Notes on: Maton
K and Muller J ( 2006) 'A sociology for the
transmission of knowledges, http://www.KarlMaton.
com [NB a version appeared in an edited
collection, but Maton says that the published
version was changed. I actually had
downloaded it from Academia.ed]
Dave Harris
Bernstein went on to develop an interest in the
structure of knowledge as a move away from
analyzing pedagogies, and this shift to discourse
meant a reconnection with 'systemic functional
linguistics'. Early Bernstein work on codes led to
a more 'formal analytical concept' of code as'" a
regulative principle, tacitly acquired, which
selects and integrates meanings, forms of
realizations, and evoking contexts"'(2).
This replaces the usual interpretation of the
early work on elaborated and restricted
code. Bernstein was always reworking his
ideas, aiming to make new objects 'visible' for
subsequent research, and then looking beneath the
empirical features to uncover structuring
principles, including codes, then even further
discussion of what generates the principles.
Ultimately, there is an interest in social order
and symbolic control, and its links from macro
structures of society to individual
consciousness. One path can be traced
through this work.
Any linguistic or symbolic ensemble can be seen as
linked to its social bases, as 'a material social
form of life' which produces various kinds of
ordered and disordered language. Following
Durkheim, it was the economic division of labour
and the link to forms of social solidarity that
produced different symbolic forms. In class
based society, symbolic resources are differently
valued regulated and distributed, and sociologists
need to understand how this occurs, and through
what mechanisms, as societies reproduce and
change. This explains pedagogic relations
and the connection to changes in the knowledge
bases of society.
Initially, the key concept here was code.
Originally, codes differed in terms of their 'more
or less complex lexical, semantic and grammatical
features', their linguistic repertoires (5), but
this was developed to refer to an orientation to
meaning, with codes leading to different modes of
communication. These would be valued
differently by schools, partly because they
differed in terms of their effectiveness in
relating to school values and practices [not
analyzed as related to domination as in
Bourdieu?]. Thus a restricted coded
orientation limits people to context-specific
meanings because it has a direct relation to the
social base; elaborated code orientations offer a
more mediated relation to the social base which
'predisposes that person to universalistic,
non-local, context independent meanings', which
implies a more specialized context [latter
requires security and cultural capital?] .
These qualities become important in modern
societies with a specialised division of
labour. A principal transmission takes place
through homes and schools, 'but not all homes and
not all schools for the same degree', hence class
differences. This provided an early connection
with systemic functional linguists, and helped
move away from the idea that code is not the same
as dialect, nor the same simply as middle class
speech [although this was how the work was often
received]. Bernstein acknowledged this link
to linguistics, especially through the work of
Halliday.
Further developments followed a more detailed
analysis of the elaborated code in the
school. Codes were not just possessed by
individuals, but became more general principles or
rules. This connected with the idea of
classification and framing, where classification
involves relations of power that regulate the
connections between contexts and categories, while
frames refer to relations within contexts or
categories. This is a distinction between
power and control, and it helps flesh out the idea
of the effects of orientations to meaning [for
example, there can be an invisible pedagogy in the
elaborated code, where weak classification and
framing leads to the concept of the person rather
than the individual specialist].
This has produced observational instruments
leading to empirical studies [some listed on page
7], and provides a detailed analysis of the
effects of various pedagogic modalities, and can
explain why particular groups operate in
particular classrooms and schools [as above, where
invisible pedagogy operates only with a fraction
of the middle class and is effective only in
correspondingly 'progressive' schools]. The
work has led to a difficult dilemma however—we can
change the structuring principles of the school to
match the codes already possessed by pupils, or
develop ways of providing pupils with the key to
the new code. The problem is that if we do
the first, we risk producing a subordinate and
lower status form of educational knowledge
specifically for working class kids [yes -- but
why?] while if we do the second, we imply that
there are two forms of knowledge and that the
working class kids lack the first one which would
be 'beyond the pale in much contemporary social
science'(8).
The idea of such codes can be applied to any
symbolic group, including work relations, although
schools remained as the major focus. The
struggle over invisible pedagogies can be seen as
a conflict between different bits of the middle
class, but what about the general issues that
shapes social structure? Here we need to
consider knowledge production and how pedagogy
recontextualizes it - the work on the pedagogic
device [nicely summarized in a convenient table,
below, page 9, and discussed more fully here].
Each set of rules is associated with a field of
activity, often associated with specific sites,
together constituting an arena. Again,
Durkheim appears on the major split between mental
and manual labour, and its 'corresponding symbolic
cleavage between sacred and profane symbolic
orders' (10). Again we have an argument
about how knowledge is produced and transmitted,
and what the consequences are for different social
groups, but there is also an implication for the
evolution of society, social reproduction and
change: conceived as '"an arena of struggle"' over
the pedagogic device (11).
