'fulfill the
search and ensure agreements between minds'.
It implies that philosophers are friends, equally
inspired by goodwill to seek agreement about what
things and words mean. There is some implied
'Universal Mind that is in agreement with itself'
which makes significations both explicit and
communicable. Proust offers a critique based
on the key point, that goodwill thinking produces
arbitrary and abstract truths. It ignores
the things that force us to think, lying in 'the
dark regions' (61). Communication only
covers the conventional, and this sort of
philosophy only engenders the possible. None
of the truths are necessary. Instead, truth
is not simply revealed, but rather 'betrayed', not
communicated but interpreted, not willed but
involuntary. The search is an 'adventure of
the involuntary'. It requires an external
force that does violence, and we need to
investigate what it is that leads to
thought. For Proust, it is certain
impressions, encounters or expressions that force
us to think.
The truths that intelligence can grasp are not
necessary ones, and we should value them instead
of those that are communicated to us in spite of
ourselves [reads a bit like the value of surprise
in ethnography]. Proust insists that he was
not free in choosing truths, and this guarantee
their authenticity. No rules guaranteed the
search for truth. Intelligence produces only
logical truth: we can make our ideas logical, but
we don't know if they are true. The sign
forces us to think. Its contingency
guarantees the necessity of thought. Signs
do violence to thought because they break through
its 'natural stupor and its merely abstract
possibilities'(62). Thinking is in this
sense creative, and thinking is always active,
interpreting, explicating, deciphering and so
on. What it actually does is to liberate the
Idea implicit in the sign in 'the enveloped and
involuted state'. We know that jealousy
forces people to seek the truth, and that
sensitive people recognize the violence of
impressions. By comparison, 'The
communications of garrulous friendship are
nothing', and classical philosophy, its method and
good will is also 'nothing compared to the secret
pressures of the work of art'. Creative art
starts with signs, requiring interpretation,
uncovering 'the signs in which the truth betrays
itself'.
We require applied intelligence [as argued above],
an 'involuntary intelligence', driven onwards by
the pressure of signs, and the need to seek
meaning and deal with suffering. Memory
works in the same way, when involuntary
memory forces meaning upon us. Thought is
eventually forced to produce essences, and this
'depends least on its goodwill'. (63).
The difference between voluntary and involuntary
is not important in itself, since these represent
different exercises of the same processes.
All the processes like perception, memory, and
imagination are limited when they are exercised
voluntarily, because we are not forced to
interpret anything. Involuntary forms
suggest the limits of the voluntary conscious
processes, and thoughts can 'rise to a
transcendent exercise', and understand its own
necessity [that is, begin to deal with necessary
reason?]. This is the role for sensibility,
because it guides perceptions that would otherwise
be indifferent, and forces thought to recognize
its limits. This is the 'vocation of each
faculty' [each of the processes of thought as
above]. Thought 'is forced to conceive
essence as the sufficient reason of the sign and
its meaning'[again, presumably, in the 17th
century sense of sufficient reason?].
Ironically, Proust's critique 'becomes eminently
philosophical' (64), helping us understand 'a
concrete and dangerous thought' operating outside
convention and good will, and containing 'an
encountered, refracted violence', which will lead
us to those essences that 'dwell in dark regions',
not the regions of the clear and the distinct
[concepts which are much discussed in later work,
including Logic of
Sense, and also in the book on Leibniz - let's
hear it for the unclear indistinct, ie the
virtual]. Ideas or essences in Proust make
him a Platonist, not in the usual sense, but
because Plato also talked about active thoughts
being forced. The more passive thoughts
which only appear active 'are the objects of
recognition'[which Deleuze goes on to condemn as a
process in Difference
and Repetition]. Recognition is
itself contingent. It is unrecognised
objects, newly encountered signs that force us to
think, and Plato recognized that these were
'"simultaneously contrary perceptions"'.
Sensuous signs make us use our memory, set the
sensibilities in motion, excite thought, force us
to conceive of essences, a 'transcendent exercise'
where each faculty overcomes its own limits [and
then a couple of sentences on Greek philosophy
which I did not understand, including Socrates
claiming that he was more loving than people's
friends were, presumably because they were
accusing him of being an aggressive and pedantic
arsehole].
Socratic irony expects the sort of provoking
encounters that precede intelligence, even
provokes them. This is Greek irony.
Proust develops something different, Jewish humour
[quite a lot on the differences again in Logic
of Sense --and explained a bit better
in Kafka
--irony involves the intercession or revelation of
a higher law which contradicts the lower ones that
were held to be sacrosanct, ,and humour refers to
misleading comic manifestations of principles --
what I would have called ironic consequences],
which involves more of an exploration of the
violence of the encounters. This reaction
also precedes intelligence, necessarily so.
We also see the rejection of Platonism in other
ways, for example in the view that 'There is no
Logos: there are only hieroglyphs' (65), and the
hieroglyph itself is a double symbol,
showing both the 'accident of the encounter [its
arbitrary nature?] and the necessity of thought'.
Part II The Literary Machine
Chapter 8 Antilogos
Proust deals with 'the opposition of Athens and
Jerusalem' (69), [partly explained in the previous
section]. This involves rejecting [as
characters pointing to the truth] a number of
possible groups of observers, philosophers,
talkers and intellectuals. To group these
together would be to indicate allegiance to the
concept of Logos, 'a single universal dialectic;
the dialectic as Conversation among Friends',
leading to the collaborations and conformity we
have already noticed. The whole thing is
driven by intelligence which searches for laws and
relations among things and words, so as 'to weave
that perpetual web linking Parts to Whole and
Whole to Part', aiming at understanding how the
ideal represents a law which is then found in each
of its parts, a very common procedure among
friends, philosophers, scientists and
scholars. In practice, intelligence always
suggests the Whole before it is present, so that
it is already known how to apply it, 'the
dialectical trick by which we discover only what
we have already given ourselves, by which we
derive from things only what we have already
bought there'[as in classic Marxist critiques
of the tautologies of idealism, Althusser's mirror
structure of ideology and all that]. On the
specific level, Sainte-Beuve's biographical
approach shows the circularity, interrogating
friends of the writer in order to show that
writing displays the effects of friends.
