Notes on: Guattari, F. ( 2013) Schizoanalytic
Cartogrphies. Translated by
Andrew Goffey. London: Bloomsbury
Academic.
Dave Harris
[The translator says this is particularly
formidable in terms of its jargon, although he
attempts to justify the use of this jargon.
If you have played your way into Guattari, say
with Machinic
Unconscious, or Psychoanalysis and
Transversality, the jargon is not too
bad, at first, but then it gets really baffling
and bullshitty, when it gets on to detail
The increasing use of the terminology of popular
cosmology {including 'chaos theory'} could
either hint at the real ontology here (as DeLanda suggests
), a bridge with modern science -- or be classic
'fashionable nonsense'. There are some really
irritating diagrams and figures, most of which I
have ignored here. The subheadings give some idea
of the irritating neologisms and general
bafflement. They seem part of the obsessive
classifications and endless purely formal
possibilities that haunt bits of the earlier
writing.
If Guattari draws a diagram with four boxes he has
to fill all 4 -- and then if one is subdivided, so
must be the others. The clarification of the
differences is then required. Then further
categories to explain any remaining contradictions
-- and so on. It is simply out of hand, and
can only be a sudden onset of academic neurosis
affecting a person admirably interested in real
politics elsewhere.
This was written after ATP. It
explains lots of the emphases in Anti-Oedipus
I have struggled manfully to make some sort of
sense out of this, no doubt at great cost to the
subtlety of the original. Irritatingly, there are
some insights here, so you can't just bin the
whole thing. But Jesus did he need a decent
copy-editor! Did the translator survive?]
Preliminary
Classical thought often operated in dualisms,
between soul and matter, subjects and bodies, or
bases and superstructures. However it is
obvious that modern subjectivity has been
produced, by machinic systems, including databases
and mass media. Even those who believe in
subjectivity as some sort of essence are beginning
to doubt. While access to data has been
democratizing the opportunity to elaborate this
data has been closed down; planetary access to
different cultures has also produced particularism
and racism. There is no point in lamenting
this situation and returning to something
premodern and transcendental.
Machines can indeed articulate statements and
record facts at great speed, but they are not
diabolical: they are 'hyper developed and hyper
concentrated forms of certain aspects of human
subjectivity' (2). New alliances between human and
machine will develop, as machines are able to not
just represent but contribute to new assemblages
of enunciation, and as machinic systems in all
domains support 'protosubjective
processes'—'modular subjectivity'.
We can see much earlier social formations as
machines affecting subjectivity, such as 'monastic
machines', or the machine at the centre of the
court at Versailles which had produced a
particular 'aristocratic subjectivity' in a way
which submitted much more to royal power.
Neither history nor sociology is adequate to
explain these processes. We should pursue
the French homophone which joins the notion of a
path and of enunciation, and see these apparatuses
as producing subjectivity through a series of
voices or pathways— (1) of power, including direct
coercion, 'panoptic hold' (p.3), and domination of
the imaginary; (2) of knowledge linking
subjectivity to 'techno scientific and economic
pragmatics'; (3) forms of self-reference and
'processual subjectivity' [related to the notion
of group subjects]. These voices mix together.
They require a schizoanalytic form of elucidation,
rather than anything structuralist or even
genealogical, because there is no universal model,
and all models are valid to some extent.
What they do is to map out existential
territories.
This means that 'there is nothing shameful about
this relativism', because whatever regularities in
stable configurations that arise do so from
particular modeling systems, voices and pathways
[especially the self referential ones which
underpinned theory and philosophy]. Logical
discourse is only a distant relation of these
'discursive chains-- of expression and of
content'. [NB 'discursive', meaning
structured like a discourse, is finally defined
formally on p.172, {well, non-discursive is
--substitute 'without' for 'with' in what follows:
}-- '[with] extrinsically circumscribed
reference...[with] part-part or part-whole
relation[s]' . The non-discursive is the opposite,
with a different series of 'internal'
connections]. Stabilization can be provided by any
ideology or cult as long as it generates
existential materials. Expressive chains do
not just signify, denoting external states, but
rather enact 'existential crystallizations'
(4). Some of these then claimed to be based
in classical reason and its categories, including
the individual, causality and so on. These may in
turn help self referential subjectivity, but they
have been produced by 'radically
heterogeneous...elements, lived experience,
particular refrains, transitional objects, even
fetishes. What has happened is that some of
these regions and modes have become singularities,
'existential stamps' that collect contingently
associated states of fact and assemblages of
enunciation.
The process of singularizing also implies
transversal consistency, but with a local
persistence. Traditional forms of discursive
knowledge can never grasp this. We need to
think about it in terms of affects, although on a
global scale. The 'ordinary moorings of
sense' now include 'virtual, incorporeal
universes' (4), in the most contingent way,
including a whole areas of uncertainty,
probability, the aleatory. Classic
rationalism attempts to systematize these
processes, but only by ignoring major elements of
them, in the form of a 'quasi militant
ignorance'. We can see this with
anthropology claiming to have found categories
that were prelogical, but which were really
'metalogical, paralogical', working to stabilize
particular assemblages of subjectivity. We
can see these processes of work on a continuum,
from children's games, through social rituals, to
the efforts to consolidate the world of the
schizophrenic. The processes obviously
affect theology and philosophy as well [where they
appear as undiscussed foundations or mechanisms].
For investigating subjectivity, there is
particular need to see how the self referential
voice relates to the other powers and knowledges:
it is the key to producing human realities, and it
is also the most singular and contingent, and the
one that displays maximum transversality. It
is not universal, but the best one able to
process different 'universes of virtuality'
(5). Voices of power and knowledge had an
external referent that grounded them and limited
their sense [the Earth {ie territories} and
Capital are cited here]. In contrast, the
body without organs [hooray!] lacks any organs of
self reference developed in this bounded way, and
is thus the source of 'continuous emergence of
every form of creativity'.
We can use this three part approach heuristically,
to criticize the emergence of ideologies like
neoliberalism, but also to begin sketching a
cartography of subjectification. There is no
claim to identify universal structure or
foundation: apart from anything else, these voices
have not always existed and may not exist in the
future, but are localized in flows of history,
emerging because they possess a particular level
of consistency. Clearly, their persistence
also depends on mechanisms to store data and
knowledge into memory and construct particular
technical and scientific orders. This in
turn requires both apparatuses and new materials,
new machines, and even new biological
technologies. Again these should not be seen
as material infrastructures, but more a list of
components that are necessary.
The current configurations emerged in 'three zones
of historical fracture' (6): the age of European
Christianity which involve new notions of the
relations between human powers and the earth;
capitalist deterritorialization of knowledge and
technique, developing 'generalized equivalence';
global computerization, which might generate a new
'creative processuality'. The latter remains
only a possibility, but if subjectivity is to
achieve its full capacity, it will only happen
through this particular voice/pathway.
Innovative social practices are also required
obviously, and together we might finally achieve a
more permanent form of subjectivity, unlike the
'crazy and ephemeral spontaneous effervescences'
of the past [including Spartacus and the French
Commune!]. A new alignment of human beings
and their machinic and natural environments could
be possible.
The age of European Christianity
A new figure of subjectivity was produced in
Western Europe [post-Rome], featuring a 'double
articulation'(6), towards both autonomous
territorial entities, like nations and ethnic
territories, and a particular deterritorialized
notion of subjective power. Unlike Islam,
Christianity wanted to develop not an organic
unity between the two but rather a '
deterritorialized Christ' (7). The two
produced a new 'metastable equilibrium' which
included a certain partial autonomy for the
particular spheres of feudalism. The result
was both aesthetic creativity and the development
of technology and commerce.
Specifically, a subtle kind of monotheism was
developed capable of adapting to particular
subjective positions, including even barbarians
and slaves. A flexible ideology like this
seems to be necessary at all stages of capitalist
subjectivity, leading to the consolidation of the
religious stance combined with 'the predisposition
to the free circulation'(8) of knowledge, money,
technology and so on. Secondly a new religious
machine based on parish schools; thirdly bodies of
crafts skill and monasteries and acting as Data
Banks for the management of subjectivity; the
development of forms of natural energy leading to
artisanal and urban mentalities', nested within
the bigger assemblages; the emergence of
particular machines such as clocks and religious
music; the selection of animal and vegetable
species permitting growth.
Threats came from Arab imperialism and from
barbarians and nomads, but Christian culture was
relatively stable developing 'three fundamental
poles of aristocratic, religious and peasants
subjectification'. It both encouraged and
held back various machinic surges especially in
the growth of technology. The legacy of this
age appears in the 'paradigmatic
reterritorializations of the type work family and
nation'.
The age of capitalist deterritorialization
of knowledges and techniques
This began principally in the 18th century,
arising from disequilibrium between men and
machines. Social territories changed.
Capital became the new mechanism to
reterritorialize and develop a semiotics of
machinic processes. Two deterritorialized
classes developed together with a general
equivalence between goods and human
activity. History became a matter of
perpetual development and relaunching, in the form
of a '"capitalist passion"' (9).
The development of printed text became more
general, so did steel and steam engines.
Time was manipulated and cease to be a natural
rhythm, leading to techniques like Taylorism and
'economic semiotization', involving seeing human
capacities as virtual and developing a predictive
calculus; biological revolutions which will lead
to biochemical revolutions. The result was
an overcoding, from human 'adjacency with
regard to machinic phyla'(10) implying corporeal
modifications in the form of a
functionalism. Oddly, although
univeralistic, this sort of functionalism has
'folded back on itself', reterritorialized on
nations, classes corporations, races and so
on. Although enlightenment was possible,
profit was fetishised leading to a specifically
bourgeois power. The combination of
universality and localism has led to 'the most
obtuse, asocial and infantiIizing subjective
background' (11) for this group, appearing as
excessively individual responsibility and blame,
described nicely in Kafka.
The age of planetary computerisation
This is where a new machinic subjectivity
develops. New media become dominant, leading
to 'polyphony' combining human and machinic
voices, while public opinion becomes a matter of
statistical apparatuses and modeling, as in 'the
film industry'. New materials are produced
and new sources of energy: the issue is whether
these will never be harnessed by suitable social
assemblages. Data Processing has increased
enormously, and this has helped machinic
subjectivities develop beyond any obvious
challenges. Biological engineering now opens
the possibility of remodelling living forms, with
consequent changes in the ecological and imaginary
spheres.
The main question is why all this potential still
seems to produce only the old systems of
alienation, oppressive mass manipulation, a
consensual politics. There are still dogmatic
theories which claim to be able to break with
capitalism. Others dream of returning to the
past, and these now include Stalinists. Yet
others think that the havoc of modernity will
eventually bring progress. Some offer the
retreat to 'chronic marginality' (12).
A proper rethinking would focus on the
interweaving of voices and pathways as
above. For the third pathway, the creation
of new existential territories will be inevitable,
relating to 'the person, the imaginary and the
constitution of an environment of gentleness'. For
the second, collective and productive developments
must be retained as legitimate, as long as human
truths are reinstated as important. In
particular, there will be a need to emphasize 'a
fundamental right to singularity' (13), including
an ethics of finitude. Existing universes of
reference in politics and ethics must be extended
to include aesthetic universes, including the
tendency to rupture sense, engage in processes,
even at the expense of being incapable of
accounting for their own developments, risking
madness. The consistency offered by the
notion of developing self reference implies that
everyone takes on their own potentials, the goal
is to transform the whole planet from a hell for
most to 'a universe of creative enchantments'.
Of course this is utopian, but questions about
subjectivity are crucial. The Japanese
example shows us that the most modern capitalist
enterprises are still connected to 'archaisms':
Shinto Buddhism seems to have been suitably
flexible here in the development of the subtle
formula. In Brazil, archaic subjectivities
also appear today in a different way: substantial
social polarization is sustained by 'a somewhat
racist Yankee wave', expressed best in television,
combined with syncretic religions, inherited from
Africa, and widely spread.
The crises of Integrated World Capitalism are deep. It requires further self
referential subjectivity, but blocks it at the
same time. The old religious superego still
tries to recolonise. However the three
capitalistic voices and pathways vary in different
geopolitical locations. In the Christian
west, a transcendent centre is preserved, the and
development is extending even to the east.
However, the system is now saturated, blocking the
second voice of pathway. The third voice of
self reference varies according to a north south
axis, in a kind of new 'barbarian compromise'
(14). The older monotheism is no longer
adequate to develop a suitable subjectivity, and
as a result, even Capital is beginning to 'shatter
into animist and machinic polyvocity' (15):
ironically, the old neglected African and Indian
cultures might be more suitable for 'subjective
reappropriation of machinic self reference'.
The same developments can even be found in Italy,
with a combination of family enterprises and major
manufacturers of electronics: here, further
development might even depend on the old
subjective archaisms.
The issue with social progress turns on these
questions of subjectivity and its
production. There are no external
fundamental mechanisms, nor universal drives in
the unconscious—both these are myths, and
liberating pathways are possible. The
current massive domination of subjectivity by
'apparatuses of power and knowledge' have still
not squeezed out alternatives, and there is a
noticeable link between creativity and the old
notions of sociality. Other types of
subjective production are still conceivable,
especially those that are 'processual and
singularizing'. These latter may be the only
way to provide us with a reason for living faced
with death and entropy.
Chapter one Analytic cartographies
[Dense and obscure, but very insightful.
Takes a lot of decpihering. I have glossed as
usual]
The point is not to reconstitute freudianism,
although bits of it still useful.
Schizoanalysis is not just a psychological
process. Elements of it already exist in
other areas. We want to avoid a new
institutional foundation. The point is to
develop a discipline for 'reading other modeling
systems' (17), not as a general model but a
metamodel. Of course metamodeling is also
common elsewhere: any act of subjectivity involves
it in the form of transferring models between
problems of different kinds, another example of
transversality. The point is to think of
analysis in a new way, not so much working with
systems of statements and structures, but more
with assemblages of enunciation which can produce
new coordinates for reading and thus new
representations and propositions. This will
be 'eccentric' (18) compared with established
professional practices and institutions.
Instead, the analysis will be focused on 'the
impact of Assemblages of enunciation on symbiotic
and subjective productions in a given problematic
context'. The context can be any particular
existential or coherent set of references,
themselves 'a process of self organization or
singularization'.
Thinking of assemblages of enunciation will avoid
existing concepts of the unconscious or of
subjectivity [not to be reduced to 'drives,
affects, intra-subjective instances and
intersubjective relations'], although both will
find a place in schizoanalysis. Some
assemblages of enunciation will not have any
semiotic, signifying or subjective components, or
even conscious components: we are moving away from
a 'problematic of the individuated subject, of the
thinking monad delimited by consciousness'.
The ensembles are always 'indifferently material
and/or semiotic, individual and/or collective,
actively machinic and/or passively
fluctuating'. These assemblages interact
with 'radically heterogeneous domains', avoiding
the usual categories and focusing instead on
singular becomings. Classical analysis only
looks at context in terms of its signifying
tendencies, but this should be seen instead as 'a
referent generative of pragmatic effects' (19) in
particular fields. The point is not to
establish signifying chains, but rather to look at
signifying mutations of all the registers in
question.
Some assemblages will be particularly valuable as
analyzers [as in Psychoanalysis
and Transversality] of the particular
unconscious formations in question. This
analytic assemblage can take the form of an
individual, like Freud; a social group [the
example is a subculture who can exploit the
potentialities of a ghetto]; more diffuse social
phenomena collective sensibilities or opinions;
some 'prepersonal practice' like a creative style,
another mutation that can [like all the
examples] link individuals and groups
without them even being aware of it. There
are multiple combinations as well.
Assemblages should focus more on the process of
formation rather than fixed apparatuses or
groups. There will never be a standard
schizoanalytic protocol, but rather a constant
challenging of rules, 'an anti-rule rule'.
Effects can either be to recalibrate analysis, or
even to produce new splits in formations.
These effects are precisely the analytic matter,
how assemblages offer each other solutions or
forms of administration, or masks. New
possibilities can arise even in context that
appear to be blocked, requiring further study of
relations of production and micro politics.
The notion of subjectivity that emerges involves
'a metamodeling of trans-Assemblage
relations'. There is no relation to a
conventional essence of a subject.
Subjectivity itself has to be established at
the intersection of various flows, of signs and
machines, sense material and social facts, and
transformations in assemblages themselves.
Such a notion is no longer confined just to human
territories. It implies further original
singularizations, 'becomings animal, vegetable,
cosmos... multivalent sex, becomings
incorporeal'(20). It is the 'abstract
machinic Phylum' 'adjacent' to humans, that
will provide these possibilities, something that
thinks for human beings. [On the phylum, try the
excellent introduction by DeLanda here]
It would be wrong to think exclusively in terms of
speech and direct communication, 'archaic forms of
enunciation'. Machinic channels are much
more important [not just technical machines but
also 'scientific, social, aesthetic etc.'].
These have extended and exceeded the old
territories based on individuals and social
groups. That communication was
'logocentric', and required mastery of particular
ensembles, but deterritorialized enunciation is
machinic and involves 'non human procedures and
memories' in the construction of various semiotics
complexes. However, this is not to impose
some evolutionary system on communication: rather
the point is to understand different modalities of
assemblages of enunciation.
Non semiotic assemblages include the
organizational codes of social insects.
Humans have similar systems such as 'those of
endocrine regulation' (21) which can also be seen
'to hold a determining place at the heart of
assemblages', as when self intoxication produces
endorphins which in turn can exaggerate things
like 'sado masochistic tableaux' or 'mental
anorexia'. Non subjective semiotic
assemblages are found in 'psychosomatic
tableaux'[Reich on 'character armour': 'stylistic character defenses that
we develop throughout our life, usually starting
before we can think or talk' -- see link].
Subjective but 'non conscientalized' semiotic
assemblages are found in human ethology, with its
interest in unconscious in printing, display,
behavioural hostility and so on [hence Plateau 11 in ATP].
This contradicts conventional psychoanalysis with
its emphasis on the Unconscious and human
language. Schizoanalysis would see this as a
reduction of subjectivity to a capitalist
context. However the productions of
subjectivity are important—it is just that they
need to be metamodelled in terms of assemblages of
different domains. Human beings occupy
unconscious domains of equal importance, found in
structures of representation and language, but
also in other systems of coding or tracing found
in different organic social or economic
domains. Subjectification, the establishment
of lived territory, will then 'only be occasional,
optional' (22). The same goes with the issue
of consciousness and the processes of becoming
conscious ['conscientalization']: if we are
driving a car, for example we have different
systems of, consciousness at different levels of
vigilance and attention. Certain forms of
machinic communication are also involved in this
example, so the overall assemblage of enunciation
also includes several levels of relations to
machines.
Schizoanalytic metamodels therefore map these
different 'compositions of the unconscious,
contingent to topographies', which involve in
connection with various kinds of social and
cultural formations. This can incorporate
existing notions of subjectivity and the
unconscious, but it will never reduce these to 'a
structural prototype'.
Consciousness and subjectivity
It is tempting to think of an unconscious at two
levels, absolute and molecular which has no
standard forms of representation by only
'asignifying figures' (22) [indicated apparently
in Freud's early work on dreams, where the symbols
were idiosyncratic and organized according to
their own logic], and the relative molar one which
has conventional representations. However,
it is important to avoid such a simple division,
found in both Freud and Lacan [unconscious and
conscious or id and ego, and the imaginary and the
real respectively]. Analysis of the
unconscious in neurosis has revealed an
accompanying hyperconsciousness [some standard
commentary about the subjective symptoms?].
Neurotics have both asignifying matter and
conventional representations with 'idiosyncratic
modes of conscentialization'(23). This
combination or assemblage should not be reduced
only to the subjective, partly because it clearly
indicates '"limit consciousness"' [eg extreme
forms of dissociation or catatonia]. It
follows that every enunciation can be both
conscious and unconscious, and the proportion and
intensity depends on assemblages themselves 'that
authorise their composite assembly,
superpositions, slidings and disjunctions'.
There may also be, operating 'at a tangent', an
'absolute consciousness... the absolute
Unconscious of a non-thetic self presence', not
involving the usual relations with the other and
with society.
Apart from avoiding binary divisions, we should
also avoid notions such as subjectivity or
consciousness considered as transcendental
entities unaffected by concrete situations.
In practice, the most abstract references always
'mesh with the real', as they encounter contingent
flows and territories. This opens them both
to historical and other forms of mutation.
Significations are not independent of the libido,
and Lacan was wrong to increasingly substitute the
signifier and its dynamics for the libido.
Sense-making can be opposed, especially passively,
to material flows including semiotic ones.
It can also originate with machinic fluctuations,
not just existing strata and static states.
This sort of process breaks with the usual system
of equivalences and fixed maps, at least as entire
assemblages (there may well be rigidity in some
areas of an assemblage, such as the way in which
the oedipal triangle is supported by the
capitalist field of production). It is more
interesting to look at those cases where
assemblages join together and develop
'metamodeling coordinates': junctions produce
connections, but not fixed constraints, and
connections can be weakened and decreased again.
[The example then ensues of a case where a singer
sufferers bereavement and as a result loses part
of the range of her voice. This apparently
shows the effect of several assemblages, some of
which exceed subjective understanding, 'the limit
of the person'. Enunciations of the past dominate
the present and restrict possibilities, symbolized
by the representation of the mother.
Treatment could have explored still further
blocks, but it is not always wise to do so, but
therapists should work in terms of an assemblage
of enunciation rather than just a lost object as
is classic. This particular case, the singer
was able to reorganise her assemblage and recover,
managing her superego differently: the experience
of bereavement was taken to be an alarm signal
rather than a fixed constraint, in a 'pragmatic
transformation' (25). This is better than
the usual negative judgement found in Freudian
analysis which might reawaken the old issue of
oedipal guilt and infantile depression.
Instead of a general social inhibition, we are
working instead with a singularization, affecting
singing specifically. Other possibilities
were awakened, including faciality traits
separated from the mother and the superego.
Apparently, this is rather like the way in which
myths work to manage the link between the death
triumph and particular Kleinian objects].
The functors [mappings between categories] of deterritorialization
Consciousness can be understood to work in terms
of deterritorialization as well as via the unity
of the psyche, which is a 'founding myth of
capitalist subjectivity' (26). Instead we should
think of processes of conscientializiation, as
existential territories become deterritorialized
and tangled. Subjectivity is restored in a
second dimension, 'energetic discursivation'.
There are four functors, F T Φ [pronounced
'Φ'] and U, each
operating in four domains, respectively flows of
material and signs, existential territories,
abstract machinic phyla, and incorporeal
universes, at least as they become brought to
consciousness ['consciential']. They operate
together [diagram on page 27] and together
configure subjectivity, desire, energy and
different modes of discourse and
consciousness. We can avoid any notion of
infrastructure, including bodily or instinctual,
any sort of determinism, especially if based on
need or lack, and any sort of behavioural
conditioning. [To avoid reproducing the
diagram, Φ and U are connected on the same
horizontal level through 'propositional
discursivity' {formal theoretical
discourse?}. On a horizontal below, F and T
are connected through 'energetic discursivity'
{driven by libido?}. The vertical dimensions in
the square are forms of deterritorialization,
objective between Φ and F, and
subjective between U and T. I fear there may
be much more to come]. The relations between
these entities is what is crucial, and the role
they play in the overall assemblage. It is
not a topology. The transformations are what
counts in the model, as the (classically
separated) orders traverse.
Everything will turn on the precise combinations
of the actual and virtual on the one hand, and the
possible and the real on the other [another
diagram page 28 -- again, Φ and U provide
actual and virtual possibilities respectively,
while F and T provide actual and virtual real
respectively]. The real and the possible are
arranged so that 'the reality of the possible
always has primacy over the possibility of the
real' (28) [necessary if we are going to
critically analyze and extend the concrete and
actual real]. We can also understand the
virtual functors as the 'integrals' of the actual
ones [not really sure about this, maybe the
argument is that changes in the virtual will
explain changes in the actual?]. In
particular the unconscious will be founded on
notions of deterritorialization.
Unconscious versus libido
Freud developed a series of abstract quantities in
order to make psychology scientific and thus
reject notions like the soul. The psyche
could then be seen abstractly, as
deterritorialized, not just as described
subjectively [phenomenologically in the usual
sense]. Despite the dangers, this did not
lead to reductionism, but offered instead a whole
series of new interpretations, equivalent to the
adventures of Dada or surrealism. Perhaps
the scientific schema increased Freud's creative
confidence. Certainly, associationism had to
be left behind in order to focus on 'the
unconscious processes of semiotic singularization'
(29), the so called primary process. A
neuronal model did persist, however, and this
produced a number of reterritorializations.
We can see this by examining his notions of the
libido and the unconscious.
The libido is both a processual energy, or a
static energy which restratified psychic
formations. Freud tried to explain these two
possibilities by distinguishing between object
libido and ego libido. However the notion of
the libidinal balance must be rejected, and a
notion of micropolitical choice developed
instead. Then, the libido can become
deterritorialized itself, and become an 'abstract
matter of possibility', involving a 'libido
phylum', the integral of various flows of
desire. Freud offered a
reterritorialized option as a flow of energy
produced by drives and organized in various
stages, always in opposition to 'entropic death'.
The unconscious similarly can be considered
differently. It is best seen as an 'ensemble
of lines of alterity, virtual possibilities,
unprecedented new becomings' (30). However
Freud saw it more as a refuge for the repressed,
constrained by the conscious or superego.
Jung continued to explore the former, but in a
limited way [thinking of a series of archetypes
and collective structures and complexes].
Later formulations in Freud were even more
territorial— a spiritual plane in a topology
devoid of content and exhibiting chaos; a temporal
plane displaying different stages of development,
which had the effect of domesticating the early
studies of child sexuality [by seeing it as a
phantasy rather than the result of actual
seduction], and which subjected the unconscious to
the ordinary experiences of time.
The object of desire similarly was initially
presented as something rich and ambiguous,
escaping binary logic, occupying a collection of
different subjects and sexualities, 'like a "knot"
of overdetermination'(31), a connection with the
unknown, revealing 'indefinite lines of
singularization'. Klein saw the object as
something outside the framework of the person,
partial in that sense, suggesting all sorts of
other connections with various becomings, but then
closed things off by suggesting a list of typical
partial objects which became 'normative landmarks'
on the individual's journey to normal genital
sexuality. This attempt to categorize
objects into good and bad ones affects Lacan and
the objet petit a as well. The
same goes with otherness. It got
reterritorialized as a quality of interpersonal
relations, and turned into a complex structure of
symbolic castration through oedipus.
The different approaches between Freud and
Guattari are summarized in a diagram on page
32. The attempt is not to form a new
scientific conceptual framework—indeed the
approach required will be 'similar to the
aesthetic disciplines'. Most psychologies
mix science and magic: there's nothing wrong with
magic which can provide useful maps of psychic
assemblages which are not so reductionist as the
scientific approaches. However, this is
readily acknowledged, and there is at all levels a
normal scientific 'deception' and a posturing
which is 'generally in painfully bad taste and
unbearably affected'.
In
practice, there are three sorts of articulation
between scientistic approaches and the applied
domain: ascetic pathways (following experimental
procedures, assuming perfectly defined objects,
establishing apparent laws, and often
associationist, and eventually leading to
behaviourism—largely abandoned, but still
appearing in the laboratories and textbooks;
'hysterical identification '(33) involving
mimesis of procedures rather than actually
attempting falsification as in Popper [sic]
(psychotherapy currently follows this path and
has developed a particular cast of initiates and
a body of doctrine, even though phenomena of
belief are still 'elaborate' (34);
'propping'(particular scientific phrases are
retained or used as metaphors). All are
reductionist. Psychology should not
apologise for its unscientific nature, but
rather identify the 'fundamentally illusory and
pernicious viewpoint' of scientism.
Indeed, science began by bracketing out anything
idiosyncratic or singular and developing an
approach based on a
'specific semiotic phylum', which simply ignores
the essential point about subjectivity. If
anything, science might benefit from reawakening
some of the subjective bases with which it began
[citing Merleau-Ponty].
Positivism remains as an obstacle to a proper
analytic approach, although it is still regarded
as a popular third stage of society as in
Comte. In practice, the three stages have
always overlapped, and even science producing
different forms of subjectivity, and even
science has not managed to dispense with earlier
forms [animist and transcendental are singled
out]. There must always be some underlying
perceptual scheme, some affects, imaginary
activity and representation, just as in dreams
or madness—different universes in different
modalities, as complex as each other even though
sometimes seeming banal.
