Notes on: Kirby V (2011) Quantum
Anthropologies. Life at Large.
Durham: Duke University Press.
Dave Harris
Preface
This book was a response to a challenge to her at
a conference to focus what she was arguing about
Derrida. She also wants to acknowledge Saussure.
The main aim will be to refuse to split cultural
studies from contemporary scientific enquiries,
seeing natural and social phenomena as 'different
expressions of the same phenomenon' (viii), an
underlying differance. The specific attack is on a
person called Protevi, who had argued that
although sympathetic to deconstruction, its proper
place is not in science, but in those studies
focused on language and culture.
Derrida himself has suggested such a split is
unfounded, and it would obviously we can
deconstruction as a general approach. It has
already shown all sorts of continuities in
different fields — why should the nature/culture
split be exempt.
Derrida uses terms such as general text or open
system, writing in the most general sense, and
these are really the same questions for Kirby that
you find in the physical sciences — determination,
causality, space-time involvement and so on.
Including them would add important insights. The
intention of this book, though is to question what
is human or anthropological.
It begins with the [famous] inversion of Derrida's
slogan 'no outside of text' which becomes 'no
outside of Nature' (x). Derrida has certainly
attacked metaphysics, but there is no reason to
exclude matter: it could be seen instead as
interior to the system. The old split represents a
received meaning. Derrida on supplemenarity
stresses this interiority [in the course of
denouncing metaphysics — that's what he means by
nothing outside the text, or no outside of text,
because textual menaings are deeply implicated in
any metaphysical argument — definitions,
corollaries, opposites and all the rest of it]. It
is not enough just to stress the differences
between matter and language. The results will be
also to indicate 'quantum implications', because
there is a similar idea of an interiority with an
'articulating energy' and a rejection of simple
identity and of simple chronologies. Barad is
cited here on the entanglements of ontology and
epistemology [so it all gets nicely circular and
subcultural].
The common area is that there is no steady
space-time continuum, no general field, no
'"everything" that preexist the relationality that
is the scene of writing, the scene of ontological
genesis as enfolding' (xi).
Because quantum implications are now so popular in
the humanities and social sciences, cultural
critics 'are already practising science', [and
their texts are material productions] so human
exceptionalism no longer has value. 'Life reads
and rewrites itself' in everything.
Chapter 1 Anthropology Diffracted
[This is drawn upon quite a lot in Barad, and I
think I discussed the arguments — about
clairvoyant stingrays or dark precursors — there.
I think reading it in full suggests even more that
we can make Derrida fit the natural sciences, as
long as we turn him into Deleuze on immanence
[='writing'} and actuality. I have glossed
and simplified a good deal]
Let's focus on the issue of beginning [and
probably, largely ignore the issue of
logocentrism]. There is a common idea that there
is a beginning and it has mutated, and this lies
at the heart of conventional causal explanations,
or for that matter conventional understandings of
human decision-making. Deconstruction will
understand this, but criticise it nevertheless.
Our currently crude measurements will maybe become
fractal.
Bennington has charted the scandalous implications
that follow from Derrida on origins — an absolute
past has never been present, there is originary
repetition, supplements actually producing solid
productions. Some of these radical implications
have not survived the institutionalisation of
Derrida. Deconstruction has become a particular
style of criticism or a philosophical methodology.
Actual implications, however are more radical
although hard to take seriously, because we are
used to assuming that entities simply are here,
and that they are confined to simple locations.
Explaining events as a consequence of
deconstruction is a way of domesticating it,
suggesting that complexity is merely apparent, the
result of particular cultural perspectives, or
attributable to the complexity and creativity of
language [my argument really]. Post-modernism has
particularly focused on the self-referential
reality of language and how it underpins culture.
By contrast, nature remains rigid, prescriptive.
This is not a rejection of cultural
constructionism, however, [feminists can't reject
anything that other feminists have done] and it
has been very useful in dispelling conservative
accounts of nature or culture. Instead, the
implications have to be pushed further than
before. For example, understandings of language
are still restricted, and we have not yet fully
grasped its 'sheer exorbitance' (3). Perhaps we've
not explored these because there seems to be no
immediately relevant way of 'resolving political
and ethical quandaries'. This offers a
restriction, even a censorship for politics.