This also has the effect of reducing authors to
merely nice boys, who people like. [Mme
Villeparisis does this, I recall, with a twist --
she says family friends like Stendhal were
horribly normal etc]. The Goncourt account
[where Proust's hero claims to have uncovered some
diaries describing salon life, and rejects them as
hopelessly descriptive and overdetailed] is an
example.
Instead, Proust proceed through a series of
oppositions, 'observation with sensibility,
philosophy with thought, of reflection with
translation' (70), and several others, for example
friendship and love, Greek accounts with Biblical
accounts of homosexuality. The results are
not logically conjoined, but show 'a non logical
and disjunctive use' (which foreshadows all the
stuff about various kind of syntheses in AntiOedipus,
with the disjunctive synthesis best representing
material reality]. Intelligence comes after
this effort, which also involves a shift to seeing
things as signs, and alluding to the implicated
and complicated, 'not... the clear images and
manifest ideas of the intelligence'.
The theme is continued with discussing Saint-Loup,
Norpois and Cottard [already defined as people who
speak in code]. All of them show 'the
bankruptcy of the Logos' and operate with
fragmentary signs [the clearest example for me is
Norpois who exposes all the dissimulations of
diplomatic language]. 'There is no Logos of
war, of politics, or of surgery, but only ciphers
coiled within substances and fragments'
(71). Proust operates with signs and
symptoms rather than attributes, with pathos
rather than Logos, with hieroglyphs rather
than analytic expressions and rational
thought. This is an implicit critique of
Greek philosophy. Signs have different
characteristics - their parts are configured
differently, they reveal different laws, they
involve the use of different faculties, they
create a different type of unity and language.
There are some connections with Plato [listed 71],
but no conception of an underlying state of
things, a world that imitates ideas, different
notions of essence, so that the Idea always comes
before or is presupposed, and so that the search
ends in a single Logos. Proust's search
involves 'qualitative transition, mutual fusion,
and "unstable opposition"', and this is referred
to the soul rather than to the states of the
world, the subjective aspects. However, we
can proceed further than subjective associations
[as above], and Swann is unable to do this,
despite his glimpses of the a superior reality of
art. For Proust, essence appears first as
'but a kind of superior viewpoint'(72), something
irreducible [apodictic?]. Art depicts
specific worlds which allude to this beginning of
the world and implies other specific
possibilities. The viewpoint remains
superior to individuals: 'It is not individual,
but on the contrary a principle of individuation'.
This is a way of referring to the whole issue of
objectivity in a modern way, where the old orders
have collapsed. Objectivity can only be
depicted in art, not in stable social
relationships and not in agreed discourses ['ideal
signification'-- describes the claims of objective
methodology in social science?]. Objectivity
arises from the formal structure of the work, 'its
style' (73). The individuated world emerges
from associations. Thinking produces
creation, 'to create the viewpoint valid for all
associations, the style valid for all images'.
[More links with Greek philosophy are pursued to
show the persistence of the Logos.] There is no
truth delivered by language. On the
contrary, language helps conceal the truth, and
the truth has to be uncovered, 'betrayed'.
Fragments, parts or individual signs do not always
help us understand the whole or to reconstruct it,
because sometimes, there is 'no totality into
which it can enter, no unity from which it is
torn' (74), and this is unknown to the Greeks -
everything however insignificant testifies to the
Logos. [More references to Jerusalem here,
referring to Plato as a Jew compared to the stoics
- I think this means he wanted to operate with
some single Logos, in a kind of philosophical
monotheism]. We can only understand
reconstruction by referring to time, admitting
that some fragments cannot be restored any more
and that some pieces do not fit. We have the
concept of time as a relation of 'parts of
different sizes and shapes, which cannot be
adapted, which do not develop at the same rhythm,
and which the stream of style does not sweep along
the same speed' [foreshadows the great analysis of
cinematic time as in Citizen
Kane]. There is no cosmic order.
Signs are no longer traceable to an underlying
Logos. We have to look at the structure of
the work itself, without any external reference,
including allegory or analogy. [Proust's
commentary on other authors, maybe in the piece on
Saint-Beuve, is used in support here].
We can only grasp particular associative chains by
a creative artistic act, and this act itself
'takes the role of an incongruous part within the
whole'.
This is how the truth is guaranteed, by this
method that fully admits chance encounters, unlike
the intelligence [condemned to act entirely
rationally and logically in Deleuze] .
Art is not seen as some organic totality linking
parts and wholes in reciprocal
determination. The painting by Vermeer has
an incongruous yellow patch [which so fascinates
the dying Cottard that he wishes he had spent his
life studying art]. The little phrase in
Vinteuil is misunderstood as a simple part or
fragment with a specific meaning [which is how all
the aristo idiots try to understand it, as Swann's
and Odette's song]; the church at Balbec shows
pleasing discordant parts that resists simple
interpretation [I missed this bit]. These
and other 'mysterious viewpoints' cannot be added
together into some organic totality. Instead
they should be seen as fragments pointing to
['determining' (75)] 'a crystallization' [Bogue is
good on this -- a crystal as an element
precipitating a change of state] . The old
organicism as in vegetal systems, disappears in
favour of 'animal totality', an emergent whole
driven by Time not Logos.
Chapter 9 Cells and Vessels
Organic unity is not present at the start of the
novel, and nor does Proust merely uncover it: he
creates a unity, from a series of incommensurable
and fragmented parts which provide the diversity
of the work. We can understand this in terms
of two metaphors ['figures' (76) ], the container
and content, or the relation between parts and
wholes. The first one talks about
envelopment, encasing and implication, where
things or names are boxes which contain --
but there is always 'excessive content'.
Names have the same qualities, like the name
Guermantes [even more so for the strange concept
of the Guermantes Way]. The narrator himself
explicates, unfolds. The second metaphor
involves complication, the coexistence of non
communicating parts, opposing aspects. Here
the narrator must choose to begin, at least, parts
of the complex composition. Open boxes
appear in the first conception, closed vessels in
the second [with a rather mystifying bit about how
the first one refers to 'the position of the
content without common measure', while the latter
refers to 'the opposition of the proximity without
communication' --slightly better explained below
(77), and see Bogue].
Qualities often combine and shift from one
to the other. Albertine, for example,
complicates the many possible characters in
herself, but she also implicates or envelops a
series of impressions based on the encounters on
the beach, and these have to be unfolded or
uncoiled.