Overall, the sort of rationality that affects
science should also be subject to an analysis
based on a cartography of unconscious
subjectivity. Without this, the map of
science does not actually represent its
territory Cartography should replace formal
logic and discourse. This would
consolidate rationality rather than replace it,
extending existing logical definitions of
representation and the notation, and restoring
'ontological pragmatics' (35), connecting
'specific existential qualities'. There is
no universal away to represent this process,
because approaches like Klein's or Lacan's are
not universal: instead we should attempt to
identify 'crystals of singularization' (36),
specific points inside coordinates which are
capable of generating 'mutant universes of
reference'. These can no longer be
accessed immediately, although once they could
in animism or in certain ruptures with
normality. Instead we need to think about
'apparatuses of analytic enunciation from
scratch', which will be like artistic creation,
not just to extend psychoanalysis or art but to
attempt to establish a whole new degrees of
freedom, to overcome existing economic and
social constraints, to restore the proper
purpose of human activity, both collective and
individual.
From postmodernism to the post media era
People have lost faith with the notion of
progress, modernity and its connection with
emancipation, so social relations seem to have
been frozen, with no challenge from the
conventional sources. However, this does
not mean that nothing can be done, as implied by
post modernists. Postmodernism is really a
'final twitch of modernism' (37), an inversion
of its formalism. It is unlikely that it
will regenerate new kinds of painting [a
relaunch of the 'creative phyla'].
Architecture might be different. However
the danger is that capitalism has always both de
and reterritorialized, especially in attacking
traditional systems of value, and replacing them
with frameworks that are similar or similarly
functioning. What we have with
postmodernism is a drive to subjective
deterritorializing combined with an equally
strong impulse to reterritorialize, developed in
particular by the tremendous growth of
communication and information machines (so the
effect is to deterritorialize only the
traditional human faculties). Collective
subjectivity has failed to grasp this and has
become conservative: the only hope is that a
subsequent inversion of history and will lead to
new possibilities for emancipation and new
'assemblages of subjective production'(38).
[Some
postmodern architects are discussed, including
Venturi, seen as into reterritorialization as
above]. So is Lyotard right?
The collapse of master narratives for him has
led him to suspect any attempt at concerted
social action and developing consensual values
in favour of little narratives, the
'heterogeneous "pragmatics of language
particles"'. He has joined Baudrillard
in suspecting the very categories of the
social and political in favour of language
games. His earlier radicalism as when he
organized Socialism or Barbarism has
faded into a simple demand for access to data
banks. We are left with only 'erratic
clouds of floating discourse in a signifying
ether' (39). But this reduces the social to
the linguistic, and the linguistic to mere
signifying chains, exactly as in modernist
structuralism. All of these approaches
have been over influenced by information
theory and cybernetics, which have been
borrowed rather than understood.
Instead we need a focus on 'concrete social
assemblages'. These are not the primary
groups of sociology. They do not just
perform at the linguistic level, but also have
'ethological and ecological dimensions,
economic, aesthetic, corporeal, phantasmatic
semiotic components that are irreducible to
the semiology of language, a multitude of
incorporeal universes of reference' (40)
existing beyond the immediately empirical [not
a bad definition of the essence of
assemblages of enunciation here].
Despite the stress on pragmatics, it is a
structuralist conception of speech and
language that dominates, one that ignores the
'unconscious, aesthetic and micro political'
formations. As a result, this approach
depends heavily upon opinion and the trends of
the day, which seem self evident [my objection
to Barthes and his
new semiology]. It ignores the link
between any particular social development and
the 'desingularizing and infantilizing
reduction of capitalist productions of the
signifier', an illustration of Lacan's saying
that the signifier becomes the subject for
another signifier.
It may be true that the 'signaletic primary
matter' is increasingly produced by machines,
but this does not mean that human creativity
must inevitably become alienated: instead,
machinic networks can be seen instead as
processes of subjectification, leading to new
forms of creativity. Assemblages of
enunciation still demonstrate options for
subjectivity. The material of logical
discursive sets can indeed be referred to
external objects in standard coordinates, but
not that which arises from 'logics of self
reference...existential intensities'. We
might also call these logics 'logics of bodies
without organs', or logics of
existential territories. Their objects
feature ontological ambiguity, and relations
between objects and subjects that can not
effectively be rendered in discourse as
unambiguous figures in a system of coordinates
of representation. They cannot be
apprehended from the outside, but only grasped
existentially.
These ambiguous objects are transversal and so
can escape conventional constraints.
Originally, Freud grasped this, as indicated
in the early conceptions of
identification, transference, the phantasm
etc., but he then reduced the logic of the
unconscious into the 'logic of dominant
realities' (41), losing the specificity of the
discourse, especially the ways in which
semiotic segments broke with conventional
signification and produced new existential
conditions including neurosis. Lacan's
topography is also compartmental.
Some linguistics of enunciation have noted the
particular pragmatic effectiveness of language
apart from the classical notions of
signification and the notation, but did not
pursue the issue beyond their own
specialisms—to have done so would have been to
break with the boundaries around
language. Nevertheless, this shows how
language can escape from its own constraints,
by making 'pragmatic singularities
crystallize', bringing sensible territories
into existence. All other semiotic
components do this as well, including 'natural
and machinic encoding'. Capitalist
subjectivity emphasizes the linguistic
signifier as part of its programme to generate
equivalences and develop abstract values, but
studies of other semiotics systems can oppose
this imperialism, and restore 'the rhizomes
of realities and imaginaries'(42). We
have to construct the alternative, though, and
'no postmodern spontaneity' will do this.
The new information and communication
technologies have to be incorporated in this
programme. They can develop innovative
forms of consultation and collective action;
they can resingularize forms of expression
[I'm not sure I can understand how this is to
be done through the use of databanks or the
'miniaturization and personalization of
apparatuses']; they can develop an infinity of
'"existential shifters"' permitting access to
different creative and mutant universes.
This will be the post media revolution.
There need be no disengagement or withdrawal
into closed groups, but rather a new platform
for minoritarian groups more alert to the new
dangers of nuclear arms, famine, ecological
catastrophe, and the 'mass mediatic pollution
of subjectivity'.
Schizoanalytic meta-modelings
Psychoanalysis has many of the same
characteristics as the Christian religion,
with its own founding fathers, writings like
gospels, congregations, excommunication of
heretics and so on. Psychoanalysis has
attempted to absorb science rather than
rejecting it. It also requires more
participation among users and 'its myths are
more deterritorialized' (43). Above all,
psychoanalysis and religion both attempt to
grasp subjectivity and its ethics with
capitalist logics in conformity with
capitalist logics—'systems of judgment
proceeding by generalized equivalence, the
conjuring and repression of animist
intensities, the conversion of singular
trajectories' and the circulation of entities
on a deterritorialized market.
Psychoanalysis offers some initial freedom of
expression, only to take it over later and
subject it to stereotypes which are 'perhaps
even more tyrannical'. In this way, the normal
constraints on discourse are removed, and thus
the illusion generated that singularities of
desire might be expressed. However, this
only disguises the remodelling of
enunciation. This makes psychoanalysis a
secondary kind of religion, 'a religion of
pure form', constraining practices empty of
content, and upholding the freedom of
expression only in principle. Before
this expression goes very far, it encounters
'the apparatus of the cure', various rituals
and 'incisive interpretations' (44). These
seem to be neutral observations based on
listening, but this becomes 'ostentatious
silence and a cheap priestliness', a remote
form of control, that can even be internalized
by the patient. It means that the
patient feels it is all his fault, especially
if he rejects the official interpretations,
and then the cure becomes further examples of
guilt and alienation. Another analogy is
to see psychoanalysis as a kind of organized
tourism [sic], something programmed and
internalized, while appearing as freedom.
The enduring popularity of psychoanalysis
despite all its crises and internal problems,
arises because its practices offer a grasp of
mutant subjectivities and of variable machines
of enunciation to grasp subjectivity, but in a
particularly deterritorialized way.
Indeed, its popularity acts as a coefficient
of deterritorialization. It reflects the
classic 'double tension' of capitalist
subjectivity, developing deterritorialization
in one direction, away from the classic
subjective orders of childhood, family or
ethnicity, while reterritorializing in a more
functional way. This is functional for
capital because it tends to neutralize and
forbid 'processual singularities', promote
'the active ignorance of contingency and
finitude' and thus infantilize its
protagonists. [Same could be said of the
enduring appeal of Psychology in Education or
elsewhere]
This sort of subjectivity cannot develop self
reflection [rendered as is not 'the object of
an eternal return on itself', 45], but
develops a spiral of regression. It
recognizes itself in the myths of the media
and in 'pseudo scientific' psychological
references. Freud knew that adult
subjectivity was always accompanied by
infantile subjectivity, but did not realize
that this is the result of modes of production
of subjectivity, not universal complexes.
Television has a particular role here in
producing subjective figures, eliminating any
challenging singularity, and even based on
psychoanalysis. The media also combine
de and reterritorialization [so does
education!] in forms of enunciation, and
this produces 'ever more platitudes' and
superficiality. Mcluhan was right to say
that subjectivity is becoming as flat as
TV. Lewis Carroll produced a 'map of
flat affects in Alice in Wonderland'.
But psychoanalysis is the ultimate practice in
reducing signification and making 'affects and
representations equivalent' [ the emotional
impact of affects and representations as in
autoethnography?] . This important
function is what explains its continuing
popularity.
We need instead to do schizoanalytic
research. Psychoanalysis should not be
personological nor about intersubjective
representations as in oedipus. It should
focus on 'the meta modeling of pragmatic
models of submission to the modern systems of
"gentle" alienation and exploitation'.
It should not confine itself to elite concerns
and practices, but extend into modern
apparatuses of health, universities, the
media. these apparatuses become increasingly
dominated by supervision or 'theological
overcoding' to preserve systems of
normalization and blame at work in the
'collective psyche' via 'a multitude of
molecular relays'.
Chapter two. Semiotic energetics
[A formalised account of the elements and
processes that link them on what is sometimes
called the plane of consistency. The
elements inhabit the four domains we have
discussed above, with some additional
qualities. The processes involve new
terminology, such as the notion of a tensor
{roughly, a combination of vectors in an n
dimensional space}. There is also the
term 'noematic', which I first came across
when reading Husserl, roughly referring to the
qualities of a perception which can be
properly traced to the mental processes of
perception, as opposed to the 'noetic' which,
again roughly, refers to those qualities
perceived as belonging to the object
itself. The whole chapter is extremely
dense and schematic, and, unfortunately,
occasionally rather pompous. What
follows is my own gloss as usual, one which
omits an awful lot of detail.
The main issues seem to be: (a) signs are
linked to non-signs in semiotization or
discursivity, requiring two levels of
subjectivity or thought {the Unconscious} (b)
the consciousness can continue to receive
effects from the non-semiotized, and these can
also be internalized after semiotization as
affects; (c) there is a 'surplus value' of
sense in both pre-semiotic and semiotic
levels; (d) this enables a pragmatics of
innovation at the third level of thought]; (e)
there is a two-way flow between the semiotic,
pragmatic and pre-semiotic levels so
possibilities can be added, sometimes
'machinic' ones;(f) a complex number of
tensors link the levels, of different kinds
with different possibilities to combine or
separate, actualize or virtualize, and their
operations are not purely subjective nor
determined, nor arbitrary but depend on the
characteristics of the four domains, which are
not fixed either but open to influence from
the others]
The semiotic energetic is to replace the
importing of classic thermodynamic
notions. Would also replaces the base
and superstructure model which affects both
Freud and Marx, with libido and economic flow
as the base respectively. The result of
this model has been to think in terms of an
'infrastructure complex' (48), which has
reduced and reified anything inside the
infrastructure, making us incapable of
noticing movements and transformations unless
they are to be traced to some model of the
energy in the base. There was often a
thermodynamic understanding of energy
here. Only those 'givens' that could be
explained in terms of the base were to be seen
as reality, and the proper objects of science,
but only by reducing the inner dynamics of
those Givens. This also made the Givens
abstractly equivalent, reducing them to 'a
"capitalistic pulp"', omitting singularities,
the effects of representation, affects and
other combinations of energetic
processes. The approach ended in
structuralism or in system building, a further
kind of 'entropism' which applies a formalism
derived from the superstructure to the
infrastructure [seeing everything as a
language]. This formalism operates with a flow
of binary alternatives. The production
of subjectivity was then separated from
semiotics effectiveness, 'a cult of
information or of the signifier'(49), and
important issues were bypassed, including the
relation between what was given by the system
and forms of conceptual and observational
expression. This in turn led to have
very limited notion of choice available in the
'megamachine of the production of culture',
and clearly offered a suitable model of
subjectivity and expression to the system of
Integrated World Capitalism.
Freudian semiotic energetics
Freud
dabbled with scientism, perhaps as a
safeguard against the ruptures of sense
exhibited by neurotics. A basic
apparatus remained, involving an apparatus
connecting energy components and mental
representation, sometimes only as a
metaphor. Thus the first model of the
consciousness suggested the notion of a
somatic drive and drive energy, possibly
biomechanical, appearing as a series of
excitations, principally erotic ones, and
requiring a constant equilibrium to resolve
the tensions. However, there was
another psychic language involving object
representations, phantasms and
intersubjective relations with
objects. Psychic life was not entirely
dependent on the causal drives, especially
since the psyche can distort the effects,
through the famous 'displacement,
condensation, over determination,
hallucination…' (50). An
ambiguity remained concerning how the two
were connected, whether the somatic was
integral to the psychic, for example.
However Freud set out to explore particular
connections between the sexual libido and
the ways in which sense was made,
notwithstanding the more cosmological stuff
about the dualisms between Eros and Death
etc.
The second topography, id - ego - superego,
placed less emphasis on the energy metaphors
and more on 'anthropomorphic models'.
The final stage was Lacan and structuralism,
where the signifying chain virtually
obliterated any notion of the libido.
Indeed, libidinal flow became a mere 'organ
of the drive' [so another dimension to the
BWO], relating only to the incorporeal and
linguistic. They retained its sense of
energy, but denied that sexual energy in
particular was special.
The schizoanalytic unconscious
The term unconscious here stands only for a
field of schizoanalysis, much more than that
delimited in psychoanalysis, where it is
restricted to the idea of a particular
family based notion of subjectivity in
developed industrial societies, or those
manifestations that appear in the process of
a cure. There will be diverse means of
semiotization, no centring of
subjectification on persons, including the
analyst, a move away from conventional
'signifying interpretation' towards to
assemblages of enunciation. These will
produce 'subjective affects and machinic
effects' (51). These will deviate from
conventional 'stratified redundancies',
initiating a process, a problematic, an
'evolutionary phylum'.
This does not involve putting aside any form
of evaluation or any attempts to develop a
scientific analysis: any way, classic
Freudian analysis was hardly falsifiable
[another reference to Popper here]. It
will operate with different source of
energy, possibly with a distinctive flow
associated with distinctive psychic
operations, avoiding thermodynamic concepts,
including entropy. These terms are
fine in special assemblages of enunciation
had dealing with science and
technology. The point is that in other
conditions, the territories, universes,
flows and machines produce different
assemblages, which can also affect each
other. We need to map the
possibilities in developing a definite
'psychophysics'(52) not confine ourselves to
particular cases. There will be no
univocal energetic base, and no dualism
between inertia and subjective
animation. Heterogeneous domains will
be straddled as a form of transversality,
producing different modes between flows of
matter and energy; abstract machinic phyla
[that here provide us with 'objective laws
and changes']; existential territories seen
as acting for themselves; incorporeal
universes going beyond the constraints
provided by the first three domains.
It will be necessary to argue that
sometimes, the interactions do not lead to
equilibrium, but that they exist already as
'powdery metamorphic bifurcations at the
heart of the most apparently amorphous of
states'[unnecessarily poetic—why not just
call this the virtual level of vectors and
attractors etc]
There will be processes of quantification
[which I think involves something other than
the normal processes of measuring stuff]. We
will not think in terms of sets whose
elements have been predefined or collected,
but rather in terms of assemblages there can
show radical transformation, 'schizzes or
relinkages' (53), that can fluctuate,
reorder, even implode. We find these
assemblages in dreams and also in
'intellection in the nascent state'.
It is not that ambiguity arises from mere
fuzzy subsets, but is found on a general
plane of immanence, occupying 'different
levels of consistency of energy', with
notions of presupposition linking
them. The assemblages that are found
on the plane of consistency can be fractured
at different levels of energy [changes of
state in DeLanda's terminology].
However,we cannot delineate these entities
or their quanta of energy without
semiotization, and that would involve us in
various other complex assemblages of
semiotization.
This semiotics will not be confined to
conventional linguistics, but will take the
form more of its early conception 'an
encyclopaedic science of the phenomena of
expression'. It will also borrow from
Hjemslev and the notion of a
'glossematics'[a note explains that Hjemslev
and the others at Copenhagen have wanted to
develop a whole 'algebra' to show the
relations and presuppositions between
different semiotic 'magnitudes', going both
beyond current linguistics and even symbolic
logic, and assuming some inner coherence in
the material being analysed. There is also
this from the Wikipedia
entry: The
glosseme is defined as the smallest
irreducible unit of both the content and
expression planes of language...It is an abstracting form of
structuralism,
concerned with how "functives" describe
relationships among "terminals" rather than
with words themselves. This system,
constructed without recourse to any
particular language or constructivist
modality, seeks to establish a universal
standard defining the necessary and
sufficient conditions of language.More
detail is provided in a clear review by
Screel, available online:
it refers to Deleuze on the cinematic sign
specifically. For me, the basic point is not
how Hjemslev differs from other linguists,
but how his notion of language and the sign
differs from very commonsense conceptions of
the sign as some clear label or name for a
clearly defined thing as in objectivity or
realism-- ambiguity haunts both names and
things and the sign actually articulates
both, fixes the meaning of both content and
expression at the same time. For Guattari,
maybe, this makes his point that linguistics
which emphasise the signifier aspect of the
sign assume some fixed meaning or set of
connected meanings, irrespective of content,
and realism or objectivity does the same for
content the other way around].
Non separability, separation and
quantification
[Here we go]. Transversality cannot be
studied using the traditional coordinates as
in physics, but nor is it just a matter of
open playfulness and contingency.
Instead there are 'non programmed
potentialities', or at least potentialities
programmed by discontinuous segments or
'unforeseen smoothings and foldings of
possibility' (54). There also can be
areas which are stratified and structured
which look like conventional
homeostases. But these will not
control subjectivity as they did in
Freud. They have their place, but they
should be seen as frozen degrees of
freedom. Nonseparabiliy, separation
and quantification refer to three types of
semiotic energy:
Nonseparability refers to 'synchronic
correlations at a distance that make
different entities compossible'. There
need be no semiotic localization, which
means that the 'observer assemblage' is not
a coordinating factor. The general plane of
consistency contains instead 'tensors of
nonseparability' linking various
entities. They are located on an axis
of deterritorialization, from finite to
infinite. There is another dimension
to be explained later in terms of semiotic
content and expression.
Separation refers to transformations linking
entities over time, providing for a semiotic
component. These transformations may
produce different possibilities—'to exit,
discursivize, delocalise or detotalize'(55).
Separation is not just the opposite of
nonseparability, since there are no semiotic
dimensions in the second process, which is
self sufficient. Separation is a
possibility contained within
nonseparability. It appears on the
plane of consistency as vectorized tensors,
the result of either discursivity or
detotalization. These tensors may be
semiotic, producing entities available to
the senses—'sensible Territories, Diagrams,
Noemas and machinic propositions '[I'm not
sure why some of these nouns are
capitalised, but I don't capitalise them
myself in what follows]. There may
also be 'tensors of surplus value of the
possible', arising from changes in the four
domains above which can both relay sense and
produce pragmatic effects and subjective
affects.
Quantification refers to those relations
between nonseparability and
separation. These two do not interact,
but they establish 'sites of entities'
forming a level that will produce
'instances' that can possess energy in
conventional terms. These instances
will appear to generate conventional flows
like action and reaction. For this to
happen, assemblages of enunciation have had
to be constructed so that they can 'become
producers of quantification', acquiring a
particular point of view or reading capacity
that interprets entities in terms of
combinations of energetic flows [so
quantification here refers to metrication,
making extensive forces from intensive
ones?]. What this implies is that any kind
of molar quantified striation must
presuppose some sort of problematic at the
molecular level [a general principle of his
metapsychology he says]. On the plane
of consistency, quantification is revealed
as the projection of a particular ability to
discern quanta of deterritorialization
inside processes of nonseparability, and
quanta of discursivity inside processes of
separation [in other words help us see how
much deterritorialization or discursivity is
present in these processes]. This is
necessarily external to nonseparability
because there is no internal semiotic
potential. It would be wrong to see
these three qualities in some sort of
hierarchy.
We find quantification on the plane of
consistency in the form of 'synaptic
tensors'(56), having the 'quanta of
discursivity of synapses' of both effect and
affect. These will connect the tensors
of surplus value to particular 'entity
sites' found an apparent systems and
structures. This is another way of
connecting ['aggregating'] nonseparability
and separation, 'intrinsic' and 'extrinsic
reference'.
Overall, the plane of consistency has 'four
domains of consistency': F, flows arranged
in 'complexions', Φ , abstract machines
arranged as rhizomes; T, where entities
appear as cutouts; U, where entities are
arranged as constellations. Although
we think of this as a two dimensional plane,
it actually occurs as a folded
surface 'traversed by a complex line of
assemblages' (57). The line will also
be discontinuous since the tensors of
discursivity produce ruptures.
[Overall, lunatic obsessive classification
of abstract forms which will have to conform
to each other as we go along probably in the
form of ad hoc amendments and revisions].
The cartography of assemblages
We find contradictory demands in this model
of the unconscious. Each of its three
levels [below] is autonomous, but the
entities on them are related, through
presupposition and through various
transformations. Such relations
threaten the collapse of the levels, but
there are 'certain topographical
constraints'[purely in his model that
is]. In the first place, there is a
'principle of exclusion' which means no
direct relations between the tensors in the
four domains. Secondly, a 'principle
of dyschrony' means that the way the tensors
are vectorized will differ, according to
whether they are found on the axis of
deterritorialization or that of discursivity
[one difference is between a synchronic and
a diachronic dimension respectively.
The other difference is that one is
'bijective' and the other 'projective': Wikipedia tells us
that 'a bijection, bijective
function or one-to-one
correspondence is a function
between the elements of two sets, where
each element of one set is paired with
exactly one element of the other set, and
each element of the other set is paired with
exactly one element of the first set. There
are no unpaired elements'.
'Projective' might refer to projective
geometry as in DeLanda].
Thirdly there are principles of
presupposition so that the first level
[intrinsic reference] does not presuppose
any other, but the semiotic level
presupposes that level, and the pragmatic or
subjective presupposes both the earlier
ones.
The four domains of the plane of
consistency
[The four domains are F, T, Φ and U as
above].
Discursivity implies a particular argument
that there is both a given and a
giving. If there is a giving, there
must be 'unary values'(58) which implies a
particular discontinuity between given and
giving, which in turn means that there must
be some process of ontological appropriation
in assemblages, if only because it is
possible to say that something is either
there or not. This provides a certain
'concatenation' between entities, and we're
going to call them cutouts for T and
constellations for U. [Apparently
based on a Stoic concept] these terms imply
a mixture but not a total interpenetration,
and thus a preservation of the heterogeneity
of components. Plural values on the
other hand relate to the given, implying a
certain dimension of continuity, and a
'processual multiplicity in assemblages'
(59), as when we find a proliferation of
different species, and can notice
differences or even accidents. These
relations of concatenation will be called
complexion for F and rhizome for
Φ [so a rhizome here is a processual
multiplicity, an unfolding of potential,
some evolutionary development?].
Another Stoic concept [oh good] implies the
possibility of only relative delimitations,
or 'trajectories of becoming'[but only in an
evolutionary direction?]
The domains of given and giving are not
always tightly compartmentalized.
Non-giving can also be given in some systems
and vice versa. [Somehow] this relates
to Hjemslev and the notion of the solidarity
of the sign in semiotics, a union between
content and expression. For Guattari,
this union arises from a common plane of
immanence which will 'authorise'
various 'translations, symmetries and
reversions' between the terms.
For deterritorialization, there is a
cosmological argument, suggesting 'two
domains of intrinsic reference' (60) related
by either tensors of discursivity or
'assemblage synapses'[really obscure and
accompanied by a ludicrously complex
diagrams of the possibilities pages 60,
61. What this particular point seems
to be about is that there is a systemic
referent in the given, but a structural
referent in the giving, surely a fancy way
of saying some objective referent which will
be connected to a linguistic one?].
The axis of deterritorialization actually
has two segments as well: finite values
offer reversible relations based around an
equilibrium point, while infinite ones imply
irreversible drifting beyond any
equilibrium. [The possibilities for
discursivity and deterritorialization in the
four domains appears in yet another diagram
61]
Structures and systems of the primary
unconscious
We find here 'tensors of intrinsic
reference' [no semiotic as above]
(62), bijective and connected by a
continuous line. These seem to represent
fixed parts of the domain, inaccessible to
schizoanalysis [if I have interpreted one of
the ludicrous diagrams correctly, these
lines run from machinic rhizomes to matters
of content, and from constellations of
universes to 'existential matrices'. I
assume that these are inaccessible to
schizoanalysis because they simply arise in
the primary unconscious].
There are two types of tensors of intrinsic
reference, though: systemic, found in the
given, linking sites in F and Φ [the
only example I could grasp was of an organic
system operating ontogenetically, that is
machinically, to join together material and
energetic flows, with the junction mechanism
developing phylogenetically]; structural,
found in the giving, linking entities in T
and U [a musical structure can crystallize
incorporeal universes and their
actualisations in melody or rhythm].
The semiotic tensors of the secondary
unconscious
These are still tensors of intrinsic
reference, but they develop 'projective
vectors with a continuous line'. They are
not reversible but have points of origin and
points of arrival, the latter being 'a
semiotic entity'. They combine both an
'ontological ambiguity' and 'a surplus value
of possibility' which can be used in
pragmatic action. Here, we can
schizoanalyze the components, expanding or
localizing, enlarging or shrinking their
object, enriching or reducing expression.
Semiotic potentials are also conveyed in
various tensors: the two tensors of
persistence run from systems to structures
and may convey sensible contents within T,
through various 'complexions' of energy and
signaletic matter [these seem to be the ones
that also run from rhizomes to matters of
content]. These can also produce
'existential cutouts' that are not tightly
defined but have a certain potential or
possibility, not dependent on either subject
or object [the only example I can follow was
a totemic icon in an anthropological
assemblage. Other examples include a
refrain of territorialization in an
ethological assemblage] Another tensor of
persistence deals with noematic contents
inside U, running just like the other
tensors of persistence but this time ending
in 'incorporeal noematic constellations'
(63): these were also contain potentials and
possibilities produced by a particular
multiplicity with a particular kind of
duration [the ludicrous example here is the
Cheshire cat smile—pass. Apparently it
occupies all points in space, rendered by
this obsessive as having an absolute speed—I
suppose ideas or thoughts, noema if you
must, obviously have these characteristics.
[Readers will be as delighted as I was to
discover that] there also two 'tensors of
transistence' this time serving as vectors
between structures and systems. They
may be diagrammatic, produced as an
actualization of the contents of F.
Here, discourse moves from existential
cutouts [existential matrices in
constellations of universes] back to various
complexions of energy and signs. These
complexions again are not fixed but have a
potential for possibilities, as long as they
obey things like existing physical laws and
other physical constraints [the constraints
affecting the use of a credit card is the
example]. The other type is machinic,
involving an actualized 'abstract
propositional expression', running from
incorporeal constellations of universes and
existential territories to machinic
rhizomes, again awakening potential for
possibilities: they can actually exceed the
matters of expression [the example here is
the 'incorporeal faciality of Christ'
attached to all capitalist machinic phyla,
as argued in ATP].
Persistence and transistence of the
tertiary unconscious
Here we have reached a level of the
unconscious which is constituted by
pragmatic synapses of effect or
subjective synapses of affect. Here, the
synapses have to configure the various
processes of nonseparability, separation and
quantification, drawing on the potentials
found in systems and structures at level
one, and semiotic concatenations at level
two [so this is the machinic notion of the
subject? It considers possibilities in
objective systems and in linguistic
structures? In a kind of abduction?].
Effects are actualised and affects
virtualised, but this depends on the
particular nature of the assemblages at
work. There is no warrant for a
continuous and rational consciousness at
work. Instead we have 'temporal
schizzes and dyschronies' (65), fragmented
becomings. We also have efferent and
afferent synapses [working outwards to carry
effects to people, and inwards to carry
affects as in C17th notions of affect]—the
first one carries surplus value from
possibilities to systems and structures in
level one of consciousness, the second
relays surplus values to the semiotic
systems in the first place.