Science has long recognised some strange issues of
identity and determination, as in quantum science,
but this has been ghettoised as well, even by
physicists. Barad is quoted again to show how this
preserved conventional physics at the macro level.
Other social science disciplines have already
elaborated deconstruction, but there is still a
simple view of language. It is now extended to
include different media, or it is used as a
metaphor for wider behaviour. None of these would
be acceptable to Derrida, because they would all
reduce différance to a matter of relations between
concepts. Derrida is not a traditional philosopher
nor a linguist. Deconstruction is not just a
subjective activity, but something with an
objective nature. It can be seen as instrumental,
but early Derrida's grammatology is a
positive science [although possibly not
attainable, as I recall]. Certainly, neither
philosophy nor science is adequate, and this
leaves open the possibility that deconstruction
need not be focused upon objects in culture or
language, or on purely subjective identities.
Kirby says she realised the difficulties by
thinking about Saussure, and the contradiction in
his work — that signs are arbitrary, but that they
gain meaning only from a system of signs. There is
only 'relational coherence'(6), and it is that
that makes specific links [to referents, or
between signifier and signified] arbitrary. This
implies a reference to something outside the
linguistic system, but Saussure argues that this
very distinction between inside and outside must
remain within language. Saussure proposed a
further study which would explain where signs
originate within society, a move from linguistics
to semiology, an area of anthropology. [Kirby
refers to Lotringer
on Saussure -- which opened a whole new abyss
for me]
Derrida's argument that there is nothing outside
the text is similar, although he sees grammatology
as the science of the system, something even
broader than semiological systems [and this seems
to produce the Magic Substance where systems do
not preexist the communication between them]. So
we have far more than a methodology. Grammatology
wants to reject differences between objects and
interpreters, or interpretive apparatus. Method is
at best a cut [to establish causality, say] which
engages the whole system of differences. Method
cannot be conveniently isolated except by
acknowledging its complexity [and the way it makes
exclusions]. For Derrida, of particular
importance is 'the sense of textual play' (8),
which is not meant to indicate capriciousness but
some notion of underlying processes including
constraints.
When deconstruction is pursued in other fields,
the notion of language is often still simplified,
and thought is tracked to resonance or metaphors
with linguistic and cultural representations [the
example given is 'feedback' in cybernetics --
anthropomorphism too, of course]. This is what
Derrida meant by the dangers of seeing
deconstruction as involving 'a "general
textuality"', 'a new "idealism"' where texts are
understood still as culturally mediated, language
only represents and the rest of it. Instead,
'differencing is "language", leaving
nothing outside of the overall 'grammatological
textile'. The representational approach sometimes
is differentiated into humanist and anti-humanist
variants, but they share a common view of language
and subjectivity, human identity and its
uniqueness.
Kirby then detours into two examples [which we've
seen already discussed in Barad]. She was giving a
paper and was worried about its reception, but a
young biologist speaking before her described the
amazing qualities of stingrays: their receptor
cells can only be unlocked by a particular
message, but they seem able to anticipate the
message. For Kirby, 'it is as if [!] the identity
and behaviour of any one observable receptor cell
is somehow stretched, or disseminated, in a
space-time enfolding' (9) [could be some unknown
process that triggers both the reception and the
sending of the message? Another dark precursor?].
If they are united over time, a message does not
seem to be actually required to have an effect.
There is both a question for origins and
causality, and for identity as separated in space
and time. Kirby even sees this sort of
entanglement between herself and the other
presenter of the paper which had 'already brought
us together before our actual meeting' (10).