The 'great categories of the Search' [metaphors of
searching, beginnning, regaining and all that?]
indicate a choice or commitment to one or the
other figure, but that several figures can
represent a category, sometimes implying a kind of
doubling. Proper names, for example act as
boxes at first, eventually emptied [explicated] in
a way that leads to disappointment, but as common
nouns, they can also be organized in a discourse
to connect 'certain non communicating fragments of
truth and lies chosen by the interpreter' [I think
again we are describing realist narratives, where
the speech of the character is reported, but the
off-screen narrator adds meanings which only
he can detect, because only he knows the
plot]. At the level of the faculties, memory
opens boxes, while desire or sleep chooses a
particular vessel, one that will enable deeper
sleep, or one that will express 'a certain degree
of love'. Desire multiplies the
noncommunicating characters of Albertine, while
memory places her in 'incommensurable' areas of
memory (78) [and both lead to jealousy and
control-freakery].
What exactly is the container and the content in
each case, and what do we do when content resists
being explicated, or we see something
incommensurable [contradictory or
incomplete]? Proust describes the madeleine
and the tea as unfolding or explicating all the
characteristics of life in Combray. However,
the true container is not the cup but the flavor,
and the content is not associated with just the
flavor, but is produced by the essence of Combray,
as 'pure Viewpoint', not just the mundane
viewpoint of an inhabitant. The initial
heuristic connection with the chain of
associations is incomplete, and creation has to
take over. The essence does not just remind
us of an individual viewpoint, but provides the
joy of discovering a pure viewpoint, a new self,
'the resurrection of a self'. Love as faces
and bodies similarly express whole worlds which
have to be explicated. Explication requires
a search for something excessive, and this is 'the
indivisible character of desire that seeks to give
a form to matter' (79). And yet the excess
is always limited by specific associations, and we
can see this when we look at how the beloved one
perceives us. Thus the excess appear in a
specific bodily form that will also go on
inevitably to be emptied out. It is like the
paradox in which we have to capture people in
order to explicate them, to exhaust all the
possibilities, although jealousy usually suggests
additional and inexhaustible ones. This emptying
can also be seen as a kind of suicide.
Names both [denote and connote], and this provides
the excess associations which arise whenever we
try just to explicate [denotations]. Content
is either originally lost, or emptied out, or
'separated' (80), which leads us to be
disappointed [with concrete individuals or simple
descriptive categories in general?]. The
world is too complex to be ordered, and even
subjective forms of association break down.
'Transcendent but variable and violently
imbricated viewpoints' appear. At first,
this produces incompatible routes towards
understanding, the two Ways -- although
Gilberte insists they can be unified, it never
happens. Even the final revelation does not
exactly unify the different ways of proceeding,
but multiplies transversal links {the key for
Bogue] The dualistic aspect of people's
faces show the same tendency [I didn't quite
recognise the description of women's faces as
offering a duality, more a complex assemblage, for
me — Deleuze seems to describe the complexity or
something that breaks out of any {mechanical as
opposed to organic} attempt to unify facial
aspects].
The world can also be seen as merely 'a
statistical reality'[a collection, an aggregate,
not a proper group], containing infinitely
different worlds, within which Swann never gets
accepted by the Verdurins. And this is the
final position of Proust, admitting an
unmanageable mixture, so that all the objects and
words appear as in 'a specifically tinted
aquarium, containing a certain species of fish,
beyond the pseudo-unity of the Logos'(81).
Disruptive elements include the surprisingly
vulgar words that Albertine uses [including an
extraordinary phrase about 'breaking her pot', at
which the translator has to intervene to explain
that this might be a reference to anal sex].
Here, it is the association between the words of
one discourse, and those that depict other
discourses that offer an image of how the
fragments of the world are brought together in
proximity [I think, 82, perhaps specifically
contiguity]. [Deleuze notes that this gives
lying a linguistic basis - and then, more
mystifyingly, also a 'geographical' one --
ie relations of contiguity here definitely].
In closed vessels we find only statistical
totalities, infinities of processes, different
elements which provide only the impression of
unity. Closed vessels can communicate,
however, by 'establishing transversals' [a big
theme in Guattari
as well]. These remind us that there is no
simple way of reducing diversity, certainly not in
a mechanical way, and the need to preserve a
multiplicity as 'original unity'. Thus
jealousy is a transversal in love's multiplicity
[good example of a pathological one, not
considered in Guattari]. Closed vessels
might be arranged differently in the
multiplicity, sometimes in opposing
directions, for example, and here when we join
them altogether, it is via the transversal, [and
we do not need to use only relations like
metaphor, analogy or other forms of repetition,
represented in another phrase which would be
impenetrable if you did not know the context: 'For
travel does not connect places, but affirms only
the difference', supported by a direct quote from
Proust about how he enjoys travel the more he
distinguishes the departure and the arrival so as
to experience the journey in its totality -- in
the bit about the train journey].
It is no longer a matter of explicating but
choosing one sealed vessel and the self that it
implies, like choosing a certain girl in a group,
or a certain word in what she says, or a certain
feeling that we have. When we attempt to
understand, we are pursuing 'the activity
corresponding to complication'(83) [pursuing
singularities into multiplicities?].
Choosing like this is like waking up from all the
creative possibilities of sleep, to rediscover the
self of the previous day, and 'the chain of
associations that links us to reality'. It
is not a conventional self that acts, however,
'because we ourselves are chosen', adopting a
certain self in the process of choosing others to
love, for example, sometimes with surprising
consequences. Proust discuss these matters
in the section about what it feels like to
wake up, and regain our own self [and seems to
conclude that it is a matter of habit to adopt the
old familiar self again].
In contrast to the mundane choices, there is 'a
pure choosing that has no more subject than it has
objects, because it uses the interpreter no less
than the thing to interpret': this underlines the
reference in Proust to what 'we' do, and it is why
sleep and dreaming is a form of pure interpreting,
breaking the conventional links to signs.
Interpreting is always a transversal process, and
heads not towards some united conception of the
fragments, but towards a higher state, which
actually involves 'preventing them from forming a
[conventional eg subjective?] whole' (83-4).
The subject of the search is not an individual
self, but rather 'that we without
content'[I think the argument is that the mundane
or empirical self would rapidly attempt to limit
interpretation, 'totalize' it].
Despite all the possible uses of signs, whether
objective or subjective, responding better to one
faculty than another, implying a relation with the
essences in a different way, there are still
really only two formal types - open boxes to be
explicated, sealed vessels to be chosen.