This [complex diagram on page 60] is only a
model, and we would expect to find a larger
number of synapses articulated in a complex
network of assemblages: the model is a kind
of ideal type [sic], representing the
'ensemble of capitalist productions of
subjectivity'.
Not only that, each synapse can have
valences [in sets of 2, 3, or 4] :
- 'Bivalent codings
and orderings' link two afferent
tensors. If they share a
consistency in F and Φ they can
produce 'an effect of extrinsic coding',
as in groundless perceptions like those
in delirium or hallucination. If
they have the consistency in T and U,
they can produce 'an aspect of extrinsic
ordering', like some lived impression in
aesthetics or dreams.
- Trivalent synapses
link two afferent and one efferent
tensor. If consistent in F, we
have a systematically closed effect,
like the conditioned reflex
system. If consistent in Φ , there
is a systematically open effect, far
from equilibrium, like those
dysfunctional micro social
systems. If consistent in T, there
is a structurally closed affect to
producing something like any ego or
superego. If consistent in U, we
have a structurally open affect, as in
becoming animal.
- [O god] There are
also tetravalent synapses, joining
intrinsic effects or extrinsic affects
with systemic or structural synapses
that may be either open or closed.
Combinations of effects and affects are
coupled or articulated, and must be if
an assemblage of enunciation is to
appear. These entities might be
located in formations preexisting
enunciation, and will need to be
established. However, whenever
effects persistently produce affects,
affect can become virtualised, and
effect actualised, 'virtual implosion'
and 'actual expansion' respectively:
neither eliminates the other totally.
Everything depends on 'a game of taking
consistency' (66). Consistency of
affect can occur at zero levels of
discursivity. If it does so, its
associated effects can also acquire
consistency [the origins of things seeming
'natural'?] . [in another kind of
consistency] virtual and actual affect can
'envelop' each other. There is no
difference ontologically between the
states. In particular, we should not
see the virtual as an unreal crystal of
possibility needing actualization before it
exists: the virtual aspects of the
unconscious are potential energies as much
as the actual energies studied by
psychologists. Nor can we retain the
normal hierarchies of thinking which have
produced different types of logic: the same
instances can be seen as elementary quanta,
semiotic operators and assemblage
quantification. It might seem like a
dream logic or an archaic one, but it must
also be seen as promising 'an era to come of
sign-particles' (67).
Chapter 3 The cycle of assemblages (first
global approach)
[Thick bullshit and obsessive detail
exploring formal possibilities. I can offer
only my own gloss expressing my own initial
understanding. I will have to return
to this as I read more expert commentaries
on what on earth this book is all
about. To give you an example of the
vulgarity of my gloss, I have rendered the
original bullshit: 'The unary
discontinuity of contingency T cannot
be simply articulated to intensive
incorporeal (non-discurive) multiplicities
U' as 'We cannot just map the
complexities of existence directly to the
theoretical multiplicities found in
U'. However, this makes it heavy
going, and sometimes my notes are actually
longer than the very brief subsections in
this chapter!]
If we operate with a two-term axiomatic
(such as Being /Nothingness), we will be
left only with a limited representation of
one term and an inaccessible ground.
Dialectics with three terms produce only
pyramids and trees. We need at least
four terms in a matrix [the inspiration for
Ettinger?]
Then we will be able to see new forms of
generation of entities, perhaps following 'a
principle of self affirmation'[69], or
autopoiesis [sic].
We can investigate models based on reference
to the outside [some determinate reality?],
using only the domains of flow, which will
give us 'discontinuous discursivity', or Φ ,
which will give us a 'continuous
"intercalary" discursivity'. However,
those metamodels based on something only
internally consistent ['endo-referred'] will
require considerably more heterogeneity of
dimensions and processes of singularization.
We cannot just map
the complexities of existence directly to
the theoretical multiplicities found in
U. A synapse is required as an
intercalation, arising from another kind of
machinic relations also found in Φ .
Nevertheless, the 'continuous' [meaning both
constant and joined together? ]
possibilities in both Φ and U provide
all the possibilities for territorialization
and contingency in actual flows and
territories [must do so, by our definition?]
.
Φ is a category of
discursivity
The usual (phenomenological) approaches to
discursivity seem to assume there is also a
discursive given. Some philosophy has
attempted to investigate non-discursive
giving. Science has attempted to
deterritorialize the given, but has not
developed the role of the assemblages of
enunciation. We have to rethink
continuous discursivity in the domain
Φ as involving the infinite
multiplicity of a state. What is given
then represents what appear as contingently
in territories [so actual as manifestation
of virtual etc].
Normal types of discursivity involve
sequential orders coordinated by the
conventional EST coordinates ['energetico -
spatial - temporal'(75)]. it can take the
mode of either a rhizome or parallel linear
chains. With rhizomes, we will expect
'knots and crossroads'(70), explicable only
as a 'machinic consistency'. With
linear chains, we will find heterogeneous
'clusters and agglomerations', separated by
levels and thresholds of
deterritorialization. Operators that
transcend [empirically, generalkize?]
these clusters will lead us to consider
constellations of universes of reference
'that refer us to the logic of bodies
without organs' (71) [presumably, seeing a
spatial potential which then takes
particular forms or stratifications?].
Rhizomes imply 'immanent machinic relations'
and linear chains 'transcendent machinic
relations' (71). Where machinic
articulations join together, we have a
problematic. We might then pursue
either interlinear compositions [the example
is a polyphonic multiplicity in Bakhtin], or
harmonic mutations found in enunciation [the
origin of things like metaphors and
analogies?]. Synapses are not involved
in machinic sequences [I can't see
why—surely they also have to be referred to
issues of universes and territories?
Maybe this is a 'pure' level requiring no
semioitzation? I think Guattari is raising
this is the question in the final piece in
this section]. This leaves the
question [indeed] of how machinism is to be
articulated [and] how enunciations intrude
into linear consistency [this is a gap that
could be filled by the classic subject, of
course. Isn't it what the politically
motivated have to do?] .
Φ is a category of exo-reference or
allo-reference
Discursivity involves memory, or something
machinic, which is the same thing. In
the domain of Φ we find whole 'chains
of machine memories', and it is this that
provides potential surplus values: we have
something more than just an addition of
components. Memory acts as an integral
for flows of pure discursivity, operating
not just with actual potentials but memories
of virtual potentials found in U, '(= the
point of view of all potential
enunciators)'—an echo here of Badiou on the
universal?]. For example, two particles can
interact and bring to that interaction 'all
the potential experiences in other
contexts'[actually rendered as some comment
about particles in the big bang]. We
should not see this as a matter relating
figures and grounds, for example,
[anti-Lyotard?] because F and Φ
operate according to different logics
[expanded inexplicably page 72], but
nevertheless discourse in machinic
propositions depends on the particular
operation of universes of reference.
Φ is a category of continuity
The domain of Φ includes 'all possible
pro-positions and trans-positions with
regard to "contingenced" states of
flow'. It is hard to see how we
can specify this process as producing
multiple possibilities working through
effects, compared to 'virtual affect', which
is 'enunciative virtualization'(73) [which
is what happens when you spell out lots of
possibilities at the formal level and then
have to think up the exact differences
between them. Are subjective
propositions the effects of machinic phyla,
or are they better understood as
universalized affects which appear objective
to new subjects?].
Φ is a proto-energetic category
It can transfer its effects in the form of
potential energy, both material potentiality
and semiotic. Energy
should be considered as transfers between
deterritorialized levels, and thus is an
integral of deterritorialization of the
discursivity of flows [the more energy,
the more discursivity in flows]. We
need a general theory of energetic charge
that allows semiotic effects '(the impact of
the sign particle)' to have real energy in
its effects. This will be part of the
general argument for a reversability of
entities, so that what was Φ can
become F, and T become U. [Classic
philosophical argument—if X has the
qualities we want, that must be because
something that causes X also has the
qualities we want]
Machinic diachrony and synchrony
We can think in terms of machinic
evolutionism in a 'mechanosphere' operating
diachronically and synchronically. In
the first case, each machine is linked to
other machines in the form of the form of
substitution or in terms of preparing
another machine for future use. There
is a rhizome of 'machinic
implication'. For the second case,
there is planetary integration, leading not
to one tyrannical mega machine but rather to
a 'powdery molecular machinic multiplicity'
(74) [why 'powdery'? Granulated,
dusty, contaminating every human?]. We
return to the issue of machines and
structures here, with machines carrying
surplus value and possibilities, while
structures are 'exo-determined,
passive'. Feedback is never
'innocent'[purely functional or neutral?],
since all feedback refers to a universe of
self reference, a proto subjectivity [that
is the ability to feed back indicates a
subjective capacity?]. These will be
subjects at various levels however, not just
the human—the organ, the cell, corporeal
memories and all assemblages.
There is also a machinic self consistency, a
matter of transistence, operating at
different levels. This gets back to
the issue of the relations between Φ
and U above. We can see this in terms
of a machinic plane of consistency in Φ ,
with a connected plane of immanence or of
self reference in U. However, this
will not be a universal plane of immanence,
but one specifically responsible for
existence.
Universes and paradigms
Kuhn's paradigms [sic] refer only to phyla
and not the link to constellations of
universes [an example of the criticism of
science above]. However, real problems
are like other living beings, but
operating in different coordinates.
Even so, there are not just the EST
coordinates, but other intrinsic and
intensive ones.
We can also amend the notion of a desiring
machine developed in earlier work. The
point there was to link effects from
signaletic matters [NB signaletic means
something that communicates but not by
signifying,ie not by being attached to a
signifier. It can have aesthetic. semiotic
or prxzsagmatric implications says Genosko]
or semniotizing] to subjective operations,
even the most deterritorialized ones.
Desire became a description of a particular
process, a line of deterritorialization,
seen as emanating from particular abstract
machines. However, we can now reframe
the issue in terms of 'problematics of the
production of enunciation' (74).
Flows and phyla
We return to the notion of flows and how
they turn into phyla. Flows tend to
smooth things out, by repeating them, giving
them an identity and thus producing linear
continuity. They also cut out
figures. They appear in finite forms,
usually EST coordinates. They carry
feedback as 'a memory of
smoothing'(75). Smoothing requires
'proto enunciation', but feedback requires
'proto machinism'[I suspect all these are
definitional. Feedback requires
generalization away from the specific
outlines of the case?]
We can consider flows as 'intensive
fluctuation', which will produce
'territorialized discursivity'. This
takes the form of a relation between primary
material, EST-based or signaletic; a
repetition of smoothed forms on a continuum,
or a form which is protomachinic; certain
operators that mediate both position and
retain these protomachinic forms:
positioning requiring both a process of
persistence or a 'memory of being' and
protoenunciation.. Fluctuations can take the
overall form of linking primary matter,
protomachinic forms and protoenunciative
substances. {no problem then -- we have
solved the question of how they link by
finding magic 'proto' qualities]
These links are best seen as a static form
of 'substantial {ie found in substances}
deterritorialization'. Another static
form involve certain relations of
expression: there may be 'autistic' (76)
relations, where the protomachinic form is
just determined by primary matter.
They can also be 'dialectical exhaustion'
(77) which emerges from the relations
between only the protomachinic figures [that
is something idealist?], and not from any smoothing
from flows of matter themselves [the diagram
on 77 this seems to have primary matter
largely derived from particular abstract
figures]. [Somehow] this will produce
a regrouping of smoothed components into
particular distributions among the functions
of content and expression [idealism sees
expression as determining content?] .
Expression itself takes the form of chains
of machinic phyla [only, no primary matter],
in the form of virtualization only through
enunciation. Territories can be
derived, linked to phyla subsequently, only
as a form of 'grasping' the implications
[uncritically applying the abstract terms,
as Hegel did when he applied the concept of
Reason to the actual Prussian State? See Althusser on the
circularity of humanist 'recognition']. This
is a static kind of 'expressive
deterritorialization'.
Assemblages of enunciation
We can explain deterritorialization in terms
of relations between the four domains. It
would involve a certain amount of smoothing
of flows as we develop protomachinic
smoothing into machinic phyla for
example. This will be part of a more
general process of smoothing and striation:
the latter produces all heterogeneity, the
former enables the transformation of
neighbourhoods between registers [cf zones
of proximity in ATP?]
. Both cases require a combination of
homogeneity and heterogeneity, opposed
alternately in both entities and registers
[as in a four by four table].
As examples, flows in F can be concatenated
in a way 'correlative' to a striation, the
generation of heterogeneity in the sensible
world. However they can be divided
into semiotic and EST flows through a
process of bipolarization, involving the
operation of smoothing machinic phyla.
Smoothing and striation are linked in the
sense that striations will involve vertical
smoothings of deterritorialization, and
horizontal smoothings of discursivization
[hilarious diagram 79]. The first one
involves the establishment of levels
operating between the possible and the
virtual [just another definition of vertical
smoothing really]. The discursive one
links F and Φ in extrinsic coordinates
[once we have made this link, we can
understand actual flows in virtual
terms?]. We still have to explain the
links in terms of 'a problematic of
energy'(80). Somehow, flows of expression
'"extract themselves"' from fluctuations in
sense data [terrible weasel] in the form of
machinic deterritorialization, and this will
energize the smoothing of flows. So
everything depends on the status of these
machines that can do this extraction [just
the repetition of the same abstract
possibility in different terms.
Basically, things have to be smoothed out,
or rendered less heterogeneous, in order to
develop relations between them, and this can
either be done in discourse or by some
process of deterritorialization operating
outside of discourse, associated with
machines].
Description of the first four phases
of the cycle of the assemblages of
enunciation
There are no simple models because in new
loops are constantly appearing in the
relations between the fields, as
deterritorialization and
reterritorialization expand.
Sensible smoothing: sub position
[Mystifying use of terms in physics such as
brownian motions and binary series, perhaps
to distinguish these processes from
subjective for linguistic ones]. In
brownian motion [taken as a simple
beginning] redundancies among entities
disperse, or become linear. This is a
way of controlling 'the aleatory chains of
the "primitive soup"' (81). There is
no clear line between these chains,
however. Nevertheless, generally
speaking the redundancy of an entity takes
place after it has been segmented: this
segment is identified and then retained in
memory in order to be reproduced, in a
linear sequence. For persistence
['persistential consistency'] there
therefore has to be a structure to identify
and one to implement the memory of
redundancy.
Identifying requires location in a system of
relative coordinates, and memory has to be
divided into two levels -- [I think the
argument here is that the immediate memory
of the segment has to be replaced by a more
general memory that will help us actually
systematically forget the first link in the
chain]. This more general external
memory is required for calibration and
reproduction of deterritorialized
forms. It is not that the smoothing of
the segments means that the original
heterogeneous inputs have disappeared.
As we know from wave physics [!] we can
become aware both of the control exercised
by discursivity and the apparent independent
status of matter: both are required if we
are to alter and develop forms.
Matter, substance and form are not connected
entirely logically [actually
'dialectically'] and the earlier elements
remain to introduce innovation once the
process of developing forms has begun.
The instantial striation of flows: dis-position
What are the implications for heterogeneity,
once we have discussed smoothing at the
sensible level? Machinic smoothing is
internal, but there can be a process that
transcends different orders, a form of
expressive coordination of smoothing.
The forms of smoothing discussed above
depend on the process of segmentation, but
we can also proceed with a process of
'differential pinpointing that I will call
in-stantiation or the marking of difference'
(82). Here, flows themselves can be
heterogeneous and show quantifiable
differences—for example, they cannot all be
reduced to a digital form.
We have to remember that flows are striated
at the junction of discursive and
deterritorializing smoothing, the
'articulation of sensible qualities' on the
one hand, and the development of a 'register
of abstract qualities' as machinic
forms. The first is both discontinuous
and finite, the second continuous and
'trans-finite', featuring
'trans-ordination'. There are
therefore two kinds of heterogeneities, one
found in the sensible, the other at the
level of potentials. The first one can
be amorphous and linked to proximal
references only. The second is
protogenetic, opening up heterogeneity,
developing possibilities, but only if it
mobilizes all four domains [-simpler links
can be recuperated or made static?], using
all the qualities, all the forms of
striation and smoothing in the entire cycle
of assemblages. In this way, each
entity will involve having added to them the
qualities of all the others [rendered as the
'requalification' of the others]. Any
particular instant of a flow will requalify
both material flows and those internal ones
associated with machines: similarly, the
overall processes of machinic flows will
entail the requalification of instants of
flow [everything is connected to everything
else is usual].
The point is that the surplus value of
possibilities found in instances of flows
depends not only on any local redundancies
they may possess, but also a number of
possible dispositions 'before, after, next
to and beyond its actual manifestations'
(84), a kind of inherent mutation of
consistency which will produce smoothing to
permit further flows and also links with
machinic phyla seen here as 'fields of
possibility'. [This is 'adjacency' --
proximity to another domain with a smoothing
neighbourhood between?] .
Machinic smoothing: pro-position
Machines operate with striated flows, some
of which are found in matter, and others as
the result of human intervention.
However, machines are not determined by the
striations, and in this sense the striations
represent instance of possibility which can
be exploited in machinic smoothing.
This internal involve selecting
interactions, regrouping them, sometimes
disposing them as bipolar options,
especially between expression and content
[abbreviated hereafter as EC] this does not
imply that the only connection between
expression and content is a transcendental
one: almost any other connection is equally
possible. However they do illustrate
machinic pro-positions 'composed of
sign-particles' (85).
Machinic expression confirms consistency on
the differences between flows, permitting
these differences to be expressed in a
language. This releases a new set of
possibilities moving away from the original
contingency in the flows. This in turn
produces 'pragmatic effectiveness' of the
machinic pro positions, a 'machinic power'
able to requalify flows including
'retroactive smoothing'.
This is an example of the general logic of
the cycle of assemblages. Intervals
[the importance of the interval is also
clear in Deleuze on Hume and Bergson] are
introduced in contingent sequences and they
can be engaged in new constructions, a
matter of being processed to the nth
degree. In this way discursive
domains, potentials and universes of
virtuality expand continuously.
However, is not just a matter of expansion,
but 'rupture and rearrangement' are also
required (86). 'Ontological mutations'
are triggered.
For example, when sensible flows are
'substantialized' and internally referenced
[made subject to thought about their
internal qualities], 'linearized discursive
sequences' arise, and these allude to a
principle of immanence. Machinic
smoothing does not follow the nature of a
flow, but opens a new possibility and
permits pragmatic machinics, putting to
work...encodings and diverse modes of
semiotization'. Universes can also be
smoothed and in this case, a whole
'generalised and infinite opening' can
appear, escaping even discourse and
producing new kinds of self
referencing. [Examples represented in
a diagram page 87, taking the form for some
reason of triangles linking matter substance
and form.
Bodies without organs are not smoothed
because they the are not affected by
extrinsic relations, such as external logic,
and located between incorporeal
multiplicities and existential territories.
The particular form of smoothing that
divides into expression and content changes
points of view on what counts as being and
what counts as a fluctuation. So it
moves beyond proximal notions only.
This makes possible a new kind of
heterogeneity away from space and time—this
is what he means by 'pro positional or Trans
positional'. Instead of local
coordinates locating a point of view, we
have more general ones prospective ones, new
and original problematics, introducing the
'statistically unpredictable'. There are
still further developments of machinic time
in particular.
With the 'EC function' heterogeneity can
produce effects, registering heterogeneity
actively, placing it in a frame of reference
that can be prolonged, enriched and
developed as a capital. Changes of
state also imply changes of energy.
Particular signaletics become charged with
energy, producing possible encodings, as an
'afferent to evaluations' (88). These
initial and elementary levels of energy
operate as a minimal thresholds for even the
most complex assemblages of semiotization.
Before we can categorize, either with
objects or subjective components, we need a
point of view, as an
interaction. The EC split helps the
point of view amplify and multiply. We
come to realize that the connection between
signifiers and signifieds is
arbitrary. But there are still
connections not discussed in Saussure: the
signifier is not completely independent but
might reveal various machinic connections
between form and reference as in
diagrammatic operations [ same as the iconic
sign?]. However, even the most passive
forms of expression can become 'active sign
particles'.
We need to turn to Hjemslev. The
figures of expression are identical to the
figures of content in form, produced by the
same 'deterritorialized machinism' (89), and
this explains their overlapping and
interchangeability in semiotic terms.
We can easily see how machines can produce
assemblages of signs in the current era of
informatics and AI. Similarly, the
connection between flows of energy and
signaletic flows is commonly perceived [the
example is using a bank card]. However, we
need to see that it is the form of these
connections that produces energetic
potential, rather than the specific contents
of the signs or the qualities [eg electronic
or not].
Consider the example of the ordinary metal
key. Each specific key is an example
drawn from a 'continuum of forms', and it
has specific effectiveness when connected to
a specific lock. We can also
identified two 'limit profiles', two
diagrams [one for the lock, one for the key?
] outlining the thresholds of error.
The passage from incorrect to correct form
[which can be seen as 'a signaletic
catalysis']has implications for mechanics
and dynamics independent of the energy
required to make it work. Once
the device has been encoded, after
signaletic catalysis, the forms of
expression can relate back to actual matter
and energy—there is a 'EC machinic
smoothing' which can in turn released the
potentials of the phyla, so a mere
territorialized local flow gets requalified
and connects with potential. For this
to happen, we have to connect the operation
of the key and lock with 'deterritorialized
machinic propositions', and 'abstract
machines'[discussed below]. This is an
example of the extensions following from the
split between expression and content [I'm
not at all sure anything particularly
gripping is being described here—we are
turning the key, and then generalising away
from that specific mechanical operation to
consider machines and how they work as a
result of their own material qualities and
the ones that we add]. For this to
happen, there must be a common and 'correct'
form between the key, the lock, and the
limit profiles.
This form effectively changes 'ontological
texture' by joining heterogeneous key and
lock, within certain variations, and then
exploring possibilities, initially by
considering the limit profiles [more common
sense on stilts]. Smooth machinic
flows continually do this, joining concrete
and possible heterogeneity, enabling them to
connect entities. Another way of
saying this is that they connect extensive
coordinates with potential, and Endo and
relative ordinates. This should be
seen as a matter of energy not identity, not
an imposition of identity on being, not an
exclusive reliance on internal reference,
but rather 'deterritorialized constancy and
consistency' (90).
Rhizomatic striation: trans
position
So a known set of flows can bring molecular
and deterritorialized charges of
energy. But they can also be striated
in another way, developing the potential of
the heterogeneity. This is an
assemblage of enunciation that is properly
machinic.
When we considered the possibilities offered
by the key, we were still operating with a
restricted paradigm, a set of effective
profiles. We could explore this
paradigm further as we saw, but the
opportunity to do so is a bit unpredictable,
aleatory. Abstract machines by
contrast coordinate links with universes and
manage possibilities, according to the
degrees of deterritorialization they
offer. We consider this not as arising
from a bipolar EC split, but as a for the
development of a rhizome. This in turn
offers 'multipolar transposition of the
possible' to the nth degree as abstract
machines interact in Φ .
Take the example of the relation between
wasp and orchid [oh no], a 'complex sexual
machine' that benefits both. Two
heterogeneous components are connected and
this is 'crystallised deep in the genetic
codes' (91), affecting not only individuals
but the species. There is an
evolutionary dimension here involving
reaction with multiple elements from the
environment, a 'possibillistic phyla at the
most deterritorialized levels'. As
with Heidegger, being is not reduced to just
what is real, but now includes the possible
and the notion of what is necessary.
But machinic operators do more—they convert
possibilities into necessary effects, a form
of 'ontological production'. Reality
is a crystallization of this machinic
activity, 'essentially a machinic
product'. This is a new kind of
smoothing, one that involves a break
['caesura'], as incorporeal universes take
on substance.
This break is not like the extraction of
flows discussed above, since a particular
instance of a flow becomes detached from all
the others and becomes autonomous. Nor
is it like the EC relation operating on
striated flows which involves a process of
making explicit the heterogeneity of
flows. This break detaches autonomous
flows completely from any extrinsic
ordering, and regroups them as E or C.
Extensive ordering now becomes intensive
[follows from autonomy]. It is no longer a
matter of producing different points of
view, more the 'operational integration of
heterogeneous points of view' (92), an
operation which actually removes the idea of
an external point of view.
Instead of separating layers in flows, or
bipolarising them, universes of reference
are put in parallel to manifest flows.
They interact and overlap in all dimensions,
as rhizomes, producing 'knots of
effectiveness'. They therefore develop
hypercontinuity, preserved even in moments
of stasis, by retaining universes of
possibilities and compossibility. In
this, what was identified as a redundancy or
an entity in a flow can be requalified, or
repositioned compared to its position in its
current stasis. This will challenge
notions of identity and
identification. The full double nature
of sign particles can be utilized—they can
refer not just to extrinsic coordinates but
to intrinsic ones too; they may appear as
located in a system of invariance or
constancy, but they can now be seen also as
bearers of energy.
Intensive characteristics in abstract
machines are not just pro positional but can
now become trans positional as a well, not
only moving through a paradigm but operating
at the level of phyla, even crossing
phyla. They represent a deep structure
for manifest flows. This structure
does not just refer to simple external
objects, nor does it operate with
arborescent logic, or with mathematical
axioms. Abstract machines produce them
and they have no fixed identity, nor can
they be coded in the terms of science
[lovely pseudy bit here: 'as hard as the
diorite stelae of King Hammurabi'].
Abstract machines constantly explore and
rework variations and derivations in fields
of possibility [which is what he says he
means by trans positional]. Does this
infer complete anarchy and endless
interference? Luckily not, because
what is happening is the useful channeling
of various instance of flow, governed by the
principles of the development of complexity,
breaking with territorialization, and
developing singularities. This
increases the power of their effects, now
understood as 'the potentiality for
singularization, or, in other words, a
reduction of entropy'(93) [sounds awfully
like the elan vitale]. As an example,
the concepts of mathematical physics were
deterritorialized and then applied to
nuclear physics, with important
results. Machinic deterritorialization
is everywhere and can escape laws,
hierarchies and metrics. It has no
beginning or end. It is 'becoming
processualizing itself' (94) [it's
God]. It is the development of
heterogeneity into difference, a constant
development of new realities. It
singularizes but also hypercomplexifies
[handy!] And we will inevitably have
to explain how these two processes are
articulated [sigh!].
Abstract machine and concrete machine
Concrete machines appear to be clearly
defined objects with boundaries, governed by
the various functional imperatives in the
form of inputs and outputs. However,
the boundaries are actually arbitrary--
is a locomotive separate from its track or
from the social assemblage that runs
it? Social machines are also not
tightly bounded—technical teams link with
engineers and politicians [sounds a bit like
ANT]. There are many 'trees of
implication' to join them. We have to
think in terms of 'a machinic functionality'
traversing specific machines. This in
turn depends on flows and signaletic
systems.
It does not make a difference whether these
things are designed by humans, or other
living structures in evolutionary
systems. Signaletics and coding are
'not peculiar to man'(95). In this
sense, we can consider physical, biological
and chemical systems as expressive
strata. We are in some danger of
repetition [!] because we have already seen
that divisions into expression and content
can occur from the smoothing of flows—and
now we are seeing it as a machinic
function. The argument so far has been
that flows pass their effects into machines
and other incorporeals and territories, but
we can also see it the other way around [so
as not to be pinned down anywhere]
We can see machines as the things that
smooth flows, even though they are
themselves a junction of flows. This
makes them ontologically mutant: they
combine both territorialized flows and
deterritorialized phyla. When they
operate diagrammatically, developing
language, images, tracings, planes or
programs for concrete machines, they are
actually doing two things [evaluating them,
that is adding values?]. One process looks
outside [is 'exo-referenced' as before] and
deals with the material process, while the
other produces complexity, singularity, and
'existential consistency'.
We can see this by considering locks and
keys again. We can think of them as
having 'contingent, concrete, discrete
forms' with a kind of 'self enclosed
singularity', and also a possibilistic forms
across continuous variation, offering
'processual singularization'. The
latter process means that locks and keys
possess a 'continuist texture'; belong to
incorporeal universes where other forms and
profiles exist, possibly as a set, whether
'authorized' or not; permit 'pragmatic
calibration of the system' enabling us to
see which particular manifestations work and
then supporting them. All machines
have this double characteristic, offering
both simple heterogeneity and 'heterogeneity
of heterogeneity'[that is different sorts of
heterogeneity—what a pseud!]. The
passage from one to the other can be
understood as a form of repetition or
reproduction. Finally, singularization
is never ending [the example says we can
always specify things like location more
precisely by using more and more accurate
measurement].