In the other example, lightning seems to display
mysterious qualities, perhaps even some capacity
for logical choice, hence its preference for
particular sites. This seems to be a dark
precursor for the actual strike, although its
communicative capacities remain mysterious. Yet
somehow, lightning chooses the most economical
route to earth, and travels both ways in steps:
however, the first steps are taken without any
information about objects on earth underneath. The
actual researchers refer by metaphor to human
intentions, but another account says that a
constant current flows beneath storms and the
earth, which charges the earth negatively and, in
other conditions, the clouds positively, and this
is kept in balance by lightning strike, an action
within a global field. This ever present field is
detectable in other ways, for example by DNA
[which apparently has electrical latency which
changes].
For Kirby, these are 'instantiations of the
graphematic (grammatological) structure' (12) that
she is interested in, with human language itself
unable to mediate these operations. [Nice
--language cannot construct everything in Nature].
It is wrong to seek culture as the only area, with
nature as its creation. At the same time, it is
difficult to escape the ways in which nature
displays a 'representational history', one which
incorporates logical origins and causes, and
denies identity and agency.
Of course, the implications of extending this
notion of grammatology 'have yet to be robustly
explored' (13) although Derrida certainly already
extends grammatology beyond linguistics and
representational systems. Textuality implies far
more than the operations of the components of the
sign. It is instead 'a splitting or trace whose
infinite dispersal in genesis confounds all
notions of dimensionality as aggregation',
including conventional notions of place and time.
We find writing in this general sense in culture
and also in nature. Nature is not just to be added
to culture, however. Instead the point is to argue
that 'the same initial conditions'apply both to
cultural activity and events such as clairvoyants
in stingrays or lightning strokes. Both are the
'differant expressions of a unified field, a
"general text"'.
Conventional differences between social sciences
and science is therefore not so straightforward.
It might be that culture assumes a dominant origin
for general textuality because a proper
understanding of nature has been lost
irretrievably, with ensuing binaries and claims of
original privilege for human thought. Politically,
this equates otherness with some 'original
simplicity and limitedness' (14) [the main
issue?], and maintains this view with 'righteous
conviction'. An adequate critical politics would
not hesitate to pursue some of the more radical
implications, even though they might be somehow
uMPalatable.
The Cartesian view that a human mind constructs
everything else [including God?] also means it's
quite hard to grasp the reasons for the success of
science. It is not just technological and
political payoffs — 'such knowledges work'.
Scientific success should be fully scrutinised,
but its procedures are not seen as relevant to
representation or communication. Language belongs
only to culture. Therefore progressive politics
can only be cultural, and other questions about
nature seem naive or pre-critical. However, 'truth
productions' in science cannot be omitted.
We fear opening the idea of a text to outside,
something not coterminous with human subjectivity.
Science therefore becomes 'a bad boy', lacking
creativity. Yet cultural analysts still flirt with
scientific approaches. Nevertheless, they believe
that it is necessary first for humans to break
from the natural world, to generate 'projections
and ideations' (15) using language. Form is
divided from substance, culture from nature, and
one side of the binary is seen as 'base,
primordial, and lacking'. However, a proper
'vigilance' for analytic activity would challenge
this logic, and open a more 'surprising and
provocative outcome' (15 – 16).
Some implications were raised at a 1966 conference
looking at the interdisciplinary possibilities of
structuralist and critical theory. A number of
different scholars were involved, including
Hyppolite and Derrida. The point was to try and
identify common ground on matters such as language
systems, objective and subjective judgements,
links between microcosmic and macrocosmic
dimensions. The young radical Derrida challenged
the notion of language and structure implied, and
Hyppolite challenged him in turn. Hyppolite agreed
that the concept of structure was not at all
straightforward and also argued that the natural
sciences have progressed by undertaking a kind of
deconstruction ['"destructuration"'].
Specifically, Hyppolite argued that we can learn
from the natural sciences, that Einstein, for
example focuses on a particular form of 'empiric
evidence' and it is that that led to his discovery
of constants, which go beyond empiricism and which
also dominate the whole discussion of space and
time. He was suggesting that there is a structure
here more general than the actual uses of
language, implying indeed even a form of writing
producing novel and improbable results which
exceed normal subjective understandings and thus
has no authors. Yet he saw this as a mutation or
accident, a defect of a structure, rather like the
way in which random monkeys might produce
Shakespeare. The broader implication was that
human beings themselves are so different as to
have arisen only from a similar mutation or error
by nature [later described as a philosophy or
experiment of nature]. In particular, could the
term [still linguistic or cultural] structure mean
something produced by chance, creating a genotype.