Signs gain their fragmentary nature because the
content of boxes is so diverse, elements are
incommensurable, and sealed boxes do not
communicate with each other or the environment
[but still relate]. It is time that explains
these 'non spatial distances'(84).
[Confusingly] these are 'distances without
intervals'[I think what this means is that they
are brought together in subjective time not
temporal time or space --or in Time?]. Lost
time introduces distances, while time regained
'establishes a contiguity of distant
things'. Both act together to 'affirm the
fragments as disjunct'. There is no total
Whole to be regained. It is not a matter of
linking episodes in time, say through the
dialectic, but affirming them simultaneously
[citing Bergson here]. This affirmation does
not imply a straightforward succession in time,
any more than fragments represent a lost whole in
space: 'Time is precisely the transversal
[medium?] of all possible spaces'.
Chapter 10 Levels of the Search
No Logos unites the fragments, and so there is no
conventional law to be formulated. The Greek
notion of Logos always saw it as a secondary power
subordinate to the Good, and useful only if it led
to some transcendental image of it. In
modern thought, however 'the law becomes a primary
power' (84), defining the good itself, 'the
law, without any other specifications', an entity,
informal unity, leading to no knowledge of the
Good [empirical generalizations take over from
searches for deeper unity?] . This law
produces new separations and partitions that do
not communicate, that are incommensurable.
We have to obey the law, and learn about it only
through being punished for transgression [fanciful
stuff about punishing the 'agonised body'].
Kafka
represents modern understandings of this
law. Proust reads it differently as a matter
of appearances concealing a fragmented
reality. This produces a certain 'schizoid
consciousness of the law' (86), sometimes
indicated by guilt and its connection with love as
an innocence between two guilts [referenced to the
turmoils of loving Albertine, wanting to love her,
while fighting off suspicion and guilt].
Only the certainty prompted by guilt ends the
process, and love is replaced by empirical inquiry
and conviction, when love no longer
interests the hero. Guilt features in the
series of understandings of homosexuality, and
appears first as a kind of primal curse, although
Proust goes on to challenge the curse, at several
levels, rescuing it as [natural].
We then have different levels of understanding,
first of heterosexual love its 'contrasts and
repetitions' (87), then a split introduced into
love to follow the different paths of Gomorrah and
Sodom, both of which contain a secret, producing
notions of sin and guilt. This is also to be
explained as merely social operating with 'a
statistical value'. This notion of
statistical values forming groups appears
elsewhere too. Underneath, is a third level,
'the agitations of singular particles', [so we are
getting close to the language of singularity and
multiplicity?], selves which form the
groups. The different Ways are statistical
composites of the individuals, 'elementary
figures'. Elementary [biological] particles
and organs are responsible for homosexual loves.
Separation is still important as a source of
complementarity, as when two sexes appear in the
same individual. The vegetal explanations
become significant, replacing some notion of an
[empirical] animal totality. The
hermaphrodite expresses the third level combining
the sexes in a way which makes them communicate,
but not participating in any statistical
aggregates [because they contain multiple sexed
selves]. So we have two statistical
aggregates, homosexual but still statistical
series relating those of the same sex, but a
transsexual third level [currently very
fashionable]. Both sexes coexist as
fragments or 'partial objects'(88) in the
hermaphrodite, requiring a third party to open and
fertilize the female or male parts [not orchids
and wasps, but general fertilizing insects here -
these are the specific male or female partners
that are encountered?]. This involves 'a
transversal dimension' of communication, which
exist even in those statistically defined as male
or female. Transexuality appears as
something 'local and nonspecific'[actually a
'local and non specific homosexuality'] where
people seek out the opposite qualities in their
partners. [Clearly appearing in Proust's
arguments about transexuality and polymorphous
diversity —Deleuze, Deleuze! finds this
'obscure'(89)]. It alludes to the efforts
that Proust himself had to make, 'supposedly', to
'change an Albert into Albertine'[a number of
critics make this point, that Albertine really is
a transposition of a certain male lover of
Proust's]. This provides a profound link
between the text and life that is not just normal
biographical influence, but the discovery of a
third level.
'Jealousy is the very delirium of signs'.
Jealousy is fundamentally linked to homosexuality,
since homosexuality 'contains possible worlds'
(90), requiring a number of suspicious viewpoints
instead of simple involvement, with implications
of one's own status as simply an element of these
other worlds. Jealousy thus becomes not just
an awareness of other worlds, 'but the discovery
of the unknowable world' of the viewpoint of the
other. Jealousy eventually also 'discovers
the transexuality of the beloved', 'the discovery
of partial objects', which is worse than
discovering rival persons. As a result,
jealousy comes to operate with a logic of
captivity, 'to immure the beloved'. All
these other possible worlds then become empty and
enveloped. Homosexual series are broken
off.
Homosexuality becomes an original sin after all
which requires punishment by imprisonment.
Imprisonment stops transversal [and internal]
communication between the components of complex
sexuality. Stopping transversal
communication, however permits other forms, which
produce 'amazing accidents and outwits our
suspicions' (91) [chance encounters?]. [With
a lovely bit of pseudy commentary: 'sequestration,
voyeurism and profanation - the Proustian
trinity', explained below ]. Imprisoning someone
means that we can see them without being seen
ourselves, and without being 'carried away by the
beloved's viewpoint', as when Proust loves seeing
Albertine asleep. We see to stop others
seeing, 'even symbolically' [we impose our
gaze]. Making someone else see, 'imposes on
him a strange, abominable, hideous spectacle', a
series of partial objects with some unnatural
couplings suggested. This involves treating
the person as an object himself, forcing him to
communicate transversally [nasty implications for
pedagogy then?].
This is the theme of profanation. A
photograph of a father becomes associated with
sexual revels [for young Miss Vinteuil in the
scene overlooked by the hero]. Family
furniture is placed in a brothel, Albertine is
embraced near to his mother's room, and dreams
involve caging his parents. Profanation like
this makes every one 'function as a partial
object', something partitioned, a spectacle, a
form of imprisonment in the spectacle.
Freud saw anxiety arising from relating to the
law. Infantile aggression against the
beloved involves a threat to the loss of love and
guilt focused upon the self. The law also
provides 'depressive consciousness' as well as the
'schizoid consciousness' induced by the first
reaction [this is much clearer when Deleuze
discusses schizophrenia through Klein in Logic of Sense].