Reproduction never ends, but we have a
boundary problem again. The example
above refers to reproduction at the
infinitesimal scale, where we can pin it
down by using sign particles. There is
another kind in Φ , often seen in
engineering as a function of the margins of
error or intervals between entities and
flows, 'mechanics in play' technologists
call it apparently. There are certain
margins that limit reproducible forms.
We see this phylogenetically with
evolutionary variation, and we can
understand this is as a control on absolute
[or 'solipsistic']
heterogeneity. All the action takes
place with molecular differences and we see
the changes from disposition to pro position
and then trans position. The infinite
does not fall back into extremes
singularization at the infinitesimal level
as above, but develops extraneously—'it
becomes productive of the possible and the
virtual' (97). [ With a further explanation
of the differences between
disposition, 'instantial striation', pro
position, smoothing via a biunivocal
relationship between flows; trans positional
striation in Φ , a general formula lying
behind concrete machines].
Signaletic machines follow this process of
'virtual deterritorialization' starting from
singularities. However concrete
machines operate with flows and existential
territories, and this helps them affect
molar fields of content [apparently
expression lives in molecular fields].
This is an important addition in operating
consistently with existential territories
and incorporeal universes, an important
'looping and inversion' found in cycles of
assemblages.
Back to rhizomatic striations, the 'bearer
of abstract machinism' (98). Some
correlated categories need to be
requalified. We have already seen a
change in ontological qualifications as we
passed from the manifest flows to more
possible its tick smoothed forms in
phyla. We can now consider one
particular stasis [a diagram on page 99]
summarizing the possibilities [I might even
reproduce it]. Smoothing offers a form
of ontological conversion, but striation
leads to 'processes of enrichment of the
possible and the virtual'. Smoothing
passively records the state of an
ontological mutation and capitalises this
state, but striations develop it, increases
the potential, the processes and the
intensities.
We need a bit more on how extensive
coordinates become intensive
ordinates. Result of this process is
that the machine ceases to rely on exo
coordinates. Whereas enunciation
before relied on discourse, temporalization
and energization, it now depends instead on
'non discursive self enunciation'. This is a
non discursive complexity. It occurs because
existential affects,meta models of
singularities and processes are transferred:
They cannot be modelled themselves.
Extensity produces a frame with an inside
and an outside and circumscribes entities:
this constructs relationships between the
object and its reference, like a figure in
the ground.
The abstract machine does not limit things
in this way because it transforms the whole
universe of reference, offering instead a
continuous system of variations of
dispositions and affectations: even if we
return to the same location, we may not
occupy the same extensively defined
site. Extrinsic coordinates were
autonomous and reversible, but intensive
ordinance are not reversible. The
extensive becomes the intensive as a result
of a process of 'negotiation' [like a driver
negotiates a bend is the example]
through concrete machines. This goes
through stages—breaking free from manifest
flows, and initially limiting the powers of
self reference, which becomes a matter of
quantity of intensity. The terms here
are non oppositional and non discursive,
unlike the binaries of structuralism.
Requalification takes place according
to 'specific rhythmic sequences' (100), for
example in the form of a refrain.
Between these sequences, there is a partial
opening to possibilistic phyla and
virtual universes that were not already
implied philosophical science fiction here,
like those descriptions of a consistent
alien world]. The combustion engine has an
obvious sequential process, but there's also
a less obvious phylogenetic one, mutations
'entailed' by the process of machinic
generation.
Energy can be translated in the form of
energetic discursivity taking on new
qualities as it is integrated into machines
sequences. Translation is only a
problem if we operate with static strata and
separate territories. If we postulate
'deterritorialized machinic knots' operating
across the whole field there is no need to
assume differences of potential to explain
transfers of energy: these will only occur
in a fully discursively limited and
contingent flow. Instead, we should
see relations between molar strata in terms
of 'the molecular play of charges proper to
sign particles' (101).
There is no general energetic charge, rather
charges associated with particular pragmatic
possibilistic effects. These are
'negentropic' . In quantitative terms,
energy changes at the molecular level are
smaller, but there are still differences
between them, 'by relative degrees of
deterritorialization'. The more they
are deterritorialized, the greater their
potential at the molar level—for example,
changes in the operation of 'signaletic
machines of mathematical physics' reached a
certain threshold and were then able to
affect the concept of classical
physics. We need to think in terms not
of a transfer of undifferentiated energy,
but rather of charged potential pragmatic
effects.This will help us grasp energy in
quantitative terms and extrinsic coordinates
on the one hand, and in qualitative terms in
fields of possibility on the other.
Later, we will discuss different existential
necessities as a relays of these charges.
We remain with the problem of differences of
degree of deterritorialization. These
seem to be neither logical nor the result of
quantification [just argued above]. We
need to bear in mind the links between
quantitative and qualitative dimensions
rather than develop general postulates
governing the exchanges between different
sorts of energy. We need to consider
negentropy in phyla as 'reservoirs of
potential effectuation' (102). They
will vary according to the 'richness' of
constellations of universes of reference,
and/or the number of openings provided to
machinic monads. This will also cover
the effects of phyla on assemblages.
Assemblages will be able to establish
transversal relations to external strata
according to their 'rates of
deterritorialization, irreversibility, self
consistency, self evaluation, self
enunciation'. Then we can call these
overall 'rates of inherence', and their
opposite, 'rates of dishrnce'found in
particular stases. These will imply
disjunction of conventional coordinates and
energy, and also the autonomy of purely
discursive chains of expression.
[Jesus! What a nightmare! Ended in a
migraine!]
Chapter four: reference and consistency
The chaotic plane of immanence
It is awfully difficult to use static
concepts to represent chaos, even fractals,
if the creation of chaos is its essence, as
it is with the '"primordial soup" of the
Plane of immanence' (103). This makes
it impossible to grasp and impossible to
subject to discursive logic. However,
there are processes that produce order [must
be as a necessary logical complement to pure
chaos], such as 'proto-fractalization' and
other forms of composition and
'complexification'. Nevertheless,
virtuality is essentially chaotic ,
inexhaustible, infinitely
determinable. There must be material
providing for these possibilities: for every
aleatory sequence there will be 'virtual
attractors of processual
complexification'[handy how it all works out
- transcendental deduction really]
We can call this a hypercomplexity, more
than ordinary notions of complexity [found
in flows and phyla] and also discourse,
which will occur as a self generating
process, discursivizing complexity. We
can call these filters. In other words
as well as combinations of order and
disorder, chaos also contains existential
operators and ways to manifest them.
We can define catastrophe [as in Thom?] as
the collapse of these discursive
filters. However, these filters are
often mutant, with incalculable
results. Comparing order with chaos
will help us focus upon the
'endo-consistency' between existential
territories and universes of reference
(104).
Within the primordial soup of the plane of
immanence, we find two sorts of relations—of
reference and of consistency.
Reference refers to the passive collectivity
of instants, both territorialized and
deterritorialized. It helps things
hold together, in the absence of any sort of
subject 'to hold together at all'. A
number of states that can be described as
'"there is"' (105) are connected. We
cannot decide if they are the same, but
there can be a process of repetition or
iteration, a process whereby 'something
stays in place by returning to it
incessantly'. This is a form of
constitution of states, and it is an example
of how 'existential glue oozing from chaos'
begins to underpin conventional spatial
order. Luckily, space is 'essentially
glischroidic'[I spent a while looking at
this term. Its origin is the Greek
term for viscosity, and it has a medical
uses in the definition of epilepsy], and
this does not necessarily produce subsets or
internal divisions. We have a notion of
existence as coexistence or trans-existence,
'existential transitivity' or
transversality.
We should not think of this in terms of the
usual notions of conventional interaction,
and think instead of action and reaction in
the particular context of related
objects. We need at least to think of
a multipolar structure. There is no
process whereby something passes between the
referring and what is referred.
Instead we have 'existential self
affirmation', and changes of state involve
no transfer of energy [since they are self
contained processes]. They also happen
at infinite speed, even faster than the
speed of light, 'a reference speed''
This in turn makes us think differently
about consistency, which is produced by
types of iteration, both of infinite speed
and decelerated speed. The latter can
also be called reterritorialization.
We can now use this notion of consistency as
a 'fundamental new dimension of
assemblages'(106), or at least those which
begin in chaos. We can also better
explain the differences between the four
domains. What happens is that infinite
speeds of reference transfer complexity and
hypercomplexity between Φ and U.
[Somehow], infinite speed becomes the same
as very changeable ['labile'] forms of
iteration and are thus at zero consistency,
while restricted speeds produced
reterritorialization linking T and F in a
process of 'existential "grasping" (or
self-referential agluttination) '. [He is in
SF mode, making it all up, and repeating
definitions in different forms of
words]. So deceleration brings more
consistency, and this in turn closes the
possibilities of opening up again. [Lower
speeds cool things down -- and vice versa]
Consistency is more temporal. It
expresses the qualities of connective
processes, how dense or precarious they are,
and also the sorts of transitions they
feature. We should not be misled by
particular extensive distinctiveness,
because this is largely contingent.
Things that appear as entities get their
arrangements and axiomatics from other
abstract machines. Only some have the
capacity to break with this connective
passivity and regain a more active
processual connectivity: this capacity would
depend on whether the [passive] consistency
can be fractured [all circular and
definitional again]. We have to allow
for such associations instead of using
binary oppositions [and one of Sartre's is
reworked page 107]. We will produce
'an open range of existential intensities'
instead. We can also break with
'ancestral myths' about the permanence of
being or even the conservation of
energy.
There is no 'brute form of being'
independently of assemblages that grasp it,
register its effects or change its
trajectory. 'Being is the modulation
of consistency', a matter of bringing
together and dismantling. If it is
cohesive and coherent, that is because of
the connection between processes of
'intrinsic consistency themselves'(107-8),
and nothing external or inherent. [And
here we have the same argument but
backwards] transversality requires infinite
speeds of reference and recursive smoothing
in processes which also implies striation.
We might consider the example of a catalyst
in chemistry. Enzymes can speed up
reactions by enormous factors. Their
action focuses on one particular aspect of a
molecule which it can recognise via a
specific filter. The whole process
shows a combination of smoothing,
acceleration and specificity of
effect. We can understand enzymes in
terms of the way or of losing ontological
consistency, a deterritorialization leading
to new possibilities. We can see the
fields of the possible in Φ and
'mutations of virtuality' in U, applied to
living matter.
Filters
The primordial soup of the plane of
immanence has two kinds of entities: chaotic
multiplicities and existential
filters. The first compose and
decompose complex arrangements at infinite
speed. Filters can be seen as 'hooks
for chaotic multiplicities'(109). The
two 'engender' each other and this provides
the combinations of reference and
consistency above : Filters provide a
relative stability and consistency, and
multiplicities provide assemblages with
hypercomplexity to re-energise them.
Chaos dominates wherever the dimensions do
not cross, and new entities arise infinitely
when they do. Both crossing and
uncrossing are found constantly together,
but sometimes one dominates: crossing
produces the possible, uncrossing
the virtual.
There are also different sorts of attractors
as filters, including circular or strange
ones, enzymes, genetic codes, even financial
institutions [weird -- these are just
'natural' too?]. Filters act as
interfaces between the virtuality of chaos
and actual potentialities. Everything
depends on how the dimensions are crossed
and uncrossed [tells us nothing
really] Reference in particular
depends on crossing producing a cycle of
assemblages. Consistency striates
Planes of reference [which are also
apparently immanent], but not binaries or
even distinctive oppositions. Instead
there are 'pathic categories' [lovely bit of
bullshit here: 'the pathic categories that
Viktor von Weiszäcker opposes to ontic
categories' -- brilliant name. Apparently,
he was a physician interested in
psychosomatic illness]. The first
apparently referred 'to willing, to power
and the diverse modalities of duty' [in
producing symptoms?] not notions of
conventional coordinates and
causality. This apparently was an
argument that subjectivity is 'the movement
of a relation to the ground' (110), but
Guattari sees it as the basis of existential
appropriation and existential transference
between T and U. [Only goes to show
that you can't just abandon the subject
without some sort of substitute of the
subjective process].
All this will eventually make sense as a
series of components of assemblages of
enunciation. They require both
absolutely deterritorialized null
consistencies and only relatively
deterritorialized consistencies.
Apparently this is rather like seeing a
quantum of energy as both wave and
particle. It is also like certain
psychotic symptoms, which feature both 'a
corporeal ego territory with a slow
consistency' and 'deterritorialized
universes associated with this territory'
referring to them, and yet with a much more
rapid consistency appearing as the 'truth
charges that delirium might harbour'.
We can operate at both exo and endo levels,
consistency of flows and phyla, and
'existential agglutination' [mysterious
magic process of the appearance of entities]
with T and U. The former give us
propositions and the latter dispositions,
potentials and instants respectively: either
may be grasped clearly while leaving the
other one fuzzy.
Proto enunciative processes
[Absolutely delirious obsessional science
fiction here, virtually indecipherable.
Largely repeats the main points above
anyway] . Filtering is more than just
'passive smoothing of powdery diversity'
(111), because an existential surplus value
is also released, requiring an assemblage of
enunciation to realize it as capital.
The four domains will be understood fully as
a matrix with more complex operators and
filters than just a linear ones we have been
discussing [figure 4.4 on page 112 talks
about synapses linking Φ and U, pathic
operators linking U and T, modules linking T
and F and ontic operators linking F and Φ
. They also link exo and endo levels
of consistency, with Φ as the most exo
and T as the most endo.] [Then he goes
completely nuts and refers to further
diagrams with loads of special terms, which
I cannot be bothered to elaborate.
Here is a very brief summary]
There can be rhizomes of abstract machinic
possibility, moving from N possibilities to
M characteristics [something more fixed and
ordered]. Each/some specific series have an
'enunciative guarantor' produced by
reference to elements in T. There are
however more deterritorialized lines which
have different sorts of enunciative
guarantors. Territorialized guarantors
in series and flows are modular, which
seems to mean firmly connected to
existential operators, unlike
deterritorialized guarantors of the kind
found in phyla. Those things that gain
an existence in phyla depend on 'mutational
filters' and because they are
deterritorialized they appear ubiquitous and
absolutely translatable. They take on
a contingent quality because they are
capable of repetition [not firm connections
to existential operators as above].
There is a form of 'modular
immanence'. For the whole thing to
work, infinite speeds at the virtual level
have to 'hold together'(112) with
decelerated speeds and make possible certain
'discontinuous intensive striations' at the
crossover—the continuous must envelope the
discontinuous and the intensive the
discursive.
Let us try and clarify the proto enunciative
processes at work in the very first stages
when entities emerge from the primordial
soup [some fucking chance!]
Exo reference/endo reference
In a given multiplicity, it is possible to
connect terms discursively, as a form of exo
reference, but this will depend on a serial
arrangement which can be considered as
endo-reference, something intensive and non
discursive, a 'proto existential
operator'(113) [same old transcendental
deduction]
Exo consistency/Endo consistency
We can have 'cold consistency, or a pure
passive territorialized connectivity, or...a
hot deterritorialized consistency'. These
[all?] display 'existential glue' which
links the exo and endo relations above, and
gives series a notion of 'existential self
reference'. They can also vary: exo
consistent domains open up new fields of
possibility in phyla following new
constellations of universes of reference
[not the other way around? Both knowing
him?] ; trans consistent domains feature
filtering and striations, mixtures,
crossings, catalysis and so on; endo
consistent domains with decelerated
flows. We need synapses to join the
excesses in a incorporeal universes of
reference to the existential levels.
This operates at infinite speed, that is
'with no ontological consistency, although
according to a principle of irreversible
necessitating (the pathic mode of
referencing)' (114) [fuck knows what that
means! Because somehow {human?} existence
depends on it? The whole notion of the
pathic seems to have been borrowed from this
original work on psychosomatic symptoms in
humans and then generalized into this major
philosophical category as some kind of
meaningful opposition to the ontic.
This seems a tad contingent to put it
mildly, and just smuggles the subjective and
human back in].
In the process of actualization or
territorialization [which seems to be what
this is about], exo consistency has to be
modified and made chaotic again. We
can apparently use this to explain what
Freud called the primary process,
'remanences of being' [ a remanence is
apparently that magnetic field which is left
behind when a magnet is removed] [looks a
bit like epiphanies].
Smoothings and striations
So far we have considered entities arising
from proximities [in time?] Of between the
four domains. However, we can use
assemblages of enunciation 'in a synchronic
fashion' (116).
Chapter five. The domain of flows
[This is the first of a series of
discussions of the processes and elements
inside each of the domains and their
interconnections. Luckily, the mad
elaborations and obsessive classifications
seem to be slowing down a bit, and there is
some repetition, at least of the basic
points, which is all that I am interested
in. No doubt the elaborate terminology
helps make allusions to sundry fashionable
theorists of the time, but for my purposes
it just looks like unnecessary bullshit.
The basic point is that flows have to be
stabilized in order to have an impact in
territories, take on an existence {I have
not retained the awful terms like
'existentialization'. which my speech
recognition software rejects}. There
are a number of ways in which this is done,
including different degrees types and levels
of smoothing, each with a different effect
as we shall see. The section ends with
a reminder that there is also a link between
flows and Φ as well as T, and that the
whole cycle has to be invoked in order to
fully realize the surplus value of this
connection]
The smoothing of flows involves a certain
degree of making them homogeneous, 'in some
cases indexed with intentionality'(117) [so
the subject slinks back in]. This can
be seen as a sort of grasping and it has the
same effect as the modularisation of
experience discussed above. We must
not forget the relation with Φ
however, which will provide new
possibilities for having an impact in T.
When different smoothings join, we can get
striations. This will look like
discontinuity from the point of view of the
link between F and T, as general
determinability is 'slowed down'.
However there can also be deterritorialized
consistency since there is always an
imminent [sic, but this is surely poor
proofreading and it should be immanent]
alternative, with connections to new
universes of reference or with underlying
chaos. It might even be possible to
say that there is always a double relation
here, but it will be important to avoid any
notion of essential or universal
connections. Instead, the relation
between adjacent realities, corporeal and
incorporeal, arises here from 'ontological
pragmatics' (118) some notion of becoming
necessary [which he claims he has discussed
before, meaning he has asserted it]. Such
pragmatics in turn requires the joint action
of 'territorialized proto-enunciation'and
'deterritorialized ontic operators (concrete
machines)', mutational filters or abstract
machines, and the 'pathic operators of self
consistency' (119)[—that is processes of
actualization in all four domains, the whole
cycle of assemblages. These all seem
to be formally required according to the
definition of ontological pragmatics in the
first place].
Purely at the theoretical level however we
still need to specify relations which both
exclude and yet co-occur, as with the
paradoxes of physics involving waves and
particles, tight determination and the
aleatory [this is because we are operating
at such an ambitious level that we want to
include theoretical physics, or is it just
that Guattari wants to involve the
terms?]. We also have the paradoxical
relations between expression and content,
semiotic and material, the contingent and
the universal, the immanent and the
transcendent. Finally we have
aesthetic and religious a-signifying
material which can still be found in
different forms of discourse.
The rhizomatic flows of Φ 'hang over'
flows both material and semiotic, but also
affect them at the molecular level. It
follows that there is no centre or absolute,
no overall law, but rather 'relative levels
of transcendence', itself contingent on the
action of different operators.
Sensible smoothing or sub position
If we consider the originary state of
matter, perhaps as a form of brownian motion
as above, then reference [a form of
connection or consistency defined above] is
universal and therefore non specific,
referring to everything at absolute
speed. We can understand this as
having a zero memory of arrangements in the
soup of chaos.
- The first stage [of
actualization as I call it] is linear
smoothing, where elements are connected
in a sequence as a form of blank
repetition, 'an empty form of' coming
into existence, with no implications for
content.
- The next stage is
stochastic linear processes [I looked
this up, and a stochastic process
appears to be one which has random
variation across a set of fixed
coordinates, like a meandering line on a
graph]. Here we have actual memory
of content, and possibilities of
relations such as 'symmetry, homology
and disparity', basic 'durations of
alterity': here memory is required to
develop qualitative changes and to
register alterity, but it does not form
'figural constellations'(121).
- That does not
develop until the stage of serial
smoothing, where the filters involved
get combined into a system of
evaluation, itself a product of the
enunciative possibilities found in
T. Here we can have a layered
memory, of events and of their layering,
linked together. The filters are
no longer passive registers of
regularities, but can actively reproduce
these regularities, by locating them in
a paradigm. These layered memories
can then regulate stochastic
linearity. [One argument for this
seems to be that random motion requires
such a memory if it is not to lapse back
into predictability]. Such serial
memory gathers more and more
associations and givens, and can develop
rhythms and refrains, introducing more
important regularities into
discourse.
- The final stage is
'sensible smoothing', where layers
acquire an extra consistency of their
own, developing their own enunciative
possibilities, becoming self consistent,
fully territorialized. This
process of consolidation also involves a
heterogeneity between serial groups, and
there can be an explicit comparison and
borrowing of their enunciative
possibilities. Here, serial
reference is consolidated into serial
consistency.
The existence of these stages is
simultaneous with the systems of reference
in each case, assuming 'infinite speeds of
determinability'. However, layering
can also be slowed down and become 'a series
of finite points of view'. Here, the
reference of these points of view to other
series is 'infinitely deferred'[rather
than completely lost] (123), and they can
return, however long it might take—this is
what constitutes the characteristics of
virtuality. Processes of
determinability continue but in the phyla
and the deterritorialized universes.
[I think this is quite an important way to
rescue the fundamental determination of
actual events, suggesting that it must
persist, but not always in the most of this
observable and empirical way, by linking
through the virtual for example]
So we have combinations of coalescence and
heterogeneity as serial determinations
become finite and limited. This is how flow
becomes 'a modular component of
enunciation', with combinations of
references and consistencies with various
levels of continuity.
The striation of the in-stantiation
of flows
Flows take an actual form as a result of
having limits imposed by a particular point
of view, even if this is an immanent one,
not from some inherent undecidable
quality. This limitation is actually
required if the full set of possibilities in
phyla are to be realized, especially their
'non discursive self enunciative
correlates'. New possibilities of
deterritorialization are implied, including
various logics that might produce 'molecular
intervals, amplifications, bifurcations, and
infinite fractalization' (124). Not only
that, the same series can sometimes be
found in different modules. This
will require further theoretical elaboration
[sigh].
The possibilities arise because distinctive
territorialized flows are both self
consistent, and open to alterity. It
is not that these are dialectically opposed,
more that they cross, and this opens 'a sort
of frantic slalom' to escape either
'petrification' or 'dissolution'[they're
alive!]. The agglomeration that is the
territorialized flow still possesses a
referential series which is potentially
infinite. The module [same as
agglomeration] uniting specific series and
the infinite referential series will be
affected by an attractor 'or phase space'
between modules. This attractor can
unify 'potential series of determinations',
infinitely so. We can therefore see a
module as a mere 'stopping zone', where
determinations are suspended (125).
This [new, magic] attractor can attract
determinations from non discursive relations
between T and U, and this itself implies
some new agglomeration coming into
existence, a new module or assemblage.
Here, we will find a 'territorialized
incarnation' of determinations that had been
virtual. It can also get
determinations from the discursive qualities
implied in flows. Here the outcome
will be machinic smoothing, those
possibilities that were not fully realized
in actual modules [maybe].
These new possibilities will then be
incorporated into memory, going beyond those
already coded as durations of alterity or
paradigm sets of serials. Thus the
attractor opens up new forms of qualitative
possibility which are not easily reduced to
quantitative description of flows to
[somebody called Ivar Ekeland there is cited
here] (126). It is another argument
for cartography rather than fixed geometry
or topology.
In this way, we have established that flows
are striated as a result of two sorts of
smoothing. One is territorialized and
discursive, because sensible qualities are
being articulated. The other is
deterritorialized and refers to 'abstract
qualities inherent in machinic Propositions'
[pro-position or Proposition mean something
special as we saw above] (127). It
follows that we have two types of
heterogeneity, a sensible one with specific
references, and another which is both
processual and proto-genetic. For the
last to be realized, we need a cycle going
through all four domains. This in turn
will involve 'over determination' affecting
each entity: again this is more than simple
determinism and quantification [it is also
described as an opening to or
'ad-vent']. Possibilities can remain
permanently, awaiting a particular
hypercomplex singularization to take on
existence. In other words, the
realization of surplus value also depends on
'a-signifying ruptures' of reality, beyond
even notions of the aleatory or random.
Overall, actual manifestations are only a
small part of what exists. Its
existence is contingent and localized, and
this in turn depends on all sorts of
'dispositions, trans-positions, catastrophes
and possible accidents'(127).
Chapter six the domain of phyla
[Usual problems here with terminology and
offhand references to some topological
procedures like the 'baker's transformation'
and 'homothety'—I have relied on Google for
a basic grasp. Overall, the problem is
to explain both absolute openness and
possibility, and the closed and fixed forms
that are also found in reality. We
have to explain both homogeneity and
heterogeneity, both stability and openness
to possibility. We do this by
suggesting that both opposing terms are
contained in the same particular forms: one
argument is going to be about content and
expression, for example, which will help us
explain how matter becomes 'signaletic'
leading to the elaborations in Φ and
U. I'm still not sure if it is at all
credible or magic—for me, DeLanda's
commentary is indispensable. As usual,
it is hard to decide if it is bullshit—just
when I do, I stumble across an
insight. I have tried to rendered
these in my own much simpler terms]
The problem is really to explain the
'ordinary consistencies and temporalities'
and their connections with Φ , where we're
going to find 'infinitely slow speeds of
separability and infinitely rapid speeds of
continuity' (129). We will need
consider the whole cycle of
assemblages. For the moment, the
problem is to move from modular flows and
explore their connections with possibilities
in the phyla. Modules operate
according to rather limited notions of
neighbourhood and distribution and this
makes them compact, but we find other
relations in the domain of Φ which are
not compact. In turn we will have to
account for determinisms which will not just
stick to each other in space and time,
operating not just with chronological chains
but other sequences, including algorithmic
ones. In Φ , we will find connections with
events that are very remote in time: there
will be a smoothing of time in these terms.
As a result, we will be able to consider
flow and transversability in a non
territorialized way, not just in F and T
where it produces layers or concretions.
We can think of two sorts of
determinability, intrinsic and extrinsic,
the first one found in modules, the second
involving serials migrating into
deterritorialized spaces and eventually into
Φ and U. In modules, a system of
reference connects entities with the same
ontological status, capable of being added
or subtracted. This is a form of
consecutive determination. However,
there will also be 'caesuras'[must
be?]. In extrinsic connection,
heterogeneous entities are connected.
We have to see connections in terms of
'discursive phase spaces, non discursive
enunciative basins'(130). An intensive
relation and a form of connection which is
not passive but 'actively disjunctive', a
way of generating complexity.
The smoothing of extrinsic
determinability
Modular connections offer a striation which
generates a sensible territory, by
aggregating different speeds [the speeds are
found in all objects, so that the most
objective of objects has a very low
speed]. However, expressive smoothing
aggregates speeds of a different nature, and
this becomes important. Separation
becomes a matter of
'"negative"determinability': this is
controlled by a particular phase space [I
don't know if this is a particular phase
space already identified elsewhere. It has a
name -- φ {also pronounced
as 'phi' -- this is the lower case form} ,
which Wikipedia
tells us might be the symbol for the
'golden ratio' -- 'an
irrational number with a value
of approximately 1.618033988 which
expresses the relationship that the sum of two quantities is
to the larger quantity as the larger is to
the smaller.' Or possibly 'Euler's totient
function, an arithmetic function
that counts totatives' {where a
totative is 'A
positive integer that is
smaller than or equal to, and coprime to, another
given positive integer.' ].
What can happen is that relations between
matter, substance and form can change from a
modular striation to expressive smoothing
[apparently illustrated in a series of
incomprehensible diagrams pp.
131,132]. What seems to happen is that
matter can now take on the consistency of a
formed flow and become 'proto-enunciative'
(131) at a particular threshold, and thus
take on an expressive function [can become
the object of something in a discourse or
semiotic sequence, or rather a potential
base for such discourses?] . It seems that a
formed flow is always [logically?
empirically?] associated with unformed
matter in a module, and that the stability
of this association is easily disturbed by
'the play of a little difference, the
intrusion of an infinitesimal
deterritorialization' [what others have
called 'trembling'] . This results in
a certain detachment of this substance from
the module and from a merely existential
status: it begins to 'work for itself
somehow' and initiate a whole new flow, a
signaletic one [more or less what I just
said]. These will break from modular
limits and become deterritorialized. They
also break the existing relation between
matter and form [explained in terms of a
tensor which confines everything to sensible
striations --it's all relentlessly
non-humanist], and thus appear to be
arbitrary or aleatory. A new kind of
determinability can then appear.