It would have a mysterious origin, and therefore
become a '"sign without sense"'. A mutant from
nature had become capable of generating its own
mutations and adaptations.
Derrida objects to certain words in Hyppolite's
formulation, which reveal underlying assumptions.
At this stage in his career, Derrida is actually a
little bit insecure and uncertain. What might be
at stake is different understandings of the
centre, and how language relates to processes of
evolution.
Hyppolite asks Derrida for his thoughts on the
relevance of the Einsteinian constant [relativity?
The timespace continuum?] for the human sciences.
Derrida replies with a wonderful example of what I
have called elsewhere conjuring up magic
substances. First the constant is not a constant
or centre because it embodies variability:
therefore it is better understood as the concept
of a game, not of a thing. Hyppolite wants to ask
if this means it is one constant in the game, or a
rule of the game, and Derrida replies that '"it is
a rule of the game that does not dominate the
game. Now, when the rule of the game is displaced
by the game itself we must find something other
than the word rule' (18 – 19).
Kirby sees this is a wonderful way to de-fetishise
language. Apparently, discussing algebra, Derrida
says that we can think of algebra as representing
a field of ideal objects governed by human
subjects, or as some '"disquieting mirror of a
world which is algebraic through and through"'. A
field is not defined by a centre or a subject, but
acts more like a game. Kirby sees this not as
'complacently meandering' (19), but rather an
indication of an early calling to explore the
mysteries of the lightning stroke, clairvoyant
stingrays, quantum action, developing awareness
For her, it leads to a view of language not as
separate from nature or the world 'but as their
playful affirmation' (20). Seeing language as
entirely cultural is to assign it a misleading
centre. And instead, we should use Derrida's terms
that affirmation '"determines the non-centre
otherwise than as loss of the centre… Surrenders
itself to genetic indetermination, to the seminal
adventure of the trace… Tries to pass beyond man
and humanism"'
Human language is not the result of a mutation,
something that established some originary
qualities. Properly understood, human beings are
in the text that nature writes, even if this is an
error [and writing is defined positively as more
than just random scribbling]. One implication is
that the [human] subject of a graphematic
structure is best understood as an 'originary
articulation'. Another is that humanness itself
contains this natural 'originary technicity'. This
might be misunderstood as anthropomorphism, but,
taken seriously, it would redefine it. We would
certainly have to change a number of 'sedimented
wisdoms' with effects on our moral compass.
Specifically, anthropomorphism would become
capable of considerable ['infinite', 21]
differentiation, traceable to 'one implicated
spacetimemattering'. Analysing that in its
different forms and identities would 'open the
question of the human, and writing, as if for the
first time'.
Chapter 2 Just Figures?
[More of nature's exuberance or excess revealed
here, causing problems for conventional notions of
rationality, and for easy splits between culture
and nature. It begins with a very
interesting question about whether maths is
natural or cultural --or whether scientific or
classical language is. Ultimately, we are to ask
whether we find writing and différance only in
culture. This one draws on Derrida, but also
enters some reservations and need to interpret or
extend him]
This chapter opens with a quote from a certain
Rotman asking why mathematical writing has not
been addressed compared to literary writing, even
though there are the same problems with
mathematical signs — after all they make up
allegedly the most rational language [although
anyone who has done a bit of maths knows that
there are the most extraordinary assumptions and
recognitions involved]. [Later we're going to get
back to the question that animated Derrida and
Husserl — whether numbers were just ideal objects]
Kirby was watching a TV programme about the
discovery of a human skull, and efforts to restore
a human appearance. One thought immediately is
that faces seem easier to grasp than bones,
perhaps because we assume we can read faces
better, or maybe grasp something of the actual
history of the person involved. Facial
reconstructions are relatively recent. Early forms
involved simple observations, of the kind artists
used, but in 1895 a more scientific method was
considered. The skull was rendered as 'a template
of measurements — a grid of longitude and latitude
whose universal intersections provided an anchor
for comparison' (24). This led to a statistical
analysis of tissue depths, which in turn led to a
better understanding of 'facial architecture' at a
general level, enabling extrapolation to specific
cases. This database has been recently greatly
extended, with more population diversity built-in,
and better technical techniques such as CT scans.