[So there does seem to be some underlying class
struggle here despite what Bourdieu says?].
Those with power can set the device to favour
their own code modality [the actual wording here
is slightly different, though, that they can set
the device 'to make sure that the dominant higher
status code modality favours their own'], which
will put less dominant groups at a
disadvantage. The question therefore becomes
the classic one of asking who rules the pedagogic
device [still not quite whose code?] and who can
impose a hierarchy on code modalities. In
this way, the pedagogic device runs from macro
structures of power to individual consciousness,
an 'attempt at beginning a grand unified
theory'(12), something at a higher level than
codes - codes are 'the effects of the device'
(13).
[The higher level of abstraction is celebrated in
terms of a formula, 13, which I have not
reproduced - basically, orientations of meaning
are embedded in classifications and frames, in
stronger or weaker ways. Again empirical
research becomes possible [one of them includes
Singh]
The pedagogic device itself was to lead to a
broader analysis still of the issue of knowledge
itself. For a device to be necessary means
we need to further analyze pedagogic discourse and
the forms taken by knowledge. The term
knowledge is often treated without being
analyzed. Educational analysis tends to
represent 'an "over-ideologized" image of
knowledge and pedagogy'(14', seeing the only role
of knowledge as to produce inequalities, so that
all that we can understand knowledge only in terms
of the perspectives of the knower or the ruling
ideas. It is true that relations of power do
affect the production and reproduction of
knowledge, but the 'internal ordering of symbolic
forms' is also important [the point that Foucault
was to discover right at the end of Archaeology of
Knowledge]. Otherwise, education
becomes merely a tool of ruling ideas [see also
the reservations on this by Bowles and Gintis in
their follow up,
and the subsequent work by MFD Young].
We need to look at pedagogic discourse and its own
specific effects, the relations within it, its
intrinsic features, those things that make its
specific in education. The concept of code
takes this for granted, and the pedagogic device
only showed how discourses were put together,
without focusing on the forms of that
discourse. The field of the symbolic
production of knowledge had been relatively
neglected. Bernstein even thought that
focusing on pedagogy was not sufficient to examine
current '"discursive culture"'(16). We need
to examine which knowledges are being produced and
distributed, and how they might shape
consciousnesses.
Again, Durkheim on the symbolic was useful.
It related both to the social base and to
specialized activities of consciousness.
Elaborated codes did not just offer more
combinations of terms. Schools subjects do
not just reflect immediately particular forms of
knowledge. Bernstein moves on to look at
discourses and knowledge structures [SIC].
The work begins with distinguishing horizontal and
vertical discourse. The former referred to
everyday knowledge, working with a segmented
structure which is context-specific and dependent,
joined together in functional ways related to
everyday life. Vertical discourse was
explicit and systematic, and so more coherent and
hierarchical [Pask's
knowledge structures!], featuring
recontextualization between general and specific
levels. This difference improves on general
'conflationary' definitions of knowledge (17),
found in psychology and in common sense.
However, actors can move between the two in
practice. The real value lies in
understanding social structure and the difference
between specialized symbolic positions in a
division of labour. It is not just a matter
of differences between concrete and abstract
thought, or local and official knowledges.
[There is a strong implication that vertically
organized knowledge structures are more valuable
and better rewarded, and that these are also
differently distributed?].
Vertical knowledge structures are seen best in the
natural sciences [the first of a series of
idealizations, sometimes explicitly based on
Popper], which occupy a triangular form, with the
most powerful integrating propositions at the
top. Horizontal knowledge structures offer a
series of specialism languages and truth tests, as
in the humanities and social sciences - the
perspectives in sociology would be an
example. Hierarchical knowledge moves by a
principle of internal development, extending the
base and sharpening the tip of the triangle,
explaining more empirical phenomena via
integration in increasingly economical ways.
Horizontal knowledge continues to accumulate new
languages. [Shades of Piaget now?].
Horizontal knowledge structures face challenges
from intellectual fashion, although they also
feature similar focuses and some repetition.
It is difficult to build on knowledge. They
lead to 'epistemologically different
understandings of the world' (20) and also offer
[similarly diverse] practices, pedagogies and
specialisms, while vertical knowledge structures
operate within the same agreed language [we are
going to get to Kuhn
before long!]. There is knowledge the
operates in World 3 [explicit Popper here],
objective knowledge not confined to subjective
states, and this has properties of its own.
In particular, it cannot be reduced to
ideology. Knowledge can still be
hypostasised [and put to the purposes of the
powerful], but it is a visible object with its own
properties and powers: those emerge from social
practices but are not reducible to them.