Everything depends on the substance reaching
that threshold, converting material into
signaletic flow [also known as 'expressive
fractalization'(133)]. We can get a
kind of determinability, an inner
proliferation, and this dominates the
formation of relations with other
identities. We have a whole
'multiplicity of entitarian choices,
optional junctions, generating so many lines
of flight of possibility'. The
external constraints on determinability
break down producing a whole 'infinite
process of imploding'. The only
connections with the original module are
through 'homothety'[a kind of projection of
a shape on to a larger area] or a 'baker
transformation'[a baffling mathematical
concept found in topology which refers to
the transformation of a substance by
stretching and folding and raises all sorts
of gripping mathematical issues about
mixture and uniformity: an early model of
chaos, apparently. It might be worth
investigating more except that it is just
being used as a possible image of the
implosions and fractal development].
This is not a descent into anarchy, because
it is still controlled by various phase
spaces and enunciative basins found in
Φ and U respectively. [The
diagram summarizing this argument on page
133 also notes that sensible flows are best
understood as contingent, while signaletic
flows are singular]
The expressive function: f(exp)
We're not talking here about a flight that
ends in abolition, because some elements of
sensible support or material base are
retained [the modular references are
reproduced is how he puts it], but also
enriched by the proliferation of
possibilities in a particular phase space
[the controlled possibilities depending upon
degrees of freedom?]. This in turn
will permit different forms of expressive
matter, depending on different forms of
creation and mutation. The original
coding is undone by these
fluctuations. These new forms may
include genetic, semiotic, or ethological
codes, and more a '"constructivist" forms of
expression including 'phonic, scriptural,
organic'(134). When an expressive
dimension develops, a matter becomes both
something for itself, articulated in
modules, and something for something else
according to various pro-positions.
We can distinguish a fractal proliferation,
the basis of this expressive function, found
in abstract machinic phyla and incorporeal
universes of reference, and various
'residual discursive forms' of it, shaped by
particular relations between matter and
forms, at the sensible level, which are
still important for the existential function
[apparently to come].
The expressive function itself works with
two registers. First it repeats
certain aspects of the sensible module that
originally supported it, including 'formulae
of symmetry'[possibly in the technical sense
of symmetry explained by DeLanda—roughly
the basic shape of objects depending on how
many characteristics they have, so a circle
is more symmetrical than a square, although
we can turn one into the other by adding
dimensions]. Secondly, deformations
arise from the new set of references in the
phase space of possibility producing new,
possibly unimaginable before, 'angles of
approach'. After all, fractalization is more
than repetition but possesses a 'surplus
value of code'. We have a phase space
introducing these possibilities 'adjacent to
F'.
[Example follows about the phase space
relative to the figure 225, an integer which
can be made up of all sorts of fractions,
irrational numbers and others, diagram on
135. {Ken Gale et al should have
explored this with the colour 'red'!} We
will probably have to think in terms of more
than two dimensions, however, and think more
in terms of folding representing different
aspects of 'contingencing' as in the baker
transformation. The possible folds are
aleatory, but also confined to a particular
structure of necessity. The entity
that results is both a mere illustration of
an infinite number of possibilities, and
also a 'contingent and necessary hook' for
the procedures of folding. In another
example, a plant on his windowsill is a
sensible territory and one of its references
is the colour green {sic!}. At the
modular level, the green colour is
'encysted' with the specific being-there of
the plant, but we can grasp the colour from
multiple points of view, and certain of its
features will be contingent, depending on
the intervention of other variables such as
light or temperature: we will end with 'an
infinity of points of view', in a particular
set or phase space. These points of
view will not be random or indifferent, but
arising from particular constraints which
will relate the variables].
It follows that human knowledge arises from
a human form that eventually happened one
day, but that human form can also be seen
according to quite different modalities,
existing on 'other ontological
levels'(136). In other words, there
are elements of proto-knowledge in human
knowledge, found widely dispersed in
structural territories or deterritorialized
systems. It is the phase space that
encloses elements enough to produce a
being-there from a state that also includes
'proto-alterity'.
We can understand this articulation in terms
of an expression-content relation [where
content is regulated by the phase
space]. In that phase space,
'intrinsic formal determinability' that
produces modules and territories are now
deterritorialized and combined with
extrinsic determinability. This
produces the paradoxical combination of a
territorial state found as a module, and a
consistent state but now subject to
extrinsic determinability. Returning
to the example, the 'serial trait'
represented by the colour green can be both
fixed in a module, and circulating in a
phase space as a fractal state, or
incorporeal discursive form [in Φ and
U respectively]. So the single
characteristic is also the same as something
circulating through virtual universes as
well as material flows.
These two worlds, 'contingent
territorialities' and 'transversal, fractal
and deterritorialized entities' might well
be grasped on a pure abstract level of
reference. This is the plane of
consistency which traverses the
collection of states of things.
However, the cartographic approach suggests
another way to grasp the connections, as an
'assemblage of intermediary temporalities',
the zones of contingency in FT and
virtuality in Φ U. It follows
that we will never encounter either in only
in a pure state, that there will be
different degrees of contingency and
deterritorialization in these expressive
assemblages, although we may be able to get
access indirectly through things such as
mystic experience or a 'divinatory hysteria'
(137) [nausea in Sartre is another
possibility for him], on the 'outskirts of
ordinary enunciation'. We should
incorporate these as components of the
cartography of subjectivity.
Summarizing, we now have: modules which
focus on finite contingency; 'monads of
infinite determinability'[first time we have
seen that term] featuring incorporeal
smoothing in Φ or U; assemblages of
both relative contingency and relative
transcendence, and these will help us grasp
the full creative role of the cycle of
assemblages.
Let's return to the notion of
expression. It is now a correlate of
deterritorialized and fractal smoothing of
modular striations. It is produced by
machines of expression which 'somehow'(138)
force the possible out of encysted modular
forms [horrible metaphor]. Smoothing
requires decompartmentalization of the
various contents produced by the local
fields of possibility. It is not a
matter of relating a simple 'univocal'
register of expression to a similar one of
content, because content is never
homogenous, and expression never
hegemonic. There are degrees of
smoothing of content, because expression has
heterogeneous components and different kinds
of consistency according to how it is
'inscribed' by various 'multiple incorporeal
referents'.
There is no general theory of expression as
a result, despite some parallels, say
between baroque music and mathematics.
Transversality [of expression] requires
deterritorialized content, but there are
still 'thresholds, decelerations and
detours'. We also need modules and
contingencies as well as more open forms.
Some thresholds in expression can be seen as
junctions producing new components of
possibility, because of their connection
with various 'adventitious universes of
reference' that had been held in
reserve. Sometimes, the surface
produced by a phase may be compatible with
'the basin of virtuality of a new universe
of reference'(139) [I think of this basin as
a bit like the hollows in space time
surrounding solid bodies that attract
passing ones]. This may produce new
components of expression which will start up
fractal folding again, or open the process
to extrinsic determinability. We're
not talking about a striation here but
rather a continuous engendering.
However, this can sometimes also be delayed
by a connection with a universe of reference
[with an allusion to 'différance']: the
combination of engendering and delay
produces stochastic paths and rhizomes [not
just constant arborescent engendering]. [So
rhizomes have an ontological mechanism]
Renewed fractal development can also lead to
new deterritorialized folding and to another
phase space. They can also be new
forms of 'referential enunciation'.
This will prevent the regular collection of
contents into paradigms according to formal
processes of composition. Instead, we
can have the consistent development of the
singular and the irreversible, possibly with
a whole new enunciative basin.
Turning to semiotics specifically, it is
impossible to locate a genesis. There
may be local ones coordinated at the molar
level and producing a particular kind of
extensive and intrinsic
determinability. There may be
unlocalized ones at the molecular level
producing 'intensive - extrinsic
determinability' (140) [apparently, these
can be more or less instant, lacking a
trajectory, so escaping from the need to
specify some energy as below]. Conventional
coordinates get deterritorialized in order
to generate categories of general
measurement [in a bit that I particularly do
not understand, there is apparently some
dissymmetry in such measurements at the
quantum level].
Signaletic flows can act as catalyses on
material flows as they turn into instants of
material processes, which means that there
must be a component of energy in
expression. There must be some
transfer of energy between action and effect
if these are to be put into connection to
permit communication [and a process of
amplification]. In effect, [and rather
the other way around], entities with a
potential for action and effect must
communicate, signal to each other, recognize
each other [also required for the mysterious
process of 'resonance' in Diff'n'Rep?.
There is a 'signaletics within the
materiality of flows'(141) and this
underpins the potential for action at the
molecular level. New possibilities
appear to alter the composition of entities,
change the qualities of separability, and
trigger 'fractal faults'. These
possibilities will eventually appear in the
molar order as well.
There therefore must be [transcendental
deduction again] some really universal and
basic principle of expression ['expressive
apprehension of entities and relations'] in
the same phase space or basin of universe of
reference. We can think of it as a
kind of energy that generates both of being
for self and of being outside of self, and
it has different levels of energy rather
than some pure form [we have to avoid all
pure forms here, Guattari says, or we will
be supporting the notion of the universal
role of the signifier]. There is an
abstract ['in the sense of extraction']
energy at work even in those familiar
modules that link matter and form [it
provides one of the tensions in modules]
These are required for any kind of
consistency arising from chaos.
However, modules operate with a memory of
flows ['a memorial taking
consistency']. This modular
consistency is disrupted by the processes
described above, and determinability can now
work in a different way, towards separation
and towards the affirmation of the
possible. These were already at work
in other deterritorialized and immaterial
areas. Entities now become 'powdery,
atmospheric, molecular', but not entirely
free to combine or to refer to each
other. Instead they are 'assigned to
enunciative basins'. These are also
relatively deterritorialized and can join
with other basins, either through internal
mutation or because of the affects of
foldings of phyla or other 'singularization
factors'.
The existential function f(exi)and the
diagrammatic function f(diag)
Expressive smoothing acts on modular
structures in another direction. It
operates towards the existential and the
pragmatic as a kind of reciprocal to the
smoothing directed at the incorporeal.
However, pragmatic actualization requires a
number of other thresholds to be achieved—Da
Vinci thought up a flying machine, but it
could not be actualized until scientific and
technological development and the
accumulation of 'immense Capitals of
knowledge' (142) and their accompanying
institutions. Expressive discursivity
bumps into the limits offered by
'reality...the modular stratification of the
everyday world'. However, pragmatics is not
just a bolt on to apparently more basic
functions of language like denotation and
signification.
Expression also produces existential
mutations [he reminds us that 'enunciation
and existence arise from the same
apparatuses of Expression and are even
similar expressions']. A renewal of
expressive functions brings about changes in
territorialized modules as well as the
opposite deterritorialization of
forms. As a results, old forms of
sensible territory develop new 'species of
existential territory'(143). All this
happens in another phase space relating to
content [with another Φ attractor] .
Partly, this is the result of various
machinic propositions which develop a
consistency [apparently to be explained
later] which can counter actual flows.
However, we now realize that Expression
actually has different properties of
requalification: it is the 'formal endpoint'
of the modular function and the way in which
it links matter and form; it is the result
of an expressive tensor, which will lead to
an eventual 'Point of Contingencing'; it is
a way of linking matter and form to produce
substance in existential terms.
We can understand the overall process in a
number of ways, including the ways in which
hysteria alters discursive chains and their
denotations and conventional expressions, as
a kind of conversion. The new chains
take on corporeal form, as 'an ontological
simulation'. The overall result is to
produce 'an existential body without organs'
which rapidly acquires 'a proxy
organicity'. In this way, discursive
chains can appear as '"scene shifters"'(144)
They also appear as existential refrains,
including 'faciality traits, emblems and
signatures'. The first one emerges
from the modular structures that produced
the human face after deterritorializing
animal faces. They are expressive
because there is a code in faciality [all
that stuff about black holes and white
screens in ATP?].
However, possible combinations are limited,
so that 'excessive laughter' for example
looks like a sign of madness. They can
also be seen as diagrammatic, and as a
signature of a particular individual or
group: this is how faces come to represent
leadership and communal loyalty [the example
is the face of Christ in the middle ages
--especially the depiction of him as
all-powerful]. Emblems and signatures
work in the same way. They denote
specific things in modules, but they also
have a a function that makes them refer to a
whole 'enacted subjectivity' with all sorts
of political and ethical implications.
When expression acts back on existence, it
does not just return to previous striations,
because it is no longer a passive
form. Now it contains 'semiotic
potentials', although these are actually
brought from phyla and universes of
virtuality.
However, we also have to remember that the
development of fractals can produce residual
forms which remain. Expressive
requalification, say in the form of a
refrain, lends these residues a new
'virulent hyper active memory' (145) and
these become open to new inputs. So
when an existential function follows an
expressive function which produces a fractal
rupture, there can be a kind of
'intermediary reterritorialization'.
This is the diagrammatic function. A
diagram folds together all the possibilities
and potentials resulting from
fractalization, and this brings surplus
values of possibility. These
possibilities actually arise from things
brought together by the phase attractor of
content. However, it is best
understood as a return to a point of
contingency [better than stasis -- it is
where we can see that arrangements are
contingent, arbitrary?] rather than an
eruption from it as with expression [in the
form of an enunciative catalysis produced by
the refrains and synapses, it seems].
It is not an irresistible process, but
something rather precarious, confined,
inspired by existential refrains [and other
pragmatic impulses?] [Marvelous
gobbledegook ensues, page 145, the gist of
which is that there must be some connection
with actual enunciations in T and U if the
diagram is to be put to work. The
whole cycle of assemblages and their various
determinabilities is invoked again].
The diagrammatic function is an example of
how expressive functions acquire energy, and
begin to circulate sign particles.
Existential refrains
We have some examples, but now we have to
establish that they arise at the junction of
two 'existential and diagrammatic
functions', that they involve a process, an
activity and a way that exceeds 'grasping'
as in the existential function above.
Again we can get some examples from
psychiatry in the form of obsessive rituals
or systematized delirium—both attempt to
recompose in erratic ways bits of an old
existential territory, but they also display
a process, 'a line of flight, a "fugue of
sense"' charged with desire.
Refrains appear in two states: 'atonic'
which simply indexes a particular discursive
residue of a dead memory, reawakening
earlier substances in modules; an excited
state which uses the surplus possibilities
in diagrams to produce 'original' shapes and
genetic processes as a kind of
catalysis. The first one appears after
an intrinsic cracking in a module which will
question the relation between matter and
form. In the excited state, extrinsic
points of view originating in diagrams are
introduced, as kind of positive
determinability [a limited one, that also
introduces negative determinability, which
is the way in which he describes the
production of separation]. Modules change as
a result as they become open to other
enunciative assemblages. Refrains
therefore act to open up choice or options
[not just reinforce the old patterns as in
the first examples in ATP of
children or birds reassuring
themselves?] but only within the
limits set by the degrees of freedom of the
system.
A number of consequences are possible.
First, the status quo persists, which we see
with emblems or institutional signatures
[the face is less suitable, apparently
because it contains more potential
creativity]. Second, there can be
unstable equilibrium, with the refrain
announcing alternative universes of
reference at the virtual level. A
potential fractalization is indicated,
transversality becomes possible. This
possible consequence appears with Freudian
slips, but also with dada and surrealism and
the use of objective chance or playful
breaks. In the third possibility,
there is a 'straightforward processual
mutation' (148), as in the example of Proust
where the processes of concrete time
eventually produce the general notion of
'lost Time'. Refrains can also appear
in the form of concrete machines to be
discussed later.
As these examples indicate, there can be a
positive practice of existential refrains,
despite the passivity introduced by
'capitalistic - monotheism'. Some
animist societies show this.
Psychoanalysis missed this altogether,
however, by introducing the constraints of
unconscious complexes or structuralist
relations with part objects.
We could even develop a positive practice
against bureaucracy if we deliberately
'artificialized, "baroquized"'the mechanisms
(149): pointless repetition as a refrain
would obstruct their normal workings, break
out from technological or scientific
paradigms, and reintroduce ethics and
aesthetics. Thus analyzing refrains
could produce 'a different subjectivity,
other enunciative modalities that dis-pose
existence differently'[sounds pretty much
like what the Situationsts were doing?
I have always liked ironic or surreal
bureaucratic procedure].
The striation of phyla
This should be understood in terms of
regularities, rules and principles that are
required to be put 'adjacent' to flows, to
provide a texture for them, and a 'relative
ontological autonomy' compared to the
sensible world and conventional coordinates
and framings. This sort of ontological
striation in phyla appears as usual where
two smoothings join, in this case expressive
smoothing and smoothings introduced by
incorporeal universes of reference.
What makes the relation between phyla and
universes difficult is that they have to be
compossible rather than clearly distinct
from each other. T and F are really
distinct, with different kinds of
determinability, and different combinations
of them to produce different sorts of
smoothing and striation. But traits of
determinability are mixed between phyla and
universes, producing a characteristic kind
of smoothing and striations which is
'rigorously synchronic and homothetic' and
which will need to be explored.
Chapter seven the domain of
universes
[Usual discussion of smoothing as an
operation to link the virtual with the
actual, the possible with the real, but this
time with some additional considerations
because we are discussing enunciation. The
most obscure of all so far,partly to use
terms that break with conventional
linguistics and thus deny its uniqueness?]
The phase spaces of possibility have
surfaces and these become 'enunciative
instances' connected with U. However,
these instances are rather peculiar in being
both 'distinct and indistinct at the same
time' (151). Face spaces are produced
as particular states of possibility as a
particular contingency, including a break
with conventional contingency, sets off a
fractal unfolding. However in that
phase space at the virtual level, all
possible fractal unfoldings are represented,
including future ones. As fractal
unfolding proceeds to infinity, the phase
space becomes identical to the general plane
of consistency or chaosmos. The only
thing that stops this infinite
determinability is the intrusion of a
particular decelerated determinability, but
not in the same way as with modules which
are more definite: here, we have a much more
'floating, diffuse, atmospheric' form.
At particular moments, phases may be
separate from each other even if they
operate simultaneously. Yet each phase
contains all the others virtually [because
ultimately they can be tracked back to a
plane of consistency, I think]. Thus
separation produced by deceleration at
particular times is also accompanied by a
relation of infinite speed, since each phase
space is an element in the whole paradigm
that leads to the plane of
consistency. What we have is 'a
vibratory state of the same process'
(152). We can see this as a kind of
'continuist - fractal - molecular
discursivity'.
But there is also a process of non
discursive enunciation, appearing as an
element in U. This is also both
distinct, local and contingent, and
delocalised and infinitely dispersed as a
kind of atmosphere. The latter quality
permits migration of the elements just as
phase mutations spread and end in the plane
of consistency. This enunciative
element is therefore both the result of
contingent separability and the
representation of possible positions of
fractal unfolding, both an actualized
enunciation [actually the locus for one] and
an infinity of virtual denunciations [I'm
not at all sure this is not just a fancy way
of saying that linguistic terms, for example
can both denote and connote].
It follows [?] that determinability cannot
be localized in either Φ or U because there
are no distinct aggregates. The
problem is that 'enunciative intentionality'
sets off continuous fractalization
[fractalization now standing for any sort of
proliferation and complexity?]. The
trouble is that it is always capable of
intercalation [I think]: we see this in
obsessive conditions.
However, together, a sense of virtual
enunciation develops, between those phases
that produce a limited kind of
determinability. In this way,
enunciations in U can also be seen to
smooth, gather and integrate particular
enunciations. This takes the form of
sets of 'traits of determinability', and
again they can be intrinsic [referring us
all the way back to the modular sequence];
extrinsic introduced by content in its
phases; infinite based on this notion of
continuous determinability. In each
case [?] the infinite fractal process takes
on the form of a contingent determination,
in this case an element of U, and this
'snags, fixes, ballasts it'(154).
The chaosmosis of the
continuum
There are three different kinds of
enunciation: modular and contingent; monadic
involving absolute determinability [where a
monad is what—a single enunciator, a single
pov?] ; mixed assemblage, with both infinite
and convergent determinability.
Modules offer a form of reference based on a
sensible territory, something actively
finite, something putting into process
contingency from a particular point of
view. Monadic forms are more scattered
since they often repeat: every time they get
actualised, an infinite set of virtual
determinations is channeled. As soon
as something becomes actualised and attempts
to relate to some other actual, an
enunciative filter interposes itself [and
this filter seems to involve infinite
possibilities again]. It might be
possible to separate particular
enunciations, but they tend to come with 'an
ontological plenitude' of possible series
that prevents any segmentation or closure or
striation. Determinability is not
confined or limited, but stays in the
atmosphere, like an aerosol or suspension.
[Still on the monadic] Apparently, this is a
characteristic of the plane of consistency
considered as a chaosmosis. It
features both chaos, with entropy and
redundancy, but also another 'paradoxical'
characteristic in the form of 'the ensemble
of neg-entropic virtualities'[creative
possibilities?]. These two poles pair
up to produce particular modes of proximity,
both spatial and temporal. Spatial
orders combine infinite distance with
'infinitesimal circumscription', while
temporal orders smooth future and past.
There is also a new energy produced by
heterogeneous basins. Somehow this
adds a certain transversality to stochastic
process, in the form of symmetry and
'gestaltist relations' between heterogeneous
situations. We can consider these
processes together as offering 'new
modalities of circumstance'. Although
apparently offering absolute
determinability, the limits are being
constantly overcome. There is 'an
eternal repetition' although this also
produces 'an inexhaustible surplus value of
sense and existence'. The whole notion
of otherness collapses, leading to 'a
generalised enunciative transfer,a hegemonic
transitivity and transversality' (156) [once
we start describing and representing
objects, we find that this is limitless, a
bit like schizoanalytic cartography
itself?].
We can experience something like this at
those moments when we realize that
consciousness constructs the entire outside
world and all the selves and others in
it. This moment of megalomania becomes
entirely internal and circular, because
nothing independent exists against which to
recognize itself [an essential externality
for subjectivity as argued above].
This might also hinted at the capitalist
obsession to find a generalized equivalence
for everything.
[Turning to the third kind, the mixed
assemblage]. We find these everywhere
in the cycle of assemblages. It is a
general problem to explain how creative
capacities of assemblages becomes stabilized
or hooked by contingency, links established
between incorporeal universes and sensible
modules. Another problem is how to
explain particular forms of temporality
between the two abstract possibilities with
things like refrains or 'existential auto
consistency'. The answer will lead us
[as in transcendental deduction] to an
underlying process that produces both the
continuous and the discontinuous, found also
in the chaosmos.
[It looks like he is trying to preserve the
notion of a universal determinability here,
page 157, as a form of enunciation
overcoming all specific forms of contingent
determinability] the smoothing of virtual
determinability appears in the form of
diagrams or singularities and should not be
seen in platonic terms completely remote
from sensible 'hooks'.
Symmetries
Different types appear in the three domains
considered so far. In F we find
'reversible, extensional symmetries'; in Φ
'relatively reversible fractal symmetries';
and in U 'irreversible internal symmetries'.
In F the connection between different
entities implies the existence of something
held in common, and this is extensional
symmetry. Each element can generates
its own relation with other elements [at
right angles so to speak]. These
relations are reversible, with no origin and
no particular direction. This is
different from the processes of fractal
proliferation because each stage is
different from the one that precedes it, it
is '"dated"' by the process (158). Fractal
symmetry in Φ is not a matter of
conventional space and time, but rather
topological deformation and
deterritorialization. Molar
similarities are based on elements at the
molecular level. Again this shows us
something interesting and paradoxical [!], a
separation that is not contingent, 'a
virtual and unlocalizable separability'.
[Wonderful abstract possibility generated by
his endless tables and classifications?]
[I can only grasp the simplest form of the
next point, that each 'signaletic element
finds itself doubled by a multitude of
"freeze frames"'. Apparently the wider
point is that unlike modular determination,
the very 'texture of determinability'
changes, and content becomes important
instead of some formal external notion of
symmetry. This permits machinic
propositions to bring something additional
to expression in the form of 'activated
formulae, virulent abstract
machinisms'. These in turn develop
'transverse, evolving, creative bridges
between different assemblages'. This
[somehow] is associated with the third kind
of symmetry [and apparently he has borrowed
the turn from some contemporary physics]
[Overall, pretty incomprehensible, I
fear. The basics appear to be that
symmetry can be creative if it is not just
reversible and extensional, but that these
forms of creative symmetry obviously have to
be described in an unusually technical way,
which seems to involve our old favourite
combination of apparently paradoxical
elements, in this case separation and
continuity].
The striations of virtual universes
Incorporeal universes repeat but also
produce irreversible singularities.
They affirm themselves; they are neither
finite nor discursive. We can call
them universes of reference or universes of
enunciation. We're going to borrow
Spinoza's weasel and say 'that it is in
their essence to exist' (159). They
feature both infinitely speedy and
infinitely decelerated types of
change. Their singularizations show
'internal necessitation'and this underpins
the existential weight of assemblages.
Assemblages in turn energize virtual
universes, as the possible becomes
necessary.
[More difficult stuff, apparently based on
Spinoza]. Assemblages 'authorise' the
existence of each other in the form of
extrinsic determinability. Intrinsic
determinability is thus subsidiary, except
for 'a pure and empty consistency of
existential grasping'. Extrinsic
coordinates include real ones in F, and
possibilistic or legal ones in Φ.
However, extrinsic forms have an internal
base of their own, a striation which must be
adequate.
What incorporeal universes do is to
energetically requalify assemblages rather
than energize them directly. This
process can be seen as either procession,
working from points of contingency in the
domain of flows through to U, then T and
back to F, or recession, beginning in U and
linking Φ, F and T. Procession is
diachronic, but recessive requalification is
synchronic or structural. Procession
involves reference, but recession
enunciation, a form of 'existential taking
on of consistency' (160). However
there is something specific to striations in
U, an 'ontological sliding' so that
references to objects become subjected to
aesthetic consistency. It is not just
a matter of abstracting universals.
Universes are made consistent or striated as
a result of a particular constellation
within them, one which is both singular and
singularising. This particular
constellation crystallizes in U. We
can describe this process in the terms of
Art or in the 'practices of certain
cults'. We must also recognize the
paradox that energetic requalification
involves the return of aesthetic
singularities. It is really the result
of experimentation, which can itself be seen
as 'irreducibly singular incarnation' of
certain smoothed energies. We can now
see experimentation as an aesthetic
performance, so actual existential acts have
the same structure whether scientific or
artistic. Despite Habermas's efforts
[sic], there are no obvious rules, but
rather 'a legality without law', rather like
Kant's notion of the beautiful [and we know
what Bourdieu said about that—the
unconscious judgments of the elite based on
their need to distance themselves from the
masses]. We can also bring in Kuhn [!]
on paradigms, if we see these as akin to
aesthetic schools, since they also implies
singular constellations of universes of
reference.
Synaptic dis-position
We have seen this process before when
talking about striations of flows.
However, there are differences in the
'synaptic interval'(161). This time there is
a break that is 'rich in content', but this
content is now a- signifying, that is
detached from its [linguistic] paradigms and
syntagms. It appears as a residue, but
it manages to offer a new kind of
expression. It will offer a 'double
articulation', linking Φ and T. It
will permit 'hyper complexification'of self
reference. It will offer a synapses
seen, or 'seems shifter', aimed not at
finding some inner lost meaning, but rather
crystallising a constellation that singular
eyes is.
[We've already discussed aesthetics and
scientific paradigms, but] now we can
include other examples of discursivity in
dreams or Freudian slips, best seen as a
genuine mutations of assemblages of
enunciation rather than as symptoms.
We can also examined dada and surrealism and
the ways in which they developed the
creative potential of synapses like this,
'dice throws', bending understandings and
sense. Other forms of psychiatry tried
to understand these examples, but they all
operated with 'the promotion of an abstract
subject'(162), some 'structurally homogenous
unconscious' in an unchallenged symbolic
order, 'constantly recentred...on
individuated lived experience' (163).
Instead, concrete productions of
subjectivity are 'essentially heterogeneous,
a multicentred processes, tributary to
assemblages of enunciation meshing with
disparate, aleatory and/or historical
realities', escaping from structure and
culture.
The issue is how to explain signified
content not as autonomous but as the basis
for certain conversions. One
conversion might be into the refrain, and
the issue is whether there is an incorporeal
equivalent. Partial contents can open
up new virtual fields. Certain
machinic propositions, requalified through
the cycle of assemblages, can 'represent the
new, non discursive and virtual instances of
enunciation', without reverting to
conventional signification. Such
machinic propositions do not just represent
the fractal and deterritorialized virtual at
the moment of breaks with contingency, but
energize them, act as sign particles [permit
new creative signification?].