We can now use algorithms to forecast 'the skull's
cranial grammar'. The old methods involved
identifying 28 to 32 points and then adding flesh
to the average depth: the artist interpolated
between these points, drawing upon an
understanding of anatomy.
As a further development, information can be
derived from the skull of the activity of muscle
and tendon, a number of 'local conversations
between flesh and bone' (25). They can even now be
inferred from other places on the skull, even
those without immediate proximity. Here it is 'the
differences [which] are able to inform and even
inhabit each other'. A particular case of forensic
reconstruction in 1993 shows the possibilities. A
lot of the skull was actually missing, yet
calculations were possible from skull fragments
and this was successful enough to recognise the
victim. A whole collection of data was used in the
prediction of characteristic '"landmark sites"'
[note 5, pages 140 – 1 says this is still
misunderstood, as an artistic, empathic endeavour
rather than the result of more scientific forensic
reconstruction].
A series of numbers therefore can generate 'an
individual morphology' (26), in some cases
producing results which counter common sense [a
particularly long nose in one case]. It is an
example of the mysteries offered by mathematics to
cultural analysts, and raises questions about
whether they are both examples of 'language',
whether there is a generalised language which will
include both. One commonsense observation is that
maths seems much more precise and pragmatic than
the language of literature. Seeing forensic
reconstruction as language, though, shows how
radically different material and bits of
information can be put into correspondence to
produce information. This is not just a process of
finding an expression for some underlying
presence. There is no factual identity being
reconstructed. It's more like the quantum world
where the particular bits of information have a
defined locality 'as well as a global presence'
(27) [a bit fanciful in my view, although it does
show the exuberance of nature again that bits of
bone can act like a kind of holograph].
Derrida looked at Husserl on the origin of
geometry, partly because H clearly saw maths as
the most ideal object, deployed apparently
abstractly. He then considered the 'logic of
supplementarity' required to attach mathematical
signs to actual natural objects. This is clearly a
very interesting general question, and extends to
considering links between any body and any
language, any subject and any world. There is also
a sense in which mathematical and natural objects
had different sorts of histories [actually
historicity].
Husserl further investigated maths in terms of
perception and experience, to get to this matter
of engagement with natural objects. He wanted to
see geometrical abstraction as really derived from
the perceptions found in ordinary individual
subjectivity, but it clearly had an
intersubjective dimension as well, and, for that
matter, a history. How do abstractions emerge as a
'functional representation' of natural
events? Equally, how did geometrical
artefacts emerge and endure, persist as culture:
Husserl saw the implications for all knowledge,
including spiritual and literary matters.
Particular ideal representations, in the terms of
the time, took on persisting factual existence,
even after their inventors had died, even after
the original arguments had been lost.
Husserl saw a contrast between the subjective
historicity of ideal objects, and normal attempts
to grasp and explain particular knowledge
acquisitions, how original even idiosyncratic
discoveries were transmissible without their
original subjective conviction. Had these ideal
objects already possess 'intersubjective and
supertemporal purchase'? (29). They did not work
by just recalling subjective meanings, but became
objects both ideal and true, for everyone,
independently of personal or social conditions.
The problem in its most general is a matter of
subjectivity going '"outside of itself in order to
encounter or constitute the object"'. Both
subjective and objective aspects are retained,
because those objects can still make sense within
specific cultures as well as having a meaning for
all human activity. Kirby can see a
connection with 'the quantum puzzles of
space-time', although Husserl apparently referred
to virtual communication at the intersubjective
level. Even so, there are still problem of showing
the connection with individual sense perception
with its likely subjective variation. The very
notion of sense implies this shared ideality.