For Proust, guilt remains superficial, social, not
really internalized, but the threat of
losing love 'truly defines destiny or the law'
(92). To love without being loved involves
this sense of exclusion from the world of the
beloved which will inevitably lead to the end of
love, 'explication...will...lead the self that
loves to its death' [add that to Rancière to
really cut some philosophical wood!].
Imprisonment [sequestration] of the loved one
makes her turn into a 'horrified spectator' of her
own 'partitioned scenes'. This is the
Proustian Trinity above -'the entire law of love'.
Law in general, once we have abandoned the Greek
conception, simply controls the parts without
referring to some ultimate whole. It
assembles parts within sealed containers,
producing 'discrepancy,… remoteness,…
distance, and… partitioning'[sounds like
leibnizian monads again, but without god].
Only occasional 'aberrant communications between
the non communicating vessels' are possible,
only transversal unity not totalization.
Forcing these vessels' to communicate by inserting
fragments from other vessels' into them only
confirms 'the infinite void of distances'. [Great
basis for a critique of participatory pedagogy --
we only we realize we are truly alone etc]
This is why Proust refers to the need for
telescopes not microscopes, even though he does
refer to the infinitely small as in the
infinitesimal differences between the faces of
Albertine. However, only telescoping helps
him unites 'the collision between worlds, and the
folding of the parts one within another'.
[And Proust is cited as saying he deliberately
used the telescope to perceive things, and how the
tiny things each constituted a world, that the
group of girls can only be understood through
'"impassioned astronomy"' (93)]. Even when
things are contiguous, distance is not reduced but
affirmed or even extended: they are 'fragments of
disparate universes'.
Chapter 11 The Three Machines
The idea is for people to learn about themselves
by recognizing what Proust writes, so the Search
is also a machine—that is it has the 'property of
being or whatever we like, of having the
overdetermination of whatever we like' (94).
It is not that we enjoy sonatas, but that the work
itself is a sonata, and also 'a
cathedral'(95), a delirium, an exercise to train
the faculties, 'anything we like provided we make
the whole thing work'. Hence 'The modern
work of art has no problem of meaning, it has only
a problem of use' [which is really what he meant
by saying we can use his books how we like?
As long as we search, and learn about
ourselves]. Art is machinic in the sense
that it is 'productive of certain truths'.
Truth has to be produced, extracted from
impressions, 'hewn out of our life'. It is
never just discovered or just created [as in
intelligent creation as above, which deliver only
logical or possible truth - 'the creative
imagination is worth no more than the discovering
or observing intelligence'. At best, memory
and creation are preliminary aspects of production
as we saw.
Art begins with an impression which 'unites in
itself the accident of the encounter and the
necessity of the effect, or violence that it
obliges us to undergo'. It presupposes some
connection between a sign and the involuntary—as
Proust says, '"it is suffering that then sets them
in motion"' (96). Meaning and truth itself
does not reside in the impression or the memory
but in their 'spiritual equivalents' produced by
the 'machine of interpretation'. This is how
art produces new links.
There are orders of truth and orders of
production, and not just those in time regained
and lost time. The final act of
systematization produces three orders—time
regained seems to collect together all the natural
reminiscences and offer them an aesthetic essence,
while lost time seems to just produce
[illustrations] 'secondary truths'. Yet the
orders are also separated conceptually. The
first one, operating with reminiscences and
essences is a matter of 'singularity' and the
production of time that corresponds to them.
The second order is equally concerned with art,
but groups pleasures and pains which refer to
something else, even if this is not immediately
perceived—worldly signs and the signs of
love. These obey general laws and produce
lost time. The third order is a matter of
'universal alteration, deaths and the idea of
death, the production of catastrophe (signs of
ageing, disease, and death)'. The truths
that the second level reinforce those at the first
through 'analogy, 'proof a contrario' in
another domain. Truths of the third order
reinforce the first, but also insist that they
must be surmounted. It is only following the
third order that helps us see that unfulfilled
pains and pleasures are not final.
Worldly and love signs are grouped here at the
first level [actually their values], since both
are interpreted primarily through the intelligence
operating after the signs and providing meaning in
the form of a general law, of the series, or of
worldliness. However, we are still only
working with 'crude resemblances' (97), and we can
see that the machine at this level produces only
partial objects, 'fragments without totality',
offering law like connections involving distance
and separation, as we saw all. Even dreams
offer us persons as partial objects, and when we
begin to understand the world, or love, at this
level, we only connect them together as isolated
fragments. We see this when we start to
realize that the fragments of a person represent
the total person underneath. General laws
never produce that insight, though, only 'group
truths or ...corresponding serial truths'.
The second type of machine produces different
sorts of connections, 'resonances, effects of
resonance' (98), as in the operations of
involuntary memory. Desire also produces
resonance [Proust's hero adds meaning to the
steeples he sees on a country drive]. Art
produces yet a third type of resonances that are
not just memory, and which require activity on the
part of the mind to discover connections [he
gropes for meaning when he trips over the uneven
paving stones]. The alliance between words
helps facilitate this sort of resonance, joining
two remote objects [that is we verbalize the
connections?]. This does not require or
depend upon the earlier production of partial
objects: instead, the relation 'is like that
between a strong and a weak beat', and also the
difference between time regained and the lost
time. Resonance depends on 'faculties of
extraction or interpretation' and offers a
qualitative production, not a general law, not a
series but 'a singular essence', something
localised or individuated. Resonance does
not just totalize fragments, but extracts
its own fragments, setting up the resonance but
not totalizing [not just developing a statistical
aggregate, but arriving at some essence, say of
Combray 'as it was never experienced...
never viewed']
Both lost time and time regained [to get back to
that terminology] operate with fragments and
divisions, and it is not that lost time is
unproductive: there are two sorts of
production. This is why Proust argues
[imprecisely] that the first offers the foundation
of the second, and that is why we have to begin
our apprenticeship with lost time before getting
to time regained.
Proust is not alone in describing occasional
examples of ecstasy or insight. What makes
him different is that he sees them as productions,
'the effect of the literary machine' (99) [it is
something that authors construct] .