So synapses in the form of machinic
propositions prevent the 'implosion' of
assemblages of enunciation [that is, their
capture by ultimate determinations?] on the
plane of consistency. They can be seen
as a new abstract machinic process,
operating between Φ and U, and displaying
four dimensions: 'singularization,
heterogenesis, necessitation and
irreversiblization' (163). [These are
all now included as further examples of
processes linking the four domains in a
diagram on 165].
Singularization is the deterritorialized
counterpart of the process of contingency in
sensible modules [so it is a floating kind
of contingency?] It is attracted to
points of the breakdown of contingency, but
offers a surplus value of possibility, one
which will produce a diagrammatic function
for example. Rather than extending
determinability to infinity in a fractal
process, it operates instead with 'a sort of
ontological stamp, a decreeing of
existential necessitation'. This in
turn links U and T. When a virtual
enunciation is singularized, in the form of
a particular constellation of the universe,
possibilities in Φ become necessary and
regular. The turning of possibility
into necessity energises an assemblage, and
shows a process whereby signaletic flows
become flows of sign particles.
Once synapses singularizes, assemblage
processes become irreversible, internally
disymmetric. This takes the form of
dating or situating even the most
deterritorialized enunciation. We see
this in the form of dating particular
constellations of universes by giving them
signatures, proper names, like Marxism.
Heterogenesis arises from the very interior
of a constellation of universes, in the form
of 'existential autonomization', being for
itself, or requalification coming from
T. Heterogeneity provides an
'enunciative matrix'[which can include the
combinations of the four processes—on the
diagram, they occupy reciprocal angles on
the diagonals between the four
domains]. It is not so much a
comparison between distinct entities, more
the persistence of a disparity or
disymmetry, which never developed into a
proper alterity. There are no
structures inside incorporeal universities
to centre them or attach them to anything
outside: heterogeneity and alterity are
better understood as the result of
'ontological self affirmation' arising in
existential territories.
Overall, we needed to discuss these stages
in the cycle of assemblages. We will
still need more details on the particular
modes of requalification. This will
help us understand the processes of living
beings, including individuation and
speciation and the effects of 'birth, death,
alterity, possibly sex and personal
consciousness'(166). We also needed to
show how new possibilities can arise from
breaks in the conventional processes or
'relays of contingency, singularity and
finitude'.
[NB we have not discussed in more detail T
-- Guattari thinks that has been discussed
adequately in his earlier accounts of
Integrated World Capitalism? Existential
implications are also pursued in the next
chapter]
Chapter eight Enunciative recursion
[NB recursion = the repetition of a
process to clarify a problem]
[The actualizing/territorializing effects of
the cycle of assemblages, although doubtless
there will also be deterritorialization as
well.]
Contingency, and its development into a
point of contingencing [same as a moment of
relative actualization or
territorialization?] is produced by crossing
operations in all 4 domains [and we have
described this in terms of the four
functions like f(exp) etc]. In Φ fractal
folds in expression initiates the
diagrammatic function. In U synapses relay
constellations of universes in a contingent
manner,and this can produce the refrain. In
T, the pathic function [now aka the
pathematic function -- in current usage
meaning relating to emotion or suffering,
but here a process producing the pathic?]
'releases' self-reference. In F, 'its own
domain', cycling through the other domains
produces 'an energized sign particle'
leading to 'concrete existential machines as
in f(exi) [the production of substance as
above] (167).
Energetic requalifications
As general expression changes to a
diagrammatic form,it can join with material
flows and change their state in a process
like energetic conversion [a parking permit
sets off a parking barrier is the example].
It shows how a semiotic with no energy
itself, sets off an eneregtic state,
overcoming the problem of explaining changes
of state with no actual transfer of energy
[in ch.2].[If I get this right] it is a
matter of seeing [what normal people would
consider as latent energy] energy as
simultaneously hyperaccelerated and
hyperdecelerated rather than of working with
different [eg latent and active,
non-transferable and transferable]
forms.[There is only one energy]. All
changes of state,all modifications are
therefore energetic,including Zen changes in
consciousness. 'It is therefore
difficult to object to' (169) the idea that
signaletic matters are also energetically
charged, in particular in developing
memories and recordings which will allow a
passage to the act. [weak extension of the
argument]
Perhaps energy lies in expression and not
form, however? If we agreed, we would
still be left with the issue of the gap
between observable and pragmatic states and
how these get bridged. Far better to
just assert that form is also energy,
although a different kind. We will be
able to explain how assemblages of
semioticization can actually amplify in
their effects. We have to accept that
there are certain thresholds of energy which
will ultimately produce 'machinic -
pragmatic effects'. [All this follows
by implication rather than demonstration, of
course].
Prior to any notion of representation of the
objective by the subjective, we have to
admit that the point of view is an act and
it prefigures 'some energized
interaction'. This includes even the
most deterritorialized and virtual
[non-subjective] acts of enunciation in U,
which produce synapses in constellations:
here we have a bridge between energy and
information [that is information
energizes]. The same goes with
possibilities in Φ, which are circumscribed
by a selection [by a synapse] of traits of
determinability, which emerge from the
general plane of consistency. These
possibilities also remain fuzzy or vague
because they can exhibit both infinite or
infinitesimal speed according to the
components of the phylum being selected.
We have therefore established a notion of
possibility, especially in constellations of
U, which are also necessary, without even
being actualized. We are suggesting
that there is a 'an infinitesimal,
unlocalized double, non separable energy'
(170) [why not call it Spirit and be done
with it?], that is not exclusive to
particular operations.
The four recursive causalities
We know there is a real chaos, but do we
really need a virtual chaosmosis as
well? [in other word, why not just
stick with theoretical physics?] But
enunciative recursion implies such a thing
[and maybe so does our whole cartographic
stance]. We can assert that real chaos
is only an 'aleatory projection' of
completely differentiated and unstructured
chaosmotic processes [and infinite regress
threatens—what is chaosmosis a projection
of?]. Instead of a discursive theory
to explain it, we will need a notion
of aggregates or populations of entities,
and to understand those, we'll have to
abandon the usual rational principles of
identity contradiction and the rest.
These aggregates will be produced by fractal
processuality, which implies a simultaneous
reality and virtuality. Even
simultaneous doesn't really grasp it because
we are talking about a contingent process
that decentres enunciations and crosses
'thresholds of veracity'. One
implication is that we have to revise our
notion of causality as involving a well
defined combination of causes lying behind
any particular state of things. We are now
working with heterogeneous causality in non
discursive space. It might not be
'rash' [weak] to see the four operations of
requalification between the four domains as
forms of causality. Thus we can think
of diagrammatic function as representing
formal cause, not least because it is
irreversible. Final causes can be seen
as the emergence of refrains following the
recession of singularities in synapses
originating in constellations of U.
Efficient causes can be seen as the effects
of energies in the form of pathic 'recursion
of heterogenesis' produced by existential
territories with effects in T.
Material or 'concrete machinic causes' (171)
refer to the affects of sign particles and
the way they necessitate.
Let's explore issues of the speed of
determinability that are implied [oh yes,
let's]. With flows, both sensible and
signaletic, discursive formations bundled in
modules, combine infinite speed within phase
spaces, and infinite deceleration
[separation] between them, in a striation of
flows appearing in any instant of
flow. However, this is a unique
ontological case.
Let's follow some implications for the plane
of immanence, 'or the primordial soup of
redundancies' (172). We will find both
discursive chaos operating at an infinite
speed of determinability, and a non
discursive chaosmosis with no extrinsic
reference, with no part part or part whole
relations, featuring some 'hyper ordering'
at an infinitely decelerated speed of
determinability, or 'immutability'.
This arises because absolute determinability
is never reached—'because even infinite time
would not suffice for it'. It thus
features a permanent virtual tension within
itself and it is that that joins it to real
chaos [the two are never finally joined,
because real chaos can never be fully
formed, and is likely to melt again 'at the
first instant']. There is always a
'deterritorializing crack' in the real that
projects into the virtual, and no
permanently uninterrupted path or duration
for an entity. It is this paradox that
we can find in constellations of universes.
Before we get there, we need to tidy up what
can happen to entities in Φ and T.
These are linked symmetrically. [We seem to
want to construe these us forces acting upon
the basic modular arrangement]. One
force offers discontinuous fractalization
working at infinite speed, and this is found
in Φ. In T we find another
fractalization, this time a 'continuist'
one, and decelerated speed eventually
producing pathic operators. The
discontinuity arises from combinations of
flows carrying both reference and traits of
determinability. This discontinuity
'integrates' positive determinability
[remembering that, according to Wikipedia
anyway, 'an integral
assigns numbers to functions in a way that
can describe displacement, area, volume, and
other concepts that arise by combining
infinitesimal data'...'a limiting procedure that
approximates the area of a curvilinear
region by breaking the region into thin
vertical slabs'. Guattari seems to use it as
a function describing and regulating or
circumscribing the operation of more
specific functions and operations?].
What modules do is to 'freeze' and select
positive traits.
In Φ, the negativity [infinite deceleration]
is preserved in a form of consistency that
is deterritorialized but which circumscribes
much more diffuse and powdery, unlocalizable
traits. This is a 'fractal molecular
consistency' (173) and is this that
integrates negative determinability.
There are also 'intermediate
temporalizations'...
Intermediate temporalities
These connect 'behaviours of pure
discursivity' based on machinic
propositions, and non discursive blocks
found as existential territories [he also
calls them durations]. For the former,
time is artificial, abstract or
digital. The latter display 'a unary
Parmenidian time' [I think of
Parmenides as an early phenomenologist
because Husserl
mentions him. I think of him as
offering an account of duration as
subjective time. A fuller account is
available on the indispensable Wikipedia].
'Temporalities of subjectification' connect
the two, producing a metamodel of an
objective world, but also particular
synaptic moments that produce an notion of
existing in the present, somewhere on the
horizon of constellations of universes.
How does this form of temporality appear in
singularized enunciations? At least it
is better than the unidimensional time, the
'informational linearity'of capitalism,
based on general equivalence between
different sorts of discursivity and
determination of existential
territories. We find this temporality
in mythic or aesthetic, even schizophrenic
meta models, which offer montages of
different components of time together with a
basis of modules and refrains—together they
produce a particular assemblage of
enunciation. However, not all these
components need be included, as long as we
resist naive models [some in phenomenology]:
time is composite and incessantly
recomposed. We can't predict that
particular components will always appear in
particular contexts, say economic
ones. Instead, particular conjunctions
of components produce particular
compositions, sometimes ephemeral, sometimes
durable, sometimes stable or unstable,
appearing in activities as diverse as
'birth, death, desire, madness' (175).
This is why enunciation is central to being
and time [and now we can re-read Parmenidies
-- and Heidegger -- 175] and discover Aion.
Discursive temporalities intersect with
existential durations, but not mechanically
[in an example, he drives his car 'on
autopilot' -- but 'particular [emergent]
connections with machinic durations and
temporalizations' wakes him up.] We find
this in many disruptive experiences. They
reveal a combination of two processes --
'fractal-processual-discursive and
fractal-recessual-nondiscursive', both found
in the 'chaotic soup of the Plane of
Consistency' (176). We can also experince
examples where a field of virtuality appears
'in a hegemonic fashion' to disrupt a normal
state of affairs -- described variously as
'a moment of fecund delirium... an instant
of seeing... a minute of eternity... a
gestalt switch' (177). A field of
possibility becomes available, a new line of
discursivity from the originally
non-discursive.
It is different in modules [which seen to
have some more direct dependence on Aion, in
that a definite interconnection or
interaction of the kind above does not
appear]. The apparent autonomy of
conventional time arises after a particular
constellation of universes finds its
simplest expression, is reduced to one
dimension. This is best seen in
capitalistic constellations, although these
may have developed at the very dawn of human
history.
Enunciative fractalization
The intermediate temporalities are
fractal. Flows connect to phyla
through 'fractal
sweeping/scanning'[allegedly discussed
above], and this also produced a relation
between molar and molecular [with a
reference back to the baker
transformation]. There are other
fractal procedures linking universes in Aion
and the registers of enunciations.
Fractalization in normal time [Chronos]
arises from attractors that articulate lines
of possibility in flows and produce 'pseudo
territories or deterritorialized
phyla'. Fractalization in Aion offers
no such circumscription, and avoids the
effects of normal time. Once it
crosses a particular threshold, it produces
'a -signifying synapses' which are
irreversible, which singularize and make
heterogeneous, and also necessitate.
This breaks with extrinsic coordinates
producing 'pure intensive iteration' with no
'discursive memory'(178). Indeed they
can produce '"active forgetting"',[somehow
linked to the eternal return—pass]. It
therefore acts as 'pure Parmenidian
immanence', with no inside or outside—it is
'a pure body without organs, a pure self
referential affirmation'. Existential
synapses also exist to cross chronic and
aionic temporalities, producing a link
between molar discursive sets and molecular
non discursive intensity [intensity here
meaning something intrinsic rather than
something emotionally intense? Not sure
though, because affect gets a big talk up
below].
Discursivity in normal time articulates sets
and elements through: envelopment,
where one subset is preeminent; through
differential solidarity of given sets with
other sets not covered in the same
reference; between elements of a subset
where there may be both rupture and passage
according to the particular combinations of
reference and heterogeneity; transcendental
referents, referred to some more general
system of coordinates. It is often the
case that capitalistic coordinates involving
equivalency dominate, but we might also
still find mythical and ideological
coordinates as well.
Discursivity in Aion involves reference to
an external context which might have
enunciative instances involved in it.
Here we have to operate with 'non proximal
fractalization', a process of 'frozen
existential grasping of heterogeneous
enunciative nuclei'(179), fragments, partial
enunciations, made heterogeneous by
intensive qualities. These offer
'molecular nonseparability' [ie found
together in some of the social aggregates?]
which apparently appear at the very heart of
the enunciative genesis of [conventional]
form and content. Intensive
coordinates are not limited by time, space
or energy and thus produce a kind of
'megalomania' in enunciating monads.
Nor is there a limit to their molecular
components, which become infinitesimal, a
matter of their machinic essence. In
conventional time, abstract machines exist
at the same level as the operators, but not
in Aionic time—there is no underlying
form. Instead, we find certain
existential qualities which are organizing
themselves. Only this assumption will
stop infinite fractal regression.
[These qualities seen particularly
mysterious as being absolutely distinct and
absolutely indistinct at the same time—the
latter arising because we can use the same
form of knowing to get to them, including
'transferential apprehension, or knowing by
affect' (180).
Thus affect becomes hegemonic [sic].
There is an endless connection otherwise
between these elements. Fractal
processes produce hyper complexity. We
experience this in terms of our 'pragmatic
sensori-motor and cognitive memories'.
This is unlike the processes with machinic
phyla, however, chaos arises instead from a
definite 'systemic deterritorialization',
developed by certain external catalytic
operators. [The bizarre example that
follows turns on the photography of Tahara,
also appearing in a separate entry.]
Certain features of photographs, including
their puncta [as in Barthes?] or other
disturbing effects can lead to the 'fractal
deterritorialization of a portrait'.
This depends on a more general process of
the deterritorialization of faciality which
breaks out from conventional
signification. As a result, we can see
faciality as a kind of basic model of the
apprehension of meaning, producing both
sense and a 'non discursive dimension of
human comprehensibility'. Different
universes of reference are transversally
related 'in a single moment of
impact'.
'The production of subjectivity is
nothing other than this fractal machinic
of faciality inexorably caught up in a
becoming-abstract'. There is no
[other] ground or limit to the implosion
involved, and this is how we can grasp 'the
totality of the world'. (181).
Existing concepts are only intermediaries,
something produced by a machine. There
are no basic building blocks. For
example, the basic organs of biology have
turned into the basic particles of
physics. Particular logics of
discursivity become more abstract [head
toward 'abstract machines of
enunciation']. We can see that there
is a 'an irreducible becoming' traversing
every established order. We should see
scientific analysis as the product of
particular kinds of algorithmic operations.
Schizoanalytic analysis therefore rejects
objectivist descriptions in favour of
grasping the impact of enunciative
processes, especially their impact on the
normal notions of signification and sense
organized according to conventional
paradigms and syntagms. This is why we
have focused on the four domains and the
ways in which the chaosmos produces
different kinds of enunciative breakthrough
in each [a diagram on 181 summarises the
different processes in the different domains
and how they converge. An additional
diagram on 182 shows how enunciation
produces energy which then produces praxis
and process. This is 'enunciative
hyper complexity'].
Necessitation
Enunciation offers 'the choice for
finitude', an attachment'with a view to
constituting a world' [echoes of the assumed
desire of the universe to actualize itself,
a kind of elan vital?]. We have seen
how this works in normal time in terms of
modular striations grasping flows.
Aionic flows are different again, no longer
stabilised by phase spaces which guarantee
their internal consistency.
Enunciation here has no other purpose but to
offer dis-position, resting on
nothing. It can exist as 'pure
existential self affirmation' which somehow
grasps the elements in the other
domains. But it can also exist in and
of itself, and this is necessitation.
Modules are not linked causally or
directly, but they affirm each other in a
form of 'intensive becoming'. In
turn, this will generate enunciation
through 'generalised transference'.
[What about that bit of necessity
that implies death and endings?]. There can
also exist 'sensible ex-modules', as monads,
connected through fractal processes, with no
substantial inner or outer contexts.
These offer empty repetition.
Sometimes this can become a refrain, still
a-signifying. They are also open to
molecularization [with a reference to
somebody called Edgar Morin] (183).
However, these still retain a potential for
registering determinations from the whole to
which they once belonged, and this is the
basis for the particular texture of
assemblages. We can see this as a
particular kind of qualitative
existence. There is a tendency to
constrain any links with deterritorialized
phyla, however, because these modules do not
perform signification but just preserve
their existence. This is a form of
underlying contingency found in
necessitation, in this context, a
necessary finitude experienced by every
machine.
Let's take some helpful examples [!].
There is a discrepancy between the actual
form of a house, with its insides and
outsides, and the existential assemblage
which notes it. Human beings can
experience a notion of the outside through
affect, for example [he talks about visual
adjustments, and different sorts of air
coming into his lungs]. [Another
example concerns an astronomer who agreed to
verify a particular calculation—unless you
know the case of Galle, this is not very
helpful]. There is also 'pubescent
hormonal speech', associated with biological
sexual maturity, which effects
refrains. There is the machinic aspect
of learning to drive a car or play
football. There are also poets who can
open up 'virtualities without shores'.
[So these are all examples of determinisms
working in both directions?].
Heterogenesis
T and U are linked by pathic operators that
produce heterogeneity. This helps an
identity to be allocated to a particular
energy site as a part of 'ontological
grasping'. However, the major part of
this operation involves 'the intensive
affirmation of a for-itself' (184).
Heterogeneous is is different [! ] and
operates through a fractal process, the
transference of knowledge, the combination
of a nucleus of self reference and a proto
energetic basin. The process also
produces apparent existentially singular
positions.
Intensive differentiation exists in all self
ordered systems. Reference is internal
but also related to other systems. It
is not a matter of the composition of
elements, but rather a disposition so that
each point becomes a centre of reference for
the whole: the human equivalent is the stage
or video, capturing elements in the
scene. The scene is not an interaction
of elements, but rather an agglomeration.
Nor a matter of grasping the scene from the
outside by an enunciative assemblage,
because that assemblage itself is
constituted by the act of looking at
something. The gaze does not just
necessarily control the scene, because it
also apprehends things which are extra
territorial, 'elements of dehiscence' [I
have looked this up before. It means
the spilling out of something through a
split or cut].
In technical terms we can see that the scene
is heterogeneous, with both modular serial
and finite relations between F and T, and
fractal, non proximal and infinite relations
between T and U. Self existential
processes are therefore both
territorializing and
deterritorializing. It is not just a
matter of forming up in extrinsic
coordinates, but also contributing to
'processual ordinates'. The two forms
are transposable, not just limited to
structures, but also linking to abstract
machines. The very dimensions of time
and substance are fractalized.
Sensible and abstract qualities can relate
transversaly. [The example is the
pathic operators of the Proustian
search, the ways in which times are
linked by connections with quite
heterogeneous substances like flavours,
memories, little phrases of music and so on.
Heterogeneity here indicates an underlying
'labour of heterogenesis' in which each
dimension is explored, and aleatory factors
are discovered to be immanent to
assemblages. This particular
assemblage appears as as a result of
'existential glue' containing all sorts of
bifurcations and degrees of freedom, with
fractal folding operating to connect
heterogeneous qualities and their
implications].
Heterogenesis therefore can 'date' the
processes involved in an assemblage of
enunciation, both de- and
reterritorialization. It produces the
crystal of an event, limiting transversal
links. For Proust, the search is dated
by events like stepping on the wobbly paving
stone, and this then produces a whole series
of expressive components and their
music-like links, a form of qualitative
hyper fractalization. This in turn
appears in opposition to the
topographical fractalization, and the result
is 'new artificial procedures of
subjectification' [that is as a result of
Proust's deliberate 'machinic'
technique]. A particular expression
can develop links with the whole
world. This looks like the result of
'an enunciating subjectivity' [not
necessarily located in a person], and
determinability seems to be decelerated and
take the form of intermediate temporality
[above] [note that as I suspected fractal
processes and determinability, 'amount to
the same thing'(185). Synapses are
responsible for these transitions [implying
some rather contingent connection between
different sorts of determinability].
The switch between different sorts of
determinability sets the tempo [for
Proust? I think we're generalising
here to all human life]. The refrains
are components of singularization
[interesting additional point] and they also
control by stopping and starting of
different forms of determination [in the
example, we can consider life as a physical
and chemical system which displays both
acceleration and deceleration].
This heterogenesis is not found in 'the
"normal" modalities of knowledge'
(186). We get this knowledge instead
through 'non discursive affects'. We
can see this more clearly with psychotic
conditions and their characteristic
coordinates, and with 'aesthetic
illumination'. We have to cross a
threshold of enunciation, [as a kind of
leap]. In practice, 'knowledge of the
other and knowledge through the other'are
continuous, music both informs the listener
and forms up their competence as the
listener. This shows that 'affect
should stop being thought of as a raw
energetic matter', but is complex and filled
with potential—love does not stop with mere
discharge of the libido but opens to unknown
worlds. We should think of a
generalised transference linking not just
individuals, but all animal and cosmic
becomings, which also have 'pathic indices'.
The gaze is not accidental, nor driven by
the superego, but is 'essentially faciality,
as the substance of all humanly significant
sense'. Every affect should be
understood as only partly human, but also
connected to women, animal and facialized
becoming, at the crossroads of sense.
Properly elucidating heterogeneity means we
can start to consider alterities 'that haunt
the affective horizons of the living world
and its cosmic beginnings'.
Considering heterogeneity revitalises affect
and its autonomous power. It is not
like topographical fractals which do not
have the power to define a world without
limits. Enunciative fractalization
develops the 'infinite operative power of
subjectification' (187). It is capable
of rewriting everything. It is the
source of 'the aleatory, bifurcation,
freedom' found in enunciative assemblages
We have considered enunciation as a form of
proto-energy in each of the four domains
rather than using one of the classic
dualisms like sensibility and
understanding. Refrains, both synaptic
and modular, make machinic propositions
effective and incarnate them. The
possibility of new arrangements must imply
some kind of molecular proto-energy,
addressed most specifically here in terms of
semiotic energy. [There is an example
of dice throwing showing that the effects
even of simple repetition of the result
increases a certain 'probabilitarian
tension', the presence of a
'deterritorialized virtual energy' which is
easy to detect. A singular result
might be produced with all sorts of
unforeseen potentials, and explaining that
result in turn involves linking with a
constellation of universes of reference, and
discussions of things like transgression or
cheating. The sequence of dice throws
acquires power in a complex
assemblage]. Such energetic
assemblages have been described as drives,
those complexes revealed by slips of the
tongue or by dream works, narrative tension
and so on.
Singularization and irreversibilization
Determinability can be defined as
information before it is assigned to a
referent. It can remain 'scattered and
powdery' in incorporeal universes, but it
also has a form of organization, 'a virtual
dis-position'(188). This is provided
through the synapses that focus it in
particular constellations. In sensible
modules it can be stratified and disposition
becomes territorialization, but one that
still displays a link between an instant and
an infinite distance [represented here using
the same symbol for infinite
acceleration]. This provides the
constant potential for metamorphosis in
stratified entities [and the example is the
famous connection between wasp and orchid
produced by a rhizome of machinic
propositions].
Nevertheless, any kind of
determinability found in a constellation
lacks the freedom of operation in the
chaosmos. It experiences constraint
such as irreversible ordering, or the
affects of well known constants including
pi. There can still be transference
from one basin of energy to another, changes
of register like those between physics and
chemistry, and this has raised problems in
physics about the conversion or conservation
of energy. His problem in particular
is how to explain how virtual proto-energy
produces actual forms of determination, and
how fractal deconstruction can be slowed in
diagrams only to take on new forms of energy
as a form of surplus value. Perhaps we
need to argue that reality is always
'predisposed to all mutations, even the
catastrophic'.
If we have a rupture in reversibility
between expressive and diagrammatic
functions, that is because it worlks as a
synapse rather than a simple connection
between the decent of expression and an
ascent of the diagram. The synapse
offers an 'enunciative surplus value'(189),
but at the price of energetic entropy and
irreversibility. Synapses can
therefore be seen as 'deterritorialized
releases of enunciation', acting as an
integral of sensible refrains.
Psychoanalysis has attempted to explain this
in terms of the phantasm or the archetype,
but this was not abstract enough.
Matter itself features hyper
complexity. We should see at work
machinic propositions which break away from
the constraints of signification and
diagrammatic functioning so as to influence
further existential enunciation [which also
operates through the pathic]. This
opens any particular enunciative scene to a
constellation of the universe of
reference. The synapse itself provides
a certain consistency, acting as a break on
possibilities, an 'a signifying catalysis'.
However, there is no alternate reference
point in concepts like absolute
otherness. Alterity is relative, and
this provides the possibility for different
forms of enunciation composed of the various
enunciative fragments in the four
domains. This happens on the margins
as a self organizing process. Russian
Formalists were close in seeing content as
only an aspect of form. The point is
to develop analytic praxes from this view
however—dealing with forms, perhaps slowing
them down or making them visible by altering
our perceptions, or other processes of
defamiliarisation. We can then acquire
metamodeling materials to guide 'an
initiatory enunciation'.
[There is a summary diagram of the different
dimensions of enunciation on page 190]
[Then there is a series of shorter pieces]
The refrains of being and sense
[Basically an analysis of one of his own
dreams, illustrating classic Freudian
mechanisms of overdetermination and
displacement, but also showing how the
elements from the various domains can also
be shown to appear. Too detailed, so
here are the edited highlights]
Dreams classically show the options for
subjectification that breaks with dominant
norms and significations. Their study
also shows the necessary components of an
open model of the unconscious. The
Freudian distinction between primary and
subsequent social processes need not be
upheld, since the dream does not arise from
some deep contents and processes but rather
indicate 'a machinics on the surface of its
text' (191). The part-objects in it
are not the results of a mutilating process
of castration but should be seen as
'autonomized operators of subjectification',
and the apparent break with sense only shows
subjectification 'in the nascent state', a
fractalization that breaks out of closure, a
matter of deterritorialization.
[Details of the dream follows. The
components are particular people, a large
square in a composite city, and a car whose
parking place has been forgotten .
There are also lapsuses, the most
interesting of which involves him calling
the character Gilles instead of his real
name!] The various associations are
then uncovered, such as which actual city it
is, which happens to be called Mer, although
the obvious associations with the sea and
his mother are extended because he
associates his father with residence in that
city. Other elements include an
earlier dream and his own four part matrix
charting the domains: an intellectual
reservation about the symmetry of the flows
between the parts is represented as the
presence of a mysterious zone in the city
square which has to be crossed in an unusual
way.
The car also changes its characteristic, in
that a Renault becomes a BMW. He drove
the BMW during the upheavals of 1968 [more
below]. The dream of losing the
Renault can be understood as representing
'four a-signifying indices' (195): it is
lost or cut out, as the 'putting into
parentheses of an ego object'; the name
becoming a set of initials has a kind of
sense [as does the substitution of a set of
initials for a name below]; there is a
hesitation over the connection between the
events; there is 'the most stupid,
mechanical association' between forgetting
where the car is parked and the theoretical
objection he had to an incomplete self
analysis in a correspondence between Freud
and Fleiss [!]
The strange substitution of the name of
Deleuze for the name of the character [Yasha
David, a Czech refugee in France and
collaborator in understanding Kafka] shows
the complexities of enunciation [but in
quite a different direction to Lacan, whose
understandings of the elaborate fantasies of
Schreber were important in his claim that
the unconscious is structured like a
language]. Guattari thinks of Bakhtin
and 'polyphonic dialogical sequences': these
linked together the various female people in
the dream and might also help understand
various constellations of different levels
of enunciation.