For Kirby, this is a matter of quite 'uncanny
structuration', where some requirement for the
future is a part of the initial condition, 'as if
the origin is already alive with what has yet to
come' (30), where this future is part of the
identity of the object. The future is no longer
just 'the unfolding of supplementary moments in
time' from an original starting point, but now a
matter of identity, 'discontinuities or
differentiations with/in itself' [does she just
mean the potential as well as the existing
characteristics — of course, this common
understanding would assume great importance for
philosophers]. The same implications will threaten
the idea of pure ideality, and disturb Husserl's
notion that ideal objects originate in culture, in
the life world, while mathematics deals with the
empirical world. [This is important to show the
originary nature of subjectivity?]. Apparently, Derrida
glosses Husserl as suggesting that the earth
itself is some primal matter, exemplary element,
and thus the [common] ground for the first
idealities — happily, it also provided examples of
early universal and objective identities, calculus
and geometry.
Here, there is some 'identifying horizon of human
existence' after all. But again there is a gloss
from Derrida on Husserl — geometrical idealities
might have emerged from this material horizon, but
Husserl also wants to argue for an '"a priori"'
necessity to develop abstract geometry from
'"pre-geometrical experience"' [I think the
argument is that only then can a properly ideal
object develop, following this
'"desedimentation"']. The process of abstraction
and creation of ideal objects flows from something
that is naturally present, and goes through a
necessary severance with such natural knowledge.
This somehow emerges from the more naturalistic
forms of interpretation themselves, so that human
intellection in the full sense appears to be
autonomous — this is a bit like the argument in
Hyppolite. [There would be a risk otherwise, as
note 8, 142, points out — human qualities of
agency and intellectual capacity would have to be
developed somewhere before the actual arrival of
humans]. The actual process of genesis is
understood instead as 'a linear notion of
temporality that segregates process from product'
(31).
There is still a kind of genesis to be explained
though when the different component parts of
geometry collapse together [in actual
applications]. The parts include an individual,
the history of geometry, cultural representations
and so on. Husserl seems to represent this odd
process again as a linear almost causal or logical
one, with phrases like '"this," and then, "this."'
Somehow, a moment of individuation can produce a
more global abstraction. For Kirby, this is really
trying to reintroduce a segregation of space from
time again, this time in the form of 'proximity or
contiguity… linearity': if one thing follows
closely from another, we can assume there is some
connection.
Husserl elaborates this a bit, and sees it as a
conundrum instead, a matter of how dimensions
condense in linearity. We begin with a natural
limitation or horizon for human perception, an
outside which is not human. But this outside is
not simply incorporated and included. Instead, a
binary structure is preserved linking both outside
and inside. The spatial divisions offer a radical
qualification for the usual notion of identity as
self presence, separated from any other.
Kirby says this is even more radical than
Derrida recognises. For D, Husserl is
suggesting there is a common horizon of
experience, acting as an ultimate arbitration for
understanding, regardless of the usual cultural
superstructures which might vary. This would be
reductive for Derrida, presuming some 'enduring
univocity, or self presence, of the same' (32).
Derrida says that technically such a pre-cultural
nature would never be accessible, and he wants to
take the opposite view, that '"noncommunication
and misunderstanding"' are the '"very horizon of
culture and language"'. There can be no universal
absolute translatability or linguistic expression.
But Husserl argues that nature and culture are
'"inseparably intertwined"' [says Kirby].
[Implications here for her naturalism though?
'Nature' is inaccessible for Derrida -- so that
has to be seen as too restricted --below. So
Derrida must misunderstand Husserl here]
Derrida says that Husserl's model of language was
restricted to the language of science [in his book
setting out to investigate the origins of
science], whereas instead, language actually
offers us 'Joycean exuberance' as in Ulysses.