Resonances multiply at the end of the search, as
the machine gets up to speed. It is no
longer a matter of some experience outside
literature, but rather an effect of 'artistic
experimentation produced by literature', a
literary effect. It shows that the machine
works, and Proust asks whether it will work for
other people as they discover analogous
effects. Any effects observed by readers
should not be misunderstood as something trivial,
some triggering of memory. Rather, it is
recognising the effects of the work of art itself.
It is not just a matter of examining Proust's own
interpretations, but rather addressing 'the entire
phenomenon itself'. There are objective
aspects such as the particular flavor of the
madeleine, and subjective aspects like associative
chains. These combine to produce something
different, 'the Essence, the spiritual
Equivalent'(100), something not just
subjective. We have not just discovered and
created, but produced, and the hero comes to
realise that resonance is produced, and itself has
artistic effects. This is not apparent at
the beginning, but emerges from 'a certain
argument between art and life'. At first,
resonance appears as ecstasy as an ultimate goal,
but this requires nothing particularly from
art. Then the resonance produces effects but
under 'given natural conditions' or through
unconscious memory. Only at the end do we
see 'what art is capable of adding'.
Artistic style itself produces resonance and
extracts an image, and does so in free conditions,
not limited by the unconscious or by nature.
Art then becomes the ultimate goal of life,
something which does not emerge from external
mechanisms. This is how art becomes the
spiritual equivalent of life.
So we shift from an interest in natural moments to
the artistic machine itself and how it produces
effects. This is just like Joyce 'and his
machine for producing epiphanies'. They
start with the object then subjective experience,
then a multiplicity of fragments which destroys
these orders, and only then can art assume its
full meaning, as a machine which itself sets up
resonances, produces epiphanies, releases the
image and reincarnates it. A short circuit
is established between signifier and signified in
a special kind of poetic language. New
linguistic conventions have to emerge to guide
this work, and produce a new whole.
Back to the third Proustian order of alteration
and death. We see the effects of ageing in
the scenes in the salon towards the end. Are
we meant to have seen the idea of death underneath
all the earlier moments and ecstasies, through a
resonance with those earlier moments? Can we
read the succession of selves in love affairs as
alluding to suicide and death? That would make it
all pointless, even art. Now we have to establish
something else as well - reconciliation, 'a
contradiction to be surmounted' which could not be
managed in the earlier orders: partial objects
remain indifferent to the death of the other,
simply offer the notion of death as some universal
end, something that contradicts ecstasies of the
earlier processes. The contradiction is
resolved after further explanation, since it was
at first incomprehensible: the third order seems
to end in death, something unproductive, so how
can we extract something productive from it, and
therefore rescue the whole work of art?
Death is conceived differently, as an effect of
time. The experience of ageing pushes
moments of the past into still more remote and
improbable areas, 'the forced movement of greater
amplitude' (102) []but we know we lived then -- so
we also know others lived centuries before? So we
know we will live on] . But this offers us a
notion of a horizon in time, something which
'dilates time infinitely', unlike subjective
syntheses and resonances which contract
time. Death ceases to be severance, and
appears rather as 'an effect of mixture or
confusion' (103), and it implies that human beings
are 'monstrous', existing within time in a much
more extensive way than in ordinary life,'that is
[only] reserved for them in space', a measureless
time [I remember this as Proust saying something
rather more mundane, that he realizes that human
beings always have limited lives, but that they
are connected somehow across the whole space of
time in which humans have lived. This
comforts our hero in a strange fatalistic
way]. In this way, the death of an
individual becomes a part of the production of
life, a work of art in itself. Time 'becomes
sensuous' [that is seems to take on a purpose of
its own], shaping faces, introducing death.
When the hero thinks of his grandmother, he has
somehow meshed this forced movement with a mere
resonance, sweeping away the resonance. Time
itself is now seen as a kind of production capable
of reconciling time lost and time regained.
Overall, we now see there are three kinds of
machine at work in producing the book: 'machines
of partial objects (impulses); machines of
resonance (Eros); machines of forced movement
(Thanatos)' [so Deleuze is still happy with
Freudian terms at this stage]. Each one
produces truths, appearing as an effect of time:
lost time produces fragmented partial objects,
time regained resonates, lost time of another kind
by amplifying forced movements. This second
way in which time gets lost is 'passed into the
work and becomes the condition of its form'.
[Heavy going. I think this means that it is
only the thought of death and somehow the survival
of human beings after death that gives a point to
the whole exercise, which is what Deleuze said
about two pages ago].
Chapter 12 Style
How will the different orders be organized
within each other, without one totalizing the
others? Each order is self sufficient,
and lacks nothing, and resists any attempt to
impose organic unity. The emphasis is on
incompletion. There are no worldly
contents which can be systematized
[empirically] or idealised in an associative
chain. The viewpoints that transcend the
subject themselves are not unified, more that
'a universe corresponds to each, not
communicating with the others, affirming an
irreducible difference' (104). Each
artistic viewpoint is the same. The
essence then becomes 'an individuating
viewpoint superior to the individuals
themselves' [further explained in the book
on Leibniz], with no power to unify or
totalize.
So what constitutes the unity of the work, and
how can different readers communicate with the
work? There is Logos or other kind of
unity. Instead, it is 'the unity of this
very multiplicity, the whole that is the whole
of just these fragments' (105). The
whole as an effect of the multiplicity, of a
machine. Leibniz was the first to
discuss this notion of communication between
sealed parts, through the argument that closed
monads all express the same world but in an
infinite series of predicates, each offering a
separate region of expression or different
viewpoint. However, it is God that
causes this envelopment and correspondence
between the monads, but God is not available
to Proust, so there is no ultimately shared
world or 'pre-established stock'[of
viewpoints]. (106). Proust thinks
that Balzac originated the problem and solved
it with a new type of work of art, where unity
is 'an effect of his books', after a
'retrospective illumination'. The Whole
that results does not alter anything about the
fragmented parts, however. There is no
individual Balzac style, or rather that the
fragments he distributes eventually result in
a confirming whole as a result. This is,
Proust argues [in Against Sainte Beuve],
a matter of style explicating, joining
together fragments which are not dissolved and
which do not exhibit some pre-established
harmony.
Proust's 'idiosyncratic' (107) language also
produces effects, and we could suggest that he
has no style in any individual sense either,
although this would require further
comparisons with Balzac [suggested 107].
Proust certainly 'explicates with images',
interpreting without identifying which subject
it is, and by multiplying viewpoints
even towards the same sentence [I have called
these bits metafictional]. The signs are
at different rates of development and are in
associative chains, but they lead to
viewpoints [which Deleuze is equating with
essence throughout, as in Leibniz?