[Other associations include the presence of
a cave in the dream, associated with the
loss of the car, which somehow invokes a
text by Samuel Beckett and a psychological
test he had invented earlier in his
youth. Some of his diaries were stolen
and this leads him to think about how his
own past might be reconstructed by his
friends, including an unhappy episode in
which he displayed jealousies towards one of
his partners: this was displaced on to an
anxiety that David was jealous of his wife
in a classic Freudian mechanism]
Bakhtin's dialogism shows how lines of sense
intersect, form a synapse of sense that can
go on to catalyse a function, especially one
accessing constellations of universes of
reference. The dream itself shows
different kinds of phyla—the circuit around
the square, the lost car, David and his
association with Deleuze, a cave, inhibition
and a jealousy. Only the third one
shows the role of proper names. The
components are heterogeneous. We can
explain the first one in terms of visual
relations found in an existential
territory. The second involves an
absent machine or potentiality. The
third is the classic mental operation [a
Freudian slip] found in everyday
psychopathology and here it acts as a
synapse. The fourth one is a
'signified utterance' that becomes iconic as
it develops: in this sense it becomes 'a
chaotic black hole, the reverse of an
existential territory. The fifth is a
'coarté effect' as in Rorschach [I couldn't
find this term anywhere, but it might
indicate a reluctance to express thoughts
explicitly?], and it can apparently link to
non discursive universes of reference.
[These initial analyses are then developed,
197 F, as 'latent lines of
subjectification'. It took some time
to emerge, and the analysis seems to acquire
the classic Freudian notion of a rational
reconstruction of events in the past].
The analysis of the synapse might be worth
summarizing in more detail. It
features both a forgetting and a lapsus
which can be reconstructed as an articulate
phrase to describe looking for a car in a
particular location with a particular
person. How these events signify is
explored in more detail—the car stands both
for a relationship with a woman and a
particular phase in his life, a glamorous
phase which included the burgeoning
relationship with Deleuze. There is
also a particular operation which results in
'a machinic surplus value' (199): the trick
of moving from a fully spelled out name to
initials contaminates neighbouring proper
names, so that they also become abstract and
machinic [maybe]—he also referred to one of
his lovers in the 60s by her initials.
Altogether, associations with 1968 inform
understandings in 1984.
The various polyphonic lines go on to become
'embedded in extrinsic rhizomatic
coordinates': the town square develops into
a particular town and then a particular
relationship with his parents. We can
consider these elements as
'deterritorialized enunciative nuclei'
(200). These are present in dreams and
in reality. The production of
subjectivity includes a role for the 'latent
unconscious contents' as well as the
'consciously explicit utterances'.
They act by forming deterritorialized
universes, and 'heterogeneous modes of
semiotization' are based upon them. We
can see this by considering the different
enunciative fragments associated with the
move to initials with both the car and the
woman—the abbreviation becomes
deterritorialized, but subsequently, there
is a 'phonological reterritorialization'
since the initials AD also stand for another
name—Adelaide [another lover who followed
Arlette Donati or AD]
We talking here about enunciative fragments,
which are discontinuous, not located in
paradigms or syntagms. They are
indexed by proper names, associated with
relationships with people. It is a
kind of code or 'a signifying
rupture'. Freed from structural
constraint, these fragments develop
'synaptic semiotic chains', based on 'an
enunciative existential function'.
This can produce a fractal process that
proliferates and develops all the resources
of the imaginary, and that in turn will help
us grasp an unresolved problem [apparently,
inhibition stems from an unresolved
relationship between birth and death -- see
below].
We can also see how the components can help
develop a 'harmonic nucleus', initially a
partial one, linking say the components one
and four [the square, with parental
associations, and the cave]. We can
even consider these to be components of a
whole enunciative field. The movement
around the square is understood visually or
iconically, but there are also different
phonological developments—the town Mer
becomes mother (mere), while the name of
another place sounds a bit like the name of
yet another woman. He thought of these
background worlds initially as a kind of
'ice palace' which later became a cave or
zone, associated with the strange zone in
the square and with the forgetting that led
to the temporary loss of the car. It
is really a struggle to understand the self
enclosed existential territory represented
by Mer by understanding it as 'cracked',
(201) having a cave, accessible only through
proper names associated with it.
There is a second harmonic nucleus,
developing from the synapse in component
three [David and the lapsus that connects
him with Deleuze]. This synapse is
going to be applied to the other components,
especially those of two and five, the
machinic and the affective
respectively. Thinking of the car
reminds him of encountering a big demo in a
particular street in Paris. It was a
gay area, and it was also the scene of a
particularly violent confrontation with the
police. It is a way of demonstrating
the coarté effect, and inhibition both
towards physical fighting and towards
homosexuality. However, there is a
process of association set off by this
location, including his encounters with
other political activists and various
ethnologists. He even took his first
patient to a location in the same
street. There is also an association
with visiting a musician. So we have
'the whole world of diverse activities of
creative machinic linkage' [evidently a
happy time].
Thinking around the associations of AD
helped to diversify semiotically, and even
overcome some of the blockages of the more
territorialized components, like the town of
Mer. However, the role of jealousy is
reterritorializing and blocking. The
whole thing goes back to his relations with
Donati and the subsequent lover and
expresses his own tensions between believing
in sexual liberation, but also becoming very
jealous of his partner -- he searched for
Donati on one of her escapades in his
BMW! This jealousy is linked to the
lapsus. It is David who is seen as the
jealous one, while any jealousy of Deleuze
must be suppressed in a 'nucleus of
neutrality' and convention.
What the dream shows is that we are both
fixed on particular 'native lands', but also
that desiring machines can develop processes
of existential importance. However,
there is often a particular escape from
control, forgetting, inhibition,
inconsistency. This is why we require
substantial analysis, and we must remember
that self analysis is also required, as in
the bit about jealousy. Sometimes,
forgetting can be the only way to prevent
anxiety about death [referenced to a
particular element in which his dying father
offered him a 50 franc note towards his
driving lessons, not realizing that it was
'no longer a great deal of money'].
Refrains and existential affects
[I still think the refrain is quite a
difficult term that just tries to do too
much—linking the human and animal, and
overdoing the musical analogy so that
refrains both calm people down and reassure
them by reminding them of their territorial
roots and assist creative thinking and
breaks with convention. The latter
arise when the refrain becomes
deterritorialized and thus acts as a kind of
semiotic resource for new experiences.
The insistence that faciality is the most
important component of a refrain is even
more overdone. It might be so at
moments with Proust,
but to generalize from that to talk about
all human understandings and subjective
responses is a tad excessive. The
discussion here also the links back to his
section on the refrain in The Machinic
Unconscious ]
The affects of the imagination are real and
persistent [as Freud said about affect in
dreams]. 'Affect sticks to
subjectivity' (203), that of the speaker as
well as the listener. Spinoza noticed
that affect is transitive—if we can imagine
someone is experiencing an affect we become
affected ourselves, so sadness turns to
commiseration, hatred to a reciprocal hatred
and so on. 'Affect is thus essentially
a pre-personal category', preexisting
identities, showing itself in unlocalizable
transfers. This was grasped better by
animist societies as a kind of circulating
spirit or power of a sacred place. We
can grasp it as showing polyvocal components
of semiotization searching for existential
consummation. It is both fuzzy and
perfectly graspable in experience, say in
'thresholds of passage' or 'reversals of
polarity'.
It is also a component of animal becomings
as we shall see.
It is not graspable in discourses that offer
distinctive oppositions in linear sequences
including sequences of memories. It is
more like ['assimilable to' (204)] Bergson's
duration. It emerges from intensive
categories arising from positioning oneself
existentially. Affects cannot be
quantified without losing their qualitative
dimensions. It is those that offer a
potential for and promote singularization
and heterogenesis, and the composition of
haecceities. Heterogeneous durations
are appropriated for existential purposes,
and this is best understood through ethics
or aesthetics rather than science.
Bakhtin is on to this in his description of
aesthetic enunciation which he says is
encompassed by the content, from the
outside. This promotes our feeling of
value, and we see ourselves as creating
form. Seeing an affect in aesthetic
terms makes it active as a component of
enunciation, not just a 'passive correlate
but its motor'. Affect is itself non
discursive and offers no energy to transfer,
so it is better seen as 'deterritorialized
machinism'.
We see ourselves as singular persons as a
result of the complexity of the production
of subjectivity. In particular
circumstances, this also produces artistic
creation. We are certainly not just
produced as subjects just by linguistic
structures. The components of
subjectivity are heterogeneous and
diverse. There is an analogy with
those attempts to reduce a literary work to
the operation of signifiers, but this will
not lead us to supposing some creative
personality [Bakhtin still]. Instead,
linguistic material has five aspects that
produce verbal affect: 'sound, meaning,
syntagmatic links, the phatic valorization
of an emotional and volitional order' (205)
[the last one, which presumably makes five
aspects by splitting into emotional and
volitional, is really just another phrase
for the production of verbal affect in
readers, surely?]. Sounds gain impact from
rhythm, intonation, mimicry and
'articulatory tension'. Things like
narrative, metaphor and 'internal elan' also
convey value and meaning. However,
this is not just something material and
physical, since it also requires 'the sense
of appreciation'[which apparently involves
becoming a whole human being—the old high
aesthetic again].
This non discursive power of affects is
hyper complex, arising from complex
processuality, or the 'proliferation of
mutating becomings'. It consists of
'modular components of proto-enunciation',
but these engender 'a dis-position of
enunciation'. Affect speaks to and
through us [with an example of a combination
of dusk and dark curtains in his room
producing 'an uncanny Affect' which replaces
the certainties he had just before, while
the leitmotifs of Das Rheingold
bring about all sorts of references,
sentimental, mythical, historical and
social]. Originally confined, these
experiences dis-pose territorialization and
overflow, engaging environment, memory and
cognition, so that a person becomes 'a
tributary' to a broader assemblage of
enunciation, and the individual subject that
speaks in the first person becomes only 'the
fluctuating interception, the conscious
"terminal" of those diverse components of
temporalization'(206). This is especially so
with affects that are not immediately
presented to the senses, where 'procedures
of elucidation threatened to flee in all
directions'.
However, perhaps the apparently sensible
affects are really produced by the more
problematic ones, in a reversal of the usual
view that the simple produces the
complex. Affect is always struggling
towards a simple identity ['constantly
questing to recapture itself'], but this is
permanently delayed by 'proliferating phyla
of problematization'. An 'infinite
movement of fractal virtualization' comes
first, which only gets simplified by
existential self affirmation. We can
see this in some psychopathology.
Affect has to cross a threshold to attain
consistency. Failure to do so produces
pathological symptoms [described in more
detail 206], which seemed to involve an
inchoate relation between the different
dimensions of affect, which include the
relative autonomy of some of them.
This is not to say that normal states always
display harmony and equilibrium—indeed,
excessive harmony and equilibria may produce
melancholy. However the normal psyche
can pass from one dimension of affect to
another instead of being dominated by
one. [NB there is an increasing
tendency to describe affect in terms of
'pathic temporalization'—this may be a
technical term, but it also seems to relate
to the practice of holding back or
accelerating particular aspects of
subjective time, producing, say, inhibition
on the one hand and maniac acceleration of
enunciation on the other].
As ever, studies of the psychopathological
can help us understand the complexities of
affect, including the impact on semiotic
activity, as in inhibitions, or the general
preservation of the gap between expression
and the interior. In general,
'semiotic discordances' are produced by
intrusive extra-linguistic components:
'somatic, ethological, mythographic,
institutional, economic, aesthetic, etc.'
(207). In normal speech, these are
usually more disciplined [including being
subjected to capitalist laws of
equivalence].
The refrain is a group of 'reiterated
discursive sequences, closed on themselves,
having as their function an extrinsic
catalysis of existential affects'[they have
catalytic effects on our real lives].
They can take different forms, segments of
prose, emblems, faciality traits,
leitmotifs, signatures and proper
names. They can form transversal links
between different substances, as in Proust
where different refrains correspond with
each other [this had such an impact on
Deleuze, apparently, that he added a bit to
his book on Proust -- I think Bogue says
this]. They can operate with sensory
inputs like the taste of the madeleine, or
they could be more problematic, as in the
notion of an 'ambience' in a salon.
They can operate with an order of faciality
as with the face of Odette [Swann decomposes
her face into a number of specific features
and then links them to various other objects
of beauty—her nose to the nose of a portrait
in a famous painting and so on. Other
faces are also briefly de and recomposed in
this way, like those of military officers,
or of the sleeping Albertine. I still
don't see the great significance of these
small sections].
Refrains join the sensible and problematic
dimensions of enunciation. If we take
into account Hjemslev on the form of
expression and the form of content, we have
four possible semiotic functions of them,
relating either to the referent or to
enunciation itself: there is denotation,
relating form of content and referent; the
diagrammatic function relating matter of
expression and referent; sensible affect, or
refrain, relating enunciation and forms of
expression; problematic aspects relating
enunciation and the form of content, AKA the
abstract machine. We might consider
these as components of the usually undivided
term 'the pragmatic' [a bit of a residual
term for conventional linguistics as we
saw]. It is the combination
['concatenation'] of these functions that
explains how systems of expression move from
the social and pre-personal, the ethical and
the aesthetic to the personal/existential
[maybe, 208].
The refrain and the abstract machine are
'bifaced', and this explains the location of
'existential praxial operators'at the
junction of expression and content.
There is no guiding structural synchrony
here but rather 'contingent assemblages',
heterogeneity, and irreversible
singularization. Hjemslev shows that
expression and content are reversible and
this explains the heterogeneity of
substances and matters. Bakhtin on the other
hand argues that enunciation is layered,
multi centred and polyphonic. Can we
explain the entire 'multivalence' of
enunciation by combining these two?
Can we see how the heterogeneity of delirium
or artistic creation can still produce sense
'outside commonsense'? We cannot just see
these as deficient versions of the normal.
It is mistaken to see enunciation as another
residual in the formal analysis of
linguistic structures. On the
contrary, it lies at 'the active core of
linguistic and semiotic creativity'
(209). It singularizes. It is
not a matter of being organized into
syntagmatic or semantic trees, but rather
pursuing the rhizomes that underpin the
particular logical stages [Guattari also
suggests that we call these by proper
names, perhaps suggesting that they are
particular conceptions by particular
linguists?].
There are refrains at work that stabilize
the environment for existential purposes,
and we can use these to grasp the most
abstract problematic affects[it occurs to me
-- is a 'problematic affect' one that
suggests a whole problematic or that arises
from a whole problematic?]
[Obscure] examples follow; Duchamp's
painting of the bottle rack triggers various
constellation of universes of reference that
relate to his personal past and to more
general cultural and economic
connotations. We can use terms like
Benjamin's 'aura' or Barthes's punctum here
too. This is a kind of 'singular
refrain making'. We find it in
architecture as well, and it describes
things like [micro] perceptions when walking
down a street. We find such effects in
ethological and archaic refrains as
well. This is where we get the entire
sense that the objects surrounding us are
familiar and not eternally strange.
Refrains of expression are particularly
important with sensible affects, and might
include, say, the intonation of a particular
voice. Refrains of content, AKA
abstract machines, are found in problematic
affects, including those that head towards
individualization as well as social
behaviour: after all, the two refrains are
not antagonistic or mutually
exclusive. An Orthodox icon does not
only represent a saint, but also opens a
whole 'territory of enunciation'. Facial
refrains get their particular intensity from
the way that they are able to shift
existential territories, both of the
individual body and of various social
identities. A signature on a document,
say a contract, can also act as 'a refrain
of capitalist normalization'.
Instead of the normal unitary notion of a
person, found in conventional psychology and
psychoanalysis, we should think more in
terms of complex affects which can even
produce 'irreversible diachronic ruptures'
[what most of us would call historical
watersheds] (210), sometimes associated with
charismatic figures like Christ or
Lenin. In the case of Lenin, the
specific procedures associated with his
specific interventions and language provided
a threshold of initiation for those who
wanted to belong to the Party, and even a
series of constraints for those who wanted a
break with it, like Trotsky.
We should think of enunciation as something
complex as well. It is like a
conductor who articulates specific musical
performances together, sometimes allowing
one to be dominant, sometimes not
'despotically overcoding' the score but
allowing some improvisation, and generally
aiming for a kind of collective emergent
effect, once a threshold has been crossed,
permitting the emergence of an entire
aesthetic object, combining things like
tempo, phrasing, harmonies and rhythms.
Assemblages of enunciation can include
multiple social voices, including some
pre-personal ones, appearing as 'aesthetic
ecstatic, a mystic effusion or an
ethological panic', appearing as a syndrome
like agoraphobia or as an ethical
imperative.
Affect is not a state to which one submits,
but a complex subjective territory,
proto-enunciation. It is also the
place from which a potential praxis can
emerge, with two joined dimensions.
First, there is 'extrinsic
dissymmetrization', where a particular
intention directed at universes of reference
[AKA 'fields of non discursive values'] can
be clarified [its relevance becomes
clear?]. Subjectivity takes on an
ethical dimension, which in turn becomes a
singularization of a trajectory, in turn
understood as part of a personal historical
process. Secondly, there is 'intrinsic
symmetrization', a bit like the aesthetic
attainment of Bakhtin above, or
fractalization [as we explore?]. Here
a deterritorialized object achieves
consistency achieved from the impact of
affect. The same goes with our sense
of being able to develop autonomous
enunciation. [A selection from Bakhtin
extends the point, so that particular lyrics
in songs, prayers or experiences like
repentance become self sufficient, requiring
no external satisfaction—the form itself
takes on a completeness, using the qualities
of the material itself, and the same goes
for the content produced by an author.
Classic misrecognition of the habitus? ].
However, we might also extend a bit some of
the other work on aesthetic form in
Bakhtin. He talks of a sense of
isolation of the form [its uniqueness?], for
example, but Guattari sees this as an
'active isolation'(211) which will set off a
process ending in a grasp of 'a-
signifiance'[sic, not 'significance'] [that
is we realize some things cannot be grasped
inside conventional signifiance?].
Other Bakhtin qualities like unification,
individuation and and totalization can also
be grasped as multiplication. Overall,
the consistency and unity of an object 'is
only the movement of subjectification' [that
is, this complex business of
subjectification, nothing to do with social
constructivism in the usual sense].
Nothing is simply given. Consistency
arises as the 'for itself' comes to dominate
an existential territory, fleetingly: the
for itself then appears as 'a stroboscopic
memory'. Reference can now be
understood as only the support for a
reiterative refrain [again back to front
from what you would normally think, where
the reiteration of a refrain confers
relations of reference]. It is the
presence of the gap [compare this with 'the
interval' that characterizes the subject in
Deleuze's work on Hume and Bergson] that
produces in us the experience or 'sentiment'
of being , a sensible affect. The same
gap also produces an active notion of being,
a problematic affect
Reiteration deterritorializes, in both a
synchronic and diachronic dimension, and
appears as a set of related intensive
ordinates. Some of these coordinates
are intentional, and these fractalize
affective territories, symmetrically as in
the Baker transformation for example.
This produces a sense of a permanent work in
progress ['inchoate tension' is his
preferred term] where affect takes on a
being, acquires consistency. Each
partition receives homothetic [projective]
effects from refrains, so that a whole set
of points of view is
established. However, others are
'trans-monadic' (212) or transversal
coordinates [we nearly forgot those!] so
that affect drifts from one existential
territory to another, producing dates and
durations which are singularities.
Proustian refrains are supposed to be the
best example.
Subjectification involves the intersection
of actual and virtual enunciative points of
view. It attempts to reduce
divisions. However, it is
'irremediably fragmentary, perpetually
shifting, spaced out'. We appear to
take on an existence after crossing a
particular threshold rather than actually
managing to establish a clear division
between us and the rest of reality and
circumscribe what is uniquely
subjective. Concepts of self and other
both result from an 'ethical intentionality
and the aesthetic promotion of an
end'. Classic conceptions of the ego
are worthless because there is no such thing
as a coherent ego. Rather we have 'a
discursive set' of relations with a
referent, often in the form of a
gestalt. It follows that the
subcategories of the classical ego are also
unacceptable. Classical conceptions
proceed to offer a meta model where some
general displaced representation of the
process of the ego is identified with a
particular scene, but this means we can
barely speak about it any further.
Nevertheless, we classically think of the
ego as the whole world, without limits,
certainly not just associated with a
body. [As in the normal sense of
egoism] we find it difficult to believe that
there is somewhere where we do not exist
[like some external reality?]. This
alternative is unthinkable, and people
prefer not to talk about it.
Affect is not simply elementary raw
energy. It should be understood
instead as the 'deterritorialized matter of
enunciation' (213). This matter
provides for insight and understanding that
can be worked on, but not as in traditional
psychoanalysis. Instead, we should
explore the 'ethico-aesthetic dimensions' by
examining refrains [apparently, Levinas also
sees a link between faciality and
ethics]. When looking at psychological
automatism, delirium or the phantasm, we
could see them as fixed states, or as a
series of practices opening up refrains to
new possibilities.
Freud began with the notion of an assemblage
of enunciation that was positively mutant,
and he explored various refrains found in
dreams and in pathologies, with only a
tenuous link with semantic contents [which
were merely the manifestations of something
latent?]. His practice involved seeing
how refrains play out on new scenes of
affect, as in free association or
suggestion. However, the semiotic
components of these refrains were not seen
as sufficiently heterogeneous, especially
since the turn towards the domination of the
signifier. Psychoanalysis should
multiply expressive components and
differentiate them. It should not
focus its efforts on individual patients and
their problems since this limits 'the
dialectic of the gaze'. Analysis
should work not just with speech but with
objects like modeling clay, or with modern
electronic media, the theatre, modern
families and so on. This should
stimulate the a-signifying components of the
refrains. This in turn will help them
to catalyze new universes of reference, by
fractalizing. Instead of just
interpreting the phantasm or the
displacement of affect, both should become
more operative and be applied to a new
range. The point would be to detect
and resolve 'encysted singularities' closed
to outside influences and evidence.
These may well be immediately contrary to
the patient's interests, but they can be
reworked to explore 'pragmatic virtualities'
(214).
How can we explain the reduction of
psychoanalysis to the play of the signifier,
in increasingly stereotyped
applications? 'It is inseparable' from
the general shape of capitalist universes,
aimed at 'the equivalence of
significations. The world where one
thing is worth no more than another; where
every existential singularity is
methodologically devalued'. In
particular contingency, like those of old
age, illness or madness, are not granted any
kind of existential status, but become
instead 'abstract parameters' to be managed
by welfare organizations in an all pervading
atmosphere of 'anxiety and unconscious
guilt'. We can see this in terms of
disenchantment in Weber as generalized
equivalents dominate and as value gets
increasingly captured. Any hope for a
future restoring social and aesthetic
analytic practices must take advantage of
the developments of new information
technology.
Genet regained
[This is hard to follow if you don't know
much about Genet the, so I only got a few
bits. Genet refused to be considered
as a writer because he thought this would
make him 'camp on the bourgeois side of the
barricade' (216), and his writing, according
to Sartre, is best understood as a
transformed onanism.]
In
general, we experience 'fragments of
sense' or 'modules', and normally, we
learn to police the 'heretical, dissident
and perverse of voices' (222) they
produce. However Genet only takes
partial control, and reverses some normal
valuations, as when punishment becomes
erotic. 'In one case, it is the
signifier that leads the dance, in the
other it is the signified'. The idea
is always to constitute 'an expression
that everywhere exceeds its linguistic
components'. By making the signifier
and signified converge, and expression is
produced that will 'impregnate a context'(223),
and the context in turn will bring about
'impulses, it's paradigmatic perversions'
affecting discursive chains with a
linguistic or not'.
A worked example appears on page 223 which
opens the '"clandestine" germination of
semantic content' by considering the origin
of the term Fatah {as in Palestinian
liberation movement}. Those
'significations surfacing in Arabic' are
explored, which leads to a new possible
meaning for the acronym fatah—'here the
signified has moved into the position of the
structural key for the signifier'. The
exercise connects or constellates 'three
Universes of reference: sexual, divine and
revolutionary', as the words from the same
route as the components of fatah
disclose. Here, it is the phonemes,
which unlock meaning
and
they also produce affects—sadness
referring to the possible death of
fighters for Genet. The theme of
alternating shadow and light is pursued in
other writing about American blacks.
[Fatah receives approval from Guattari
because it allows for the possibility of
its own death, unlike the slogan for
Israel which insists that Israel will live
for ever]. There are other more
abstract 'modules' at work as well, like
various games threads, 'an abstract
machine for flaking, layering the real'
(224), and there is a comparison with
Proust and the interweaving of
'leitmotifs, ...fecund
moments...refrains'. Memory
is not allowed to dominate, but the
continual confrontation with 'heterogeneous
realities' is pursued, a continuing opening
up, an insistence on the presence of death
and finitude and 'the risk of total and
definitive incomprehension'.
The
creative aspects are best understood as
'enlarging fields of virtuality, allowing
new Universes of reference and singular
modalities of expression to emerge by
conjugating heterogeneous voices...
it is a matter of producing another real,
correlative to another subjectivity'
(225). Sometimes the pursuit of
signification ends in a loss of control,
when even the author is overwhelmed by
associations [the example is Genet writing
the term 'Hitlerian'and being overwhelmed
by thoughts of the church of the
Trinity—something to do with both of them
featuring eagles possibly]. They can
also be dialogues in the Bakhtin sense,
and this can engender 'a surplus value of
sense, a supplement of singularity, an
existential taking consistency'.
Proust had developed the relation between
Charlus and Jupien as one resembling the
wasp and the orchid [a marvelous scene
where they encounter each other by
accident, rapidly identify each other as
complementary homosexuals, and go off for
a quick one, all without exchanging words,
all through extraordinary postures and
looks]. For Genet, a flower is
linked to a particular convict, then
flowers and conflicts are linked in
general, and this in turn helps Genet
choose '" the universe wherein I
delight"'.
[Lots more examples of the writing ensue,
PP. 226-7] Overall the writing is the
result of 'the modular concatenation of
cosmic and signaletic fluctuations and the
"fabulous" harmonising of voices that were
not generically destined to meet each
other'(227). This leaves 'the
subject without any hold on the creative
process', neither from passive
contemplation nor from active
orchestration. The writer is not
enunciating, doing more like 'primitive
swallowing', attempting self mastery or
perhaps the deliberate production 'of a
mutant subjectivity'. These
processes must 'avoid being imprisoned by
the phantasm'. The example is a
chance encounter between Genet and a
couple of Palestinians [Hamza and his mum]
in a refugee camp which produced profound
affects although these were never fully
understood. For Guattari what has
happened is the development of 'an
existential operator or synapse...
an Assemblage that is at once psychic,
material and social, able to put in place
a new type of enunciation'(228).
Hamza is about to depart on a mission, and
he disappears for 14 years; his mother
treats Genet as if he were her son and
this produces 'genuine love at first sight
for this unknown couple', a '"fixed mark"
for love'. The whole sequence is
converted into a fable with mystical
visions of the son always together with
the mother, fabulous connections between
the couple and the Christ Pieta, the
ability of Genet to play all the
parts. The whole process shows how
the emergent set of images, the fable
'become self sufficient, self referent,
self processual' (229), 'a specific away
of discursivizing subjectivity' in a
particularly open way, by constantly
scrutinising the religious icon' and
showing new signs of possibility.
'Reality not only opens up, it is charged
with infinite virtualities', but there is
still a restraint by working with
mythological characters. Eventually
there will be 'a new splitting of the
world' (230). This arises from
synaptic connections, which are not just
'simple rearrangements or harmonics of
sense', because they generates 'the
pragmatic effects, an existential surplus
value, the release of new Constellations
of Universes of reference'. These
will exceed the mundane issues of identity
and persons and produce 'much more
molecular praxes'. Thus the specific
rather mundane fate of the Palestinian
warrior does not detract from the power of
creation because it 'doesn't reside in its
visible cogs but in a machine of abstract
intensities, conjugating Universes of
jouissance, poetry, freedom, death to
come'. The actual couple has been
cut out for a particular purpose,
isolating it from a whole continuum of
space, time and 'all the connections with
country, family and kin' [Genet's own
words apparently]. [and Genet thinks
that death will be welcome as long as he
has achieved something in 1000th of a
second].