[There is a bit of a weasel about whether the
abstract qualities of such knowledge are simply
heuristic, helping to make knowledge distinct from
social practices for analytic purposes].
This latest development also raises a host of
questions, especially:
(1) Whether these
distinctions are too clear cut, especially when
attempting to describe actual intellectual
disciplines. The characteristics of
horizontal knowledge in particular look as if it
is subject to constant change with no
continuity, but if this so there would be no
intellectual field. Accumulation of new
languages does not always cause a crisis in the
older ones [we definitely need Kuhn here].
However the issue is whether greater abstraction
and generalisability arises rather than a return
to themes that have been already addressed but
with new assumptions and languages. The
different perspectives in social sciences are
the result of different languages, even if they
use the same terms such as social class or
patriarchy, and this will limit
'development'[23, clear value judgement
here]. The issue also turns on whether
social sciences can progress as natural sciences
do, and here, two particular characteristics of
knowledge structures become important, their
'"verticality" and "grammaticality"'(23).
The first one relates to developments through
integration into more general propositions:
there is some work in linguistics apparently
turning on the technical qualities of language
'especially grammatical metaphor', specifically
relating to mathematics enabling progress in
science.
(2) The importance
of grammar or conceptual syntax [seems to be the
same as the above?], and whether they can
develop precise empirical descriptions or formal
models of relations. A 'stronger' grammar
can relate alternative theories [a
tautology?]. More than one theories do
exist inside a vertical knowledge structure, and
there may be conflict, but theory choice is
different -empirical research can resolve choice
if the grammar is strong enough [not at all what
Kuhn argues!]. New theories are both in
conflict with and commensurate with existing
ones, and a successful theory must explain
everything that its predecessors did, as Popper
argued [and Kuhn denies - Newton's theory of
gravity, for example did not explain the precise
nature of the force better than its predecessors
in one of his examples, and nor did oxygen
theories explain more results than phlogiston
ones, I recall]. Horizontal knowledge
structures have no such agreed empirical test
and can only work with critique, a different
form of conflict and conflict resolution 'in
which the strength of grammar plays a role'
(24-25). Bernstein goes on to argue that
economics, linguistics, logic and maths are
horizontal, but have relatively stronger
grammars and so can make intellectual progress.
Theory choices based on notions of 'consistency
and compatibility with other theories (their
internal strengths of grammar) and their capacity
to explain the results of empirical research
(their external strengths of grammar)'(25). This
produces a choice based on 'integrative,
subsumptive and explanatory power', or what Maton
calls a 'knowledge code', based on the relations
with knowledge and objects of study. Any
other changes are deemed to be 'ideological rather
than rational', based 'more on a "knower
code"', based on the status of who is making the
claims.
These distinctions could be clearer [they badly
need modification according to recent work on
science!]. They still remain at the
metaphorical or suggestive [highly idealized]
stage, without underlying structures.
Sociological relations are also important, and 'a
discipline is more than just its structuring of
knowledge'.
What is the relation between these knowledge
structures and educational knowledge?
Knowledge structures have to be recontextualized,
if they are not to be just another version of
pedagogic codes. The framework might be
developed to consider such relations in the
future, and here notions of knowledge changes
might be useful - for example, the subject of
English might be structured 'in ways that often
debilitate the integration of already learned
knowledge', and express an invisible pedagogy
rather than making knowledge structures visible
(27). The relations between knowledge in
general and curriculum structures also leave a
'space for the play of ideology' in any
recontextualization, but recontextualization
itself might be limited by the structure of
knowledge as a material basis: Bernstein already
argues that evaluative rules are artefacts, but
still must bear some relation to parent
knowledge. This again might be explored in
the future, and there is some useful linguistic
work to assist. There is a final problem of making
Bernstein's emphases consistent, combining
integrating and collection codes to educational
knowledge codes. Maton (2007) is on
the case.
[The conclusion offers a neat summary of the
article, emphasizing the broadening focus of
Bernstein's work, tracing school knowledge
'upstream towards its epistemic sources'(30), but
insisting on differential distribution and
acquisition, a key part of social
reproduction. There is finally an interest
in epistemic communities which persist over time,
as in mathematics, as offering a 'pure form of
communism', (31) apparently as Merton
argued. Here, a knowledge structure seems to
have generated a knower structure or scholarly
community. Bernstein wanted to develop a
similar one for sociology, attempting to move
beyond just accumulation to get to the principles
that would enable the building of a vertical
knowledge structure persisting across time, and
connecting sociology and linguistics].
back to ed studs
|
|