However, it is these essences that are
combined into multiplicities].
Explicating the significance of each sign
often involves beginning with two different
objects, which might offer objective
resemblance or subjective associations, and
this is how a viewpoint proper to each of the
objects is attained: this also dislocates the
object. A single viewpoint is subdivided
into viewpoints of these objects which do not
communicate. They work by 'setting up
resonance among themselves'[the example is how
the painter Elstir interchanges the sea and
the land which remain distinct - it is their
viewpoints that are being combined in the
painting].
Style which explicates 'produces
[objects as] partial objects'. This in
turn 'produces effects of resonance and forced
movements' in the form of an image.
Producing these images 'in the pure state is
what we find in art', above all in
music. We can follow essences from the
signs of art to the lower level signs.
'Objective description and associative
suggestion' (108) are inevitably reintroduced,
as a result of the 'material conditions of
incarnation' contained in the essence.
Free artistic creativity seems to be limited
by this, another reason for not thinking of
style is a matter of individuals but of
essence [to be nice and paradoxical,
Deleuze then defines essence as
'nonstyle'. He plays the same trick
talking about nonsense in Logic of Sense,
so that it looks as if there's some deep
connections or contradiction being suggested
here, although sometimes nonsense just means
something which is not sense. To spoil
his rhetorical tricks, my notes render that
meaning as 'non-sense'].
So [individual] style is unified by something
outside. This is not essence as
viewpoint, which remains 'perpetually
fragmenting and fragmented'. It is a
special unity that appears afterwards, enables
the viewpoints to exchange the essences to
communicate. It is communicated by what
looks like another fragment, 'a final
brushstroke'. What is happening is that
'a world reduced to a multiplicity of chaos'
is unified by 'the formal structure of the
work of art' [why not just say that before,
you prat! This is going to turn out to
be an artistic version of the 'plane of
consistency', a 'plane of composition',
which philosophy/art both constructs and then
explorers as if it was something
external]. [Proust's] art introduces new
linguistic conventions to which the work
itself submits [citing Eco].
The structure is particularly
characterized by 'a transversal dimension'.
[Bogue says Deleuze discovered this concept in
Proust,but also met it in Guattari's work --
nicely made practical in Chaosmosis]
In Proust, it is described in terms of
understanding of the route of the train to
bring into communication the viewpoints of a
landscape [we understand the track as uniting
specific geographical places and also people
who appear on the stations. I read that
as just a straightforward banal device to use
a journey to connect things]. Proust
brings into communication things that do not
communicate among themselves. The
various Ways are also constituted by a
transversality [the author's particular way of
connecting people, countryside and
ancestry]. Transversality is the route
of the fertilizing insect in the reproduction
of hermaphrodite plants. Proust's
contribution is to develop the linguistic
conventions of transversality, within and
between sentences, and also to connect
Proust's book to those that he liked.
This transversality communicates with the
public, with the other works by the same
person, and with the works of other people and
with works to come. Transversality
establishes unity and totality, but not as a
matter of totalizing objects or subjects [it
all sounds like a fancy version of how analogy
works]. Proust adds this dimension to
the characters and events in the book, and
transversality operates in time, but 'without
common measure' (109). Only then are the
sealed vessels brought into communication [the
examples are Odette and Swann, or Albertine
and the narrator—seeing Odette as an old woman
tied up with the Duke of Guermantes is the
'final brushstroke'. I must say that the
same suspicion of nonsubjective formal kinds
of communication also intruded with the other
unlikely coincidences where the characters
meet. I can see that these unlikely
meetings help break with any simple objective
description of the characters, as does the
surprising interest of Albertine in Gomorrah].
[The last sentence says that it, something
that he has been calling time, is also a 'the
dimension of the narrator, which has the power
to be the whole of these parts without
totalizing them', another rather damp squib
then. It could be Derrida, on writing].
Conclusion to Part II Presence and Function
of Madness: The Spider
It is not a matter of whether Proust was mad
himself, but how madness appears in the work
and what its function might be. There
are two different modalities of madness in de
C and Albertine. De C appear as as a mad
person early in the novel. Morel is
terrified of him. He always seems to be
in the grip of some [self-destructive] madness
rather than just being immoral [although the
Verdurins just see him as an immoral prat].
Mme de Sturgis forbids him to visit her
children because he was always pinching their
chins [can't say I've made a note of that], a
matter of irresponsibility rather than
immorality. His madness becomes certain
at the end of the novel. Albertine is
retrospectively seen as mad, and Andree even
suspects that she might have been led to
suicide by it.
The connections between madness,
irresponsibility and sexuality is not
explained in terms of the Oedipal schema,
despite 'Proust's cherished theme of
parricide' (111) [must be pretty implicit - we
do get to hear very little about his father,
and there are clearly tensions about not
letting Mama kiss him goodnight].
De C is a strong personality and individual,
but his individuality also conceals many
unknowns things. His two 'notable
points' are the eyes and the voice [a pretty
restricted notion of faciality then], and both
are capable of displaying a number of
emotions. This makes him into a secret
and mystery to be interpreted. He also
endlessly interprets himself as a kind of
'delirium of interpretation'.
He offers 'three major speeches to the
narrator'. Beneath the signs he
transmits, there is something essential
elsewhere, some Logos which he subscribes
to. The three speeches have a common
structure: first denial and distancing
[strange cycles of attraction and repulsion I
called it], and then a third unexpected one,
displayed by 'rage... sadistic fantasy…
the eruption of madness' (112).
These appear in all the speeches, but the
madness is really only diagnosed and managed
by trampling his hat [ hilarious scene] in the
third speech. There are also
'involuntary signs' which 'rout the
Logos'[disrupt his self control]. They
seem to belong to deeper feelings, like
offended pride, some' idee fixe' [obsession] ,
a certain pathos, demonstrated in his eventual
social and physical decay. Speech no
longer dominates communication, and we have
'aberrant transverse' forms instead, such as
in the initial encounter with Jupien [which is
wordless and involves them both exchanging
meaning via postures to show their sexual
tastes]. It is not just that the secret
lies in homosexuality, but rather that there
is some 'deeper universal madness inextricably
intermingling innocence and crime' [deep
anomie or egoism for me]. We discover a
world in which speech is not necessary, 'the
silent vegetal universe'.