Architectural enunciation
[Again I have little independent knowledge
of this]
There is been a bewildering variety of
architectural styles, and underneath we
can probably discover 'ethico-political
choices' (232). We can better
understand what has happened by
considering 'architectural enunciation'
and its connections with the 'trade of the
architect', rather than a sequence of
dominant styles. Architects should
not be seen as 'artists of built forms'
but as people offering 'services in
revealing the virtual desires of spaces,
places, trajectories and
territories'. They should develop
their singular approach connecting
'individual and collective corporeality',
and regulate desires against interests,
become an analyst of subjectification,
and, through architectural enunciation,
contribute to 'contemporary productions of
subjectivity'. Then we get on to two
'modalities of consistency of the
enunciation of an architectural
concept'[concept in the usual sense here,
presumably, although there is still this
initial insistence on singularity]
Polyphonic components [a term also used in
the section above on Genet to refer to
modules] include the categories of a
certain Boudon used by architects—those of
refer to real space, those of refer to an
external [eg symbolic] referent, those
that refer to representations of
architectural space, those that relate to
ways of mediating between the spaces,
using 'scale'. The should best be
seen as specifics derived from an
underlying virtual enunciation, explaining
the tremendous variety of architectural
products. Guattari supplies his own
specific forms of enunciation on the
'continuous spectrum of virtual
enunciations':
Geopolitical enunciation, referring to the
terrain or the cultural climate;
urbanistic enunciation, relating to things
like town planning regulations; economic
enunciation where buildings express
capitalist relations of force and respond
to market value; functional enunciation
relating to functional links with our
other urban structures and functions
linking 'micro facilities (light, air,
communication, etc.)'(234). These
will be expressed through various networks
including social stratification various
social bodies, and people like planners
and experts. then we have technical
enunciations relating to equipment and
materials relating to engineers and
chemists; signifying enunciations as when
buildings incorporate symbolic forms or
reflect specific ideological models like
new towns; existential territorialization
related to space [euclidean space
positions the object in a univocal fashion
within 'an axiomatico-deductive logic'
(236) , apparently, while projective
spaces offer metamorphic perspectives
privileging the imaginary over reality,
and labyrinthine topological spaces
attempt to envelop tactile bodies as a
deliberate affect]. We also have
scriptural enunciations to coordinate the
other components, and here the very
development of expression offers
'coefficient of creativity... new
potentialities', the introduction
of ethics and aesthetics for example.
There are 'synchronic existential
dimensions' as well (237). Drawing on
Bakhtin, there are 'cognitive ordinates'
where a discursive logic guides the
scriptural enunciation described
above. There are also 'axiological
ordinates' adding 'anthropocentric
valorization' including ethics and economic
and political systems. Finally
'aesthetic ordinates' where objects 'start
to emit sense and form on their own
count'. Again this can lead to new
articulations between 'the built, the lived
and the incorporeal'. These persist,
even though capitalism attempts to impose
'functional, informational and
communicational transparency', because they
remain 'at the heart of the architectural
object'. These ordinates are found
underneath an 'external discursive face'
although it also appears in a non discursive
mode, which we can access as we experience
'spatialized affects'. There is a
constant tendency for cognitive consistency
to 'topple over into the imaginary'.
Axiological consistency can lead to the
challenge to those dimensions that are
supposed to depict alterity and regulated
desire [the implication here seems to be
that people get tired of them].
Aesthetic thresholds can exceed those
particular forms and intensities which they
were designed to depict.
Overall then, the specificity of
architecture is that it tries to grasp
affects of specialised enunciation.
These will always be paradoxical objects
that can be understood not in purely
rational terms but 'through meta- modeling,
aesthetic detour, mythical or ideological
narrative'(238), like the part object.
It requires transversal investigation across
heterogeneous levels, but not to domesticate
them—rather to 'engage them all deeply in
fractal processes of heterogeness'.
Architecture should be a catalysis to
trigger semiotic 'chain reactions'to help us
escape an open up new possibilities.
Dwellings for example engender a 'feeling of
intimacy and existential singularity'
connected with the aura of familiar
surroundings or landscapes occupied by
memories, and this can 'generate
proliferation and lines of flight in every
register of the desire to live, the refusal
to give in to the dominant inertia'.
It is the same process of 'existential
territorialization and synchronic taking
consistency' that we find in the refrain or
in other ways of occupying particular
places.
Architects therefore should help us
recompose existential territories in the
face of destructive capitalist flows.
They should identify points of singularity,
and should use 'every cartographic method'
to do this. Commitment and the
development of 'a particular regime of
ethico-aesthetic autonomization' will
support this process. Architectural
truth 'will then be an effect of existential
consummation and superabundance of being'
(239). Architect should welcome the
chance to be 'carried off by the process of
eventization, that is to say, of the
historical enrichment and resingularization
of desire and of values' (239).
Ethico-aesthetic refrains in the theatre
of Witkiewicz [W, to spare my speech
recognition system]
[I know even less about the theatre or this
person, which is a shame because I'm
particularly interested in these refrains,
which connect existential territories and
incorporeal universes of reference, as I
recall. I have only found a few nuggets ]
Subjectification is constantly modified in
the process of enunciation, so it can never
be completed or disconnected from the
world. 'From this point of view,
theatre work may constitute one of its most
significant paradigms' (241). Sensible
refrains act as operators, linking the phase
transitions between assemblages of
enunciations. For example, 'a perverse
enunciation' can occur, even in the middle
of solemn ceremonies, or, going the other
way, a Freudian slip can disrupt a register
of enunciation. There are also
'problematic refrains, or abstract machines'
which are less easy to grasp. Some
narrative montages in W's theatre
demonstrate this. These refrains are
not just to be seen as something which
signifies latent content, but rather are
'essentially existential shifters' which
extend the consistency of universes of
reference, through 'circumscription,
singularization and support'. These
universes cannot easily be localized; they
are incorporeal with no particular limit in
space and time, and having no 'organ' (242).
Some act as symptoms of particular neurotic
apprehensions of the world [which are
existential, Guattari insists]. Some
faciality refrains help even newborn babies
relate to the maternal world. A
particular 'modal pentatonic refrain' leads
to the 'Debussyist universe'. We can
enter the judicial world through various
refrains referring to gesture, clothing and
intonation. All of this requires
'specifically assembled catalysers'.
These refrains can be recognized when they
disrupt 'expressive concatenations', their
syntagms or discourses. This can
cause a particular discourse to stop
developing relations and rather to 'pile up
on itself and go round and round to
infinity', or in bad cases, 'an implosion of
the expressive system'. In good cases,
the refrain can activate a particular
'segment of expression or content' and help
to generate the process leading to a 'self
referenced enunciative nucleus'[a new
conscious and reflective basis for
enunciation?]
In the actual play [The Pragmatists],
the five principal characters develop
polyphony around the original theme, carried
by some 'degree zero of expression, this
inexhaustible flow of speech, this
uninterrupted internal chattering' [sounds a
laugh] which apparently gets connected,
rather to his shame, to a conversation
with one of the female characters
[Mammalia], and which is seen as some
'constant stream of existence'. More
positively, it is also seen as 'an
indispensable chord in the symphony that
constitutes his essence'[then a bit that
reminds me of Gale and Wyatt on the endless
creativity of writing—'[he experience of
life is] " actually just the fact of talking
itself... With words the wealth of
possibilities is far greater than with
events"']
Then there is a bit about double characters
and how this common theme in plays is
subverted by W—a double system of values
produces 'an ethico-political wrenching',
between aesthetics and morality, pure form
vs. equality and justice. One
character in particular wants to pursue
aesthetic authenticity as 'a desire for
abolition. "To live means to create
the unknown!"' (243) [so Gale & Wyatt's
endless project is a search for aboliltion
of the subject -- except it's far too
domesticated?]. This death drive is
contrasted with a robust life drive in
another character. Apparently, it all
links to a campaign against alcohol in
Germany before 1914, which was associated
with various youth movements 'which in a way
prefigure National Socialism'.[Apparently
this also appears in The Magic Mountain,
where Mann denounces 'abstinent
scum']. The ferociously healthy one
appears at first as a pragmatist, open to
exploit the personal joyful benefits of
everything, including art. This turns
into a project for 'a fantastic and macabre
cabaret', and he wants the death drive
character to direct it.
Various relationships, including incestuous
ones complicate matters, but the idea is
that 'in every domain the pragmatists appear
to be called on to triumph over passionate
idealists'(244). However, there is
another character, the principal one, the
'Chinese Mummy' who offers an 'abstract
machinic refrain', which dominates and
escapes control by the characters. She
turns on her sponsor, the life affirming
one, and, via an affair in which the death
affirming one drinks her blood, becomes 'a
deterritorialized being', able to break away
from the dualism offered by the other two
characters. She does this by a
particular form of enunciation that says
there is a connection between abolition and
pure creation from nothing, that everything
is connected with everything else, that
reality is nothing but these connection of
segments. She is complemented by one
of the characters as 'the most real
Character of us all', bringing reality into
their one sided perceptions.
She creates in effect 'an incorporeal
hyper-or sur-reality', and this is similar
to the work of Kafka or Roussel. She
acts as an intermediary to join together
virtual threads that connect dreams and real
life. One thing this does is to
prevent the passion for self abolition by
one of the characters, tortured by the
prospect of sleep without dreams [like
Hamlet!]. Apparently the associations
between women, mothers and death has to be
challenged, and more generally guilt
dissociated from objects. She does
this in a bizarre way, constructing a sound
poem, reminiscent of Artaud, from the
syllables of the name of the maternal figure
who everyone loves [keep up!]. In this
way, the name of the character Mammalia is
deterritorialized, ceases to become a
signifier [laden with all sorts of freudian
guilt etc] , becomes part of 'an
a-signifying refrain arising from a purely
poetic rhythm'(245). Also, the
characters becomes deterritorialized [by
being reinterpreted by the Mummy, as a kind
of symbolic violence]
The guilt is never entirely sublimated,
however, and W offers no simple
remedies. Instead we are talking about
'a direct transmutation bearing on
heterogeneous orders of reality' with no
redeeming central theme, especially not
'"any lousy teetotalling spirituality"'
[quoting W ][then an irritating diversion
into another play!].
So we can see various kinds of
refrains, about health for example, together
with various asignifying refrains, poetry in
this case, and a sequence of colours in the
other play. There is a problematic
refrain as well, turning on how difficult it
is to convert 'a passion for abolition into
aesthetic creation', and how to manage
desire for the 'woman-other'(246). We might
be able to neutralise the femininity of some
of the women [Mammalia is mute at first],
perhaps even kill them, 'if possible at her
request'—but women have to be killed
infinitely because of the eternal return of
the tension, a threat that egos will close
up on themselves. Overall, the problem
is to 'ward off death by processualizing
creation', but without prostituting
it. The theatre of W addresses this
directly, warning against both implosion and
the 'prefabricated myths of psychoanalysis,
or initiatives in psychological
re-adaptation or re-socialization'.
Instead we have to pursue 'an open
prospective re-singularising analysis', like
Artaud's theatre of cruelty—'"Dadaism in
life"'.
Keiichi Tahara's faciality machine
We can see a photographic portrait as
providing a representation [at several
levels, as in Barthes?], But we can also use
certain traits of the face for quite
different ends, to evoke memories or trigger
affect. Tahara shows this second
aspect best, and uses aspects of the
subject's face to 'prepare the landscapes
that obsess him'(247), as a further example
of subjectification and its effects.
In effect, enunciation is transferred from
the spectator to the photograph, which has
its own effects 'which starts to scrutinise
you, which interpellates you, penetrates
you'. We can examine all the
photographs of personalities in a recent
album [only some of which is online].
They show us three essential components: the
face is cut out or deterritorialized; the
gaze is subject to 'a fractal rupture'; the
original significations attached to a proper
name or subject become attached to an
apparatus instead.
The human face can already be seen as a
gestalt figure detached from an animal
muzzle. Modifications unnecessary for
a culturally acceptable face, however, such
as the proper dimensions of a smile that
avoids becoming a grimace. Tahara
shows how that rates of facial it he can be
affected by framing and lighting effects to
break the original montage and reveal
different potentials. His portraits
therefore tend towards becomings of various
kinds, 'non human, animal, vegetable,
mineral, cosmic'(248), and these in turn
constitute 'prospective unconscious
dimensions'.
Examples of framing include rounding off the
angles 'in an effect of fuzzification',
using mirrors, imposing other frames on the
face or person, using 'quadranglar objects'
or a rectangle of light, or combinations of
these procedures. We can even see the
'nesting of frames' demonstrating 'stages of
fractalization', with layers or branches
overlaying and enveloping persons.
Result can be 'generalised disruption'or a
particular kind of static
petrification. Sometimes the light
cuts the face vertically, or renders the
face as a series of vertical strips: this
cut is often a straight line, or can be
multiplied into a series of columns.
Rarely, the cut is horizontal, which 'brings
to mind a musical score cut vertically by a
stave'. Further deterritorialization
involves making a small part of the face
emerge from a larger dark mass; decentring a
focal distance, sometimes with cigarette
smoke for example, or blurring both face and
background. There is a You Tube collection
of some of the portraits here
Meanwhile, try these:
Having deterritorialized and cut out, a new
assemblage of enunciation can be developed,
in pursuit of an aesthetic goal. For
example, a portrait shows one eye visible in
the light with just a glimmer of the other
one in the shadow, in a 'quasi-hallucinatory
fashion'(249). The invisible eye can
be depicted metonymically by a small trace
of white. This complementary relation
produces 'the existential effect of
being-seen-by-the-portrait', apparently much
admired by surrealism.
Could be this one (apparently, this is
Boltanski, but not the photo that Guattari
actually refers to):
This
is another one which might be it (
below). Guattari talks this up
rather: 'the window at which Boltanski
appears itself encompasses other
windows, and these three stages of
fractalization by the nesting of frames
then find themselves prolonged by the
multitude of layers and branches that
seem to envelop the person represented
in American shot' (248) [note seven
explains the 'American shot' as 'a term
from French film criticism that refers
to a framing of the character in ¾
length medium long shot' (284).]
So now we have
deterritorialized the face, the image does
not have a simple representation, no
'"photographic referent"' as in Barthes
[that apparently related to the 'optionally
real thing' whereas photographs have the
capacity to relate to the 'necessarily real
thing' since there must have been an object
placed before a lens]. As a result,
the 'imaging intentiality of the spectator'
is necessarily engaged, in constructing the
portrait, 'bringing into existence' the
person. This in turn produces a
certain precariousness, as we become aware
that the photo is 'gazing at me from my
interior... I am expropriated of my
interiority'[I become aware that an object
has influenced my subjectivity?].
This relation between the interior and the
photograph can also produce 'an autonomous,
abyssally fractalized gaze'.
Representation is animated and hollowed
out. In the example, a portrait of
Arman [which I can't find], a complementary
relationship appears between his beard and a
sculpture in the right background, his eye
in shadow and an 'eye window protected by
bars'. Other elements have the same
effect—eyes obscured by a bar of shadow,
half closed eyes with light playing on the
eyelids, the light on the frames of a
person's spectacles which are 'substituted
for the brightness of his gaze',other light
effects on glasses or eyes, or a way in
which the iris or cornea 'becomes the
seat of the omission of a light-gaze'(250).
So normal sense is fractured, an
'existential transfer of enunciation is set
off', and a portrait captures the gaze.
Barthes uses terms like stadium as
opposed to punctum, where the
stadium is the conventional coded
signification and the punctum is the
'"accident which pricks me"'. The
punctum becomes a metonym for a wider form
of rupture, especially if it becomes a
'stigmata punctum', affecting our whole
notion of time. However, this
'stubbornness of facticity' only affects
some cases like the portrait of Barthes'
dead mother, that provokes a whole
memory. Tahara has different concerns,
not to establish the identity of the
subject, nor in deliberately changing the
operations of signification. Instead,
'attested faciality' can even interfere with
contextual clues provided by the photograph
and thus bring into play 'deterritorialized
universes of existential reference'.
However, faciality has always had a
deterritorialized function—the face of
Christ haunts 'western capitalist
subjectivity', the faces of US presidents
appear on the dollar bill [shades of ATP].
There is always 'existential substance' in
any signification, as well as formal sense
[somehow, this shows the prevalence of
'deterritorialized faciality' in all
signification]. Whatever appears as a
sensible quality, a gestalt or even an
abstract problematic, 'always does so as an
enunciative nucleus incarnated in a
face'[doubtful]. This applies to
voices, which are also 'predisposed by this
kind of non discursive faciality'
(251). As a result, whatever appear as
a simple 'present to itself' also features
'an absolutely different present'[not much
different from Derrida arguing against
Husserl that any language implies an other,
or, for that matter, Husserl on the need for
an other to limit subjectivity—a big theme
in Deleuze eg in Logic
of Sense]. This is not the
'big Other' of Lacan, but a
different kind of alterity, 'modulated by
the big and the small terms of history and
by the mutation of technological
phyla'[Christ knows what he means here, a
more concrete other which can be massively
generalized or local according to the
importance given to it by history? How
on earth could technological phyla produce
different sorts of other?
Communication technology?]
It would be wrong to consider photography as
a dated medium compared to cinema or video
[which implies it is communication
technology that he means]. The
photograph above all other forms show the
'existential temporality of the machines of
representation'—not as overloaded and
talkative as other media, not peddling
dominant enunciation to close down 'the free
processes of subjectification', but rather
allowing a certain freedom for 'the powers
of partial temporalization'[that is making
you realize the effects of time?
Making you realize that something real once
did exist?]. [He also thinks the comic
strip can do this].
Overall, Tahara and others have developed
diversity and play in the 'machinic
components of the "armed" gaze'.The
photographer is subjectively effaced.
Moholy-Nagy, earlier, had developed this
idea to outline eight types of gaze:
'abstract,
exact,rapid,slow,intensified,penetrative,
simultaneous and distorted'[this is
referenced by Sontag 1973 On Photography].
Again, the portrait has been
'deterritorialized and
desubjectified'. Instead we have a
'processsual faciality' that takes part in a
project of staging or 'landscapifying',
offering certain traits to the enunciator
[who is the spectator after all?]. Two
examples follow, with the first relating to
Tahara's portrait of Kounelis [apparently
'two discs of raw light break away from the
eyes, literally tearing the gaze towards
us. They echo an equally rounded
glimmer of light {on the right hand side of
the face}. Consequently it is the
whole photograph that becomes an eye].
The second one goes back to Arman where a
white globule imposed on the nostril
resonates with our other circles and traces
to counterpoint the absent eye and to the
photo which faces him, the sculpture.] In
another example, two white globules appear
from overexposing white shirt buttons, and
relating to a map of Europe with large pins
stuck in it. In another case two large
lampshades have taken the place of eyes, and
in yet another one two particular forms of
light at the bottom of the photograph look
like 'two capsule satellites'[apparently
this suggestion of extra meaning from
patterns of light is known as a 'type of
"parasiting"'(252).
Apparently Tahara told Guattari that first
of all he has to understand what's going on
in a gaze even before he takes a photo, and
Guattari sees this as being able to 'free
oneself from the superimposed significations
that are imposed on the facialitarian
landscape as if by themselves, it is to
allow oneself to be dominated by the other
gazes that organize themselves before your
eyes'. Tahara photos offer instead
'multiple fractal cracks', that do not close
off interpretative sequences. Instead,
these can be reiterated indefinitely and
'emptily'[compare with the empty
signifier?]. They can be 'new
existential stases...new lines of sense and
new universes of reference'. There are
'partial nuclei of enunciation' and an
'existential taking body' [sic], and these
connect with all sorts of part objects
transversally. In turn, the 'scopic
drive' can be connected to other
constellations of interest and desire.
Although Tahara attaches proper names to his
portraits, he does more than just represent
people and denote an identity or offer a
connoted message. The proper names
should be seen really as 'notes of a
musicality that everywhere exceeds
them'. Bodies are deterritorialized
and are transferred to us immediately and
directly, appearing 'without limit and
without organs': the proper names therefore
are only an index for many other effects.
'Cracks in the street'
This is a paper delivered at a conference,
originally about discourse and then the
'text of the state', but he decides in the
end to stick to the idea of
discursivity. Discourse is 'a
trajectory', or wandering, featuring various
encounters, or the 'immobile peregrination'
(253) when we contemplate a Zen Garden, or
the pleasure of an autistic child at seeing
water drop in a film by Victor -- Ce
Gamin-la -- which apparently
follows the experiments of Deligny, whom we
have met before. However such
discursivity might indeed depend on
particular treatments of the
commentators. There is also 'non
verbal semiotization' which is increasingly
important and nowadays assisted by
computers. Overall the discussion can
focus on textual discontinuity: 'gaps,
ruptures, interstices, slippages, margins,
crises, liminal periods,peripheries ,
frames, silences' (254).
The focus is 'a composite memory of three
paintings by Balthus on the theme of the
street'[I think I have found them on the
Web. I think I have arranged them in
the right order from earliest at the top]:
In the second example, the perspective is
'thrown out of joint' the canvas is bigger
than the characters look more solid.
The woman's hair combines with the frame of
the shop to produce 'a sort of Chinese
ideogram of a red colour'. Her hand
can be seen as just hanging there or as
grabbing the thigh of the woman in front of
her, the one carrying the '20 year old
toddler in a sailor's uniform'.
Although there are discrepancies, the
gestures of the men and women 'respond to
each other head on...like the front and the
reverse of a new race of androgynous
beings'. All of the relationships are
enigmatic, connected by gazes which are
often empty and disconnected. This
leads Guattari to see 'an imperious
occupation of space ...a radar- like system
of surveillance, through which the hegemony
of a seeing without a subject, without any
object, with no purpose, predominates. A
sort of panoptic supergeo'. The rather
stylized setting only emphasizes the
effects. [I must say that my attention
was also drawn to what others have called
the 'sexual struggle' going on in the left
foreground]
The third version has a more 'molecular
treatment of plastic elements', a
gradualized topology' which also serves to
'project us into an irreversible mutation of
the universe'(255). The characters are
smaller. It could be a theatre but
also 'a zen composition for the city,
associating living and inanimate
forms'. The gazes are unfocused and
the eyes blurred. Sightless windows
encircle the scene.
What we get from these paintings is 'the
irreducible polyversity of the components of
expression' to produce an aesthetic
effect. These components are loaded
with sense and recognizable forms, others
carry history and cultural messages, while
still others are 'a-signifying components
that rest on the plane of lines of the
Affects of colour' Simple hermeneutics or
semiotic cannot reduce this heterogeneity,
there is no resolution of the different
elements of aesthetic discursivity. It
is another example of how it is time to
resist 'the plague of the signifier'
(256).
In the first paintings, the signifier 'has
no ontological priority over the signified'
[it makes no attempt to explain the
objects?] . The painting has been
produced 'in the manner of the early
Italians' so it has 'cultural connotations',
an 'aura of the archaic', and that also
awakens affect. Where shall we find 'a
signifying caesura' that generates
sense? [As in classic structural
analysis, presumably the split between
signifier and signified]. We can only
suggest one if we can definitively 'keep the
functors of expression and the functors of
content separate' [that is assume some
objective content to be definitivey
labelled?], but in this case they are 'all
participate in the same deterritorialized
formalism, as the Danish linguist
Hjemslev had postulated'.
Aesthetic discursivity involves an active
heterogenesis between different registers,
enacted by operators, 'concrete machines'
which both dissociate and gather matters of
expression and make them polyphonic as in
Bakhtin. These machines can also
transversalise these matters, shift between
the levels of deterritorialized forms and
processes, where the latter are abstract
machines. This is the
'existentializing function' of aesthetics
which involves a 'suspension of speech'
(257), " a non discursive mode of
expression" [quoting P Klossowski, Balthus's
brother]. Images do not run in a
sequence like speech and can therefore
ignore time [like photos?]. They can
also show how things in the foreground are
related to those in the background on the
same surface.
However, enunciation about pictorial
expression makes it discursive again. We
have to find 'concrete operators' to help us
pass between discourse and pictorial
expression. Klossowski suggests that
painting can allude to a memory of being
outside of coordinates of space and
time. It is like the problem in
Heidegger of thinking of Being without
changing it into a specific being: for him
that showed that there is no easy solution
to explaining existence, only constant
questions, equilibrium followed by flight,
proliferations, cracks and gaps.
In the second version of the painting we
find a 'phatic operator', which disrupts
form and perceptual schema to produce 'new
enunciative cutouts'. The
gesticulations are exaggerated and the
characters seem like they are stuck
on. This serves to break with the
internal logic of the painting to 'make
signs to, to interpellate the
spectator'. The characters seem to try
to drag us into the scene [especially the
sexual assault?]. We are required to
become clairvoyants [I would say
voyeurs]. Our own gaze is
captured. That helps link the gaze
machine in the painting and the unconscious
processes triggered in us. The result
is 'a curious trans human, trans machinic
relation of intersubjectivity' (258).
This link arises both from expression and
contents acting together to become
'ostensive bearers of a message'.
There is also 'a threatening tonality' which
threatens the system of gazes. This is
because the precariousness of the apparatus
reminds us of our own 'ancestral fear of
fragmentation and dismembering'. We
see the cracking of structures of sense so
the painting takes on this fear and then
relays it back to us. However,
paradoxically, this can actually come to
guarantee our own 'existential
consistency'[a kind of realization that full
understanding and consistency is impossible
except as some kind of accomplishment?].
So we have seen various 'processual
operators to enslave our vision'[where
enslavement refers to an attempt to program
it, with a deliberate connection to computer
software --master and slave programs and all
that?]. In the second painting we see two
principal operators: cutting out, the
disarticulation of motifs and the
construction of 'tableaux vivants'(259); the
composition of lines and colours that is
asignifying, with the consequence that we
can now see 'constellation of
existential universes' composed of the dance
of forms and the superegoistic pole of
petrified gazes.
We see these combined and transformed in the
third painting. There is an
exaggerated cutting out of forms, although
these are now shifted into the
background. Instead of molar forms of
cracking, we have more molecular forms such
as the 'powdery grain of pictorial
matter'. It is no longer the
interrelationship of gazes among the
characters, but the whole painting becomes a
gaze. When we grasp this we are
'implanting a "becoming Balthus" at the
heart of our ways of seeing the world'.
Aesthetics can offer this sort of subjective
mutation, although each assemblage has to be
grasped concretely. The third painting
makes this passing of meaning or
transversality, or the 'transfer of
subjectivity' the central operation, its
real subject. It works through
'molecular fracturing of forms' and
corresponding intensification of colour even
though the palate is restricted. This
visible but vague fracture can be understood
in terms of fractal objects. [fractal
sets are 'indefinitely extensible through
internal homothety' (260)], and this helps
us break with fixed identities. The
process might be applied to both states of
the psyche and the socius—so ego splitting,
various complexes and so on can be better
understood than by Freudian or structuralist
analysis. The transitional object can
be rethought, for example because it
involves a 'transition of reference' from
one particular constellation of universes to
another.
Back to the painting, we can see it
triggering a fractal impulse transforming
and producing a kind of cascade, between
spatial dimensions and other temporal and
incorporeal ones. In particular, there
are three points. First, the painting
'permits an escape from systems of
representation closed in on themselves—they
become 'a "strange attractor" of
transversality'. Secondly, the
painting offers 'processuality','a constant
repositioning of its ontological references'
that will in turn modify existential
dimensions and turn them in the direction of
'permanent resingularization'. Thirdly, this
process shows how subjectivity is self
produced from this process and reprocessing.
There are political and ethical
consequences. We might take this is an
example of how to escape from constraining
discursivity, capitalist subjectification,
and replace it with multi centred
heterogeneous polyocal approaches. We
will focus on the signified, the iconic, the
non-digital and thus liberate 'molecular
populations' (261). These possibilities have
been ignored in various kinds of
positivism. Linguistic structuralism
tries to confine the existential function to
a box called 'pragmatics', less important
than syntax and semantics. However,
what this process does is to constitute
existential territories, together with
various refrains rooted in ethology, and
even facial compositions and all the various
objects found in the psyche. We should
see these as 'possible procedures of
fractalization', as part of the
recomposition of existential
territories. Only then will we be able
to see how particular modalities of
subjectification can develop in their own
right.
Music could offer a privilege terrain for
this sort of process. We can examine
the history of how voices and noises have
been smoothed by various instrumental and
scriptural machines as well as 'new
assemblages of collective listening.
The 'new sonorous matter' can be seen in
terms of a fractal breach of these
processes, a new processuality. We
would need to explain this in detail,
exploring the emergence of tonal music,
scales with equal intervals, which break
with a natural harmonics, how the scales
developed [then there is a nice example of
how semi tones like C and F were originally
seen as satanic leading to new equalized
scales]. The whole story will involve
little differences accumulating, produced by
an underlying 'molecular fractalization'
(262).
back to Deleuze
page. At last!!
,
|
|