If the Logos is an animal offering animal
unity, the pathos 'is a vegetal realm' with
indirect communication among its isolated
elements, a world of fragments,
'schizoid universe of closed vessels, of
cellular regions' (113). 'Contiguity
itself is a distance'. This is the world
of sex which the speeches teach us about, a
world of [queer] combinations between men and
women, and their male and female parts [ten
possible combinations for Deleuze], unfolding
after considering at first the most orthodox
combination of male men and female
women. Starting with the orthodox is
apparently found elsewhere, producing new
series which become in their turn 'a new
galaxy… decentred or eccentric', new
fragments and transversal connections.
This is how we learn about de C—first the
connections between ideas, voice and speech,
then a more disturbing world of signs and
cells. One example of the unity of this world
is provided by the disturbing picture of de C
being followed by a series of hooligans and
beggars, as if he is somehow producing them.
For Albertine, the galaxy of girls explains
her first, then a series of jealousies, then
the complexity, 'the coexistence of all the
cells in which Albertine imprisons herself in
her lies' (114). The narrator 'starts
with Albertine's face', and its components as
'a mobile set' [so some agreement with Guattari
here], and as he closes in, he sees a series
of different Albertines. Here, it is
still 'the law of loves and of sexuality' that
provide for compositions and later
decompositions, both hetero and homo.
The two series then display a transsexual
universe with a number of regroupings 'along
aberrant transversal lines'.
Conventional sex has 'a surface normality',
but queer sex is marked by sufferings and
anguish, 'what is called neurosis'.
However, at the vegetal level, essence returns
within decomposition, apparent madness
absolves itself and becomes a human comedy
with a new power. The search itself
unites normal and mad elements.
Although there is a general law uniting
Albertine and de C, their madnesses are
different. First, de C. has an
overdeveloped 'imperial individuality' which
makes us think he must be hiding something
that he is unable to communicate. We
discover this only by 'violent accidental
encounters' as de C is forced to enter new
risky milieux. Albertine has a different
problem, struggling to become an individual in
the first place amid a group of young girls:
the 'mystery of her individuation' (115)
is the topic, and it can only be grasped when
her communications are disrupted, and
Albertine herself imprisoned. De C is 'a
master of discourse', leaving him with a
problem with involuntary signs which can
disrupt his speech or even contradict
it. Albertine is capable only of simple
lies, operating with a view of language which
simply expresses things or objects, open to
manipulation only through lying.
Psychiatry of the time distinguished 'two
kinds of sign - deliriums', associated with
paranoid interpretation, or 'erotomaniacal or
jealous' demands. The first began
gradually, reacting to external forces that
eventually became a general network which
produced 'the series of verbal
investments'. The second one was linked
to 'real or imagined external occasions' and
led to something being postulated about
specific objects, leading to 'a delirium of
action animated by an intensive investment in
the object' (116), the delirious pursuit of
the beloved person, rather than 'a delirious
illusion of being loved'. The first
disorder produces 'radiating circular sets',
but the second 'a succession of finite linear
processes'.
Although Proust did not apply this work
specifically, we can see de C and Albertine
following these two paths. It is clear
that de C is a paranoiac, at the centre of a
network. Albertine is herself an object
or in pursuit of objects, even when imprisoned
by the narrator [the argument seems to be that
she can still see this as some kind of pursuit
of love without being loved]. The
narrator is also erotomaniac and jealous, open
to the 'constellations of lying', not de C's
'delirium of ideas and interpretation'.
Albertine's and the narrator's behaviour are
confused - the narrator is jealous of an
Albertine who is herself jealous of the
objects [women?] she is trying to
attain. His erotomania directed at her,
is interrupted by her erotomania [towards
women]. He imprisons her, and this
prevents him from realizing her demands until
it is too late. The narrator and de C
also get confused in the process of
interpretation. These both offer
'partial identifications' and the problem is
to decide their function.
We have to distinguish the narrator and the
hero, since the novel is not just a matter of
realizing subjectivity. The narrator
actually represents the 'machine of the
Search' (117) the hero is merely an effect of
the arrangements of the machine. The
narrator - hero 'does not function as a
subject' [very similar argument in Kafka --
an initially split subject is replaced by a
machine] . Proust constantly presents
the narrator as incapable of seeing or
perceiving. He has no origins, not even
a conventional body, 'no organs, or
never… those he needs, those he
wants'. When he kisses Albertine for the
first time, he says that 'we have no adequate
organ to perform such an action that fills our
lips, stuffs our nose, and closes our
eyes. Indeed the narrator there is an
enormous Body without organs'. [I must
say I can't remember another reference
anywhere to this view that bodies or organs
are inadequate: it all seems to turn on one
paragraph in a 12 volume novel! When I
read it, it just seemed to me that the poor
lad was overwhelmed with sensations, and
couldn't quite locate them anywhere. Or
maybe, he was too polite to locate them in the
obvious place.]
Spiders also see nothing, perceive nothing and
remember nothing. They only receive
vibrations from the edges of their webs,
producing 'an intensive wave' in the
body. Spiders 'answer only to signs'
[there is an odd bit that says they are
'without eyes, without nose, without
mouth'—doubtless, literary licence].
They search through a web structure, and each
'thread is stirred by one sign or
another'. The spider and the web
together constitute a machine.
Back to the narrator [!]. The narrator
'has no organs insofar as he is deprived of
any voluntary and organized use of such
faculties' [he's not a character, ya prat! If
only he had read some later stuff on the role
of the narrator in realism]. It is faculties
that function within him, awakening an organ,
as it were, 'as an intensive outline roused by
the waves that provoke its involuntary
use'. Sensibility memory and thought are
involuntary, reactions 'of the organless body
to signs'. This machine, the body and
the web, 'opens or seals each of the tiny
cells' touched by the search [its 'sticky
thread']. The narrator has this strange
'spider body', acting as a spy, policeman,
jealous lover or interpreter, and even madman
or 'universal schizophrenic'[hasn't he
discussed this better through the notion of
indirect free discourse?]. Universal
schizophrenia defines and describes the more
specific psychoses of de C and
Albertine. He sends a thread towards de
C or Albertine, 'in order to make them so many
marionettes of his own delirium, so many
intensive powers of his organless body, so
many profiles of his own madness'(118).
back to Deleuze page
|
|