There seems to be no univocity there, only
constant equivocation, massive poetic potential,
endless '"theasaurisation"' (33). Joyce's work
shows that there is no fundamental natural
foundation for language, but rather a general
equivocation between all languages, [a kind of
linguistic virtual] full of poetic synthesis and
consequences, fully representing '"the
labyrinthine world of culture"' itself equivocal
and poetic. However, apparently Husserl can be
seen as offering a parallel to Joyce, something
transcendental [and subjective?]. Joyce himself
never abandons intelligibility, producing a
'veiled promise of… univocity'. So in a way, both
Husserl and Joyce show failed projects — Husserl
can't fully acknowledge the dynamism of language,
so there can be no univocity, but Joyce while
celebrating plurivocity doesn't show how this is
managed to produce intelligibility. In both cases
too there is an implication that subjects are
'"unfit"' to guarantee correspondence — but Kirby
thinks that Derrida is still thinking of human
subjects and has thus missed a
chance.
She does not want to assume that language has been
invented by humans to access a separated world.
This affects both Joyce and Husserl — and Derrida
also, at this stage 'lends itself to such a
reading' (34). Assuming human exceptionalism, he
has too limited a notion of general language or
general textuality which really should be
understood as 'a global articulation of and by the
world', not confined to what is possible just for
humans. This makes his critical purchase
'significantly limited'. However, properly
thought, the aphorism that there is no outside of
text leads to different implications [below]
[and does at least dispose of the notion of simple
origins in nature]. There is a 'relational
involvement' with the world implied in this
aphorism, one which cannot assume a natural
outside that has no language.
Kirby wants to go further, to argue that if we
look at this issue the origins of representations
and the split between subject and objects,
never completed neatly, we might conclude instead
that we are talking about 'the Earth's own
scientific investigations of itself'. We can then
see Joyce's plurivocity as a matter of 'fractal
arabesques that unfold within objectivation' (35)
[possibly with the implication that scientific
language is the kind of straight and direct
version, and this rescues Husserl as saying
something more positive, even if limited. However,
Kirby might be arguing that we should see poetry
and scientific language as not completely
distinct?].
Language itself would be something global, a
patterning of energies, whose exterior causes can
also be understood as internal investigation, 'a
comprehensive form of "self" alienation' as
necessary to scientific knowledge [as in artistic
alienation?]. No particular theory of language
will be able to describe it as completely
unaffected by the exterior. Derrida would be
wrong to argue therefore that nature is
inaccessible.
Instead, language is not confined to culture, but
should be understood as a much more general
'encrypting'. The specifically linguistic forms
should be seen as the last stage of a process, a
final effort. There is no radical break with
origins. The origin gives a different account of
itself [it all sounds very Hegelian to me]. It
would be misleading to say that writing exists at
the origin, or that there is no difference between
human language and general encryption — the
difference is 'the system's enduring ingenuity',
and the gap between general and human language is
'the stammer of language'.
Derrida sees language as emerging when we lose
direct contact with nature, providing a limit
which we can never go beyond, to ground our
representations, for example. Since we can never
fully identify this absence. We have to reinvent
nature, [as second nature].. However, we can
'persist in reading Derrida against himself'
(36) see his aphorism as an invitation to
interrogate language, to explore whether there is
general language, and can test the idea of a
radical break in human language, seeing it instead
as 'a process of differentiation whose energies it
is'.
It is no longer necessary to think of human beings
as the author of this arrangement. In Derrida,
this appears as the objection to Husserl on
natural origin of human language. [We must not get
too sociological and risk] an account implying
that every specific language would bear the mark
of '"empirical subjectivity of an individual or
society"'. Husserl does not think that we can
explain human subjectivity in this [social]
scientific way. However, this may be overdependent
on the idea of concepts rooted in individual
perception, a kind of self presence that Derrida
wants to refute. If we turn to Saussure instead,
we see that signifier and signified 'are
consubstantial', and this would seriously qualify
Derrida's critique of self presence. We need to
reject the idea of communication as an individual
representing reality necessarily imperfectly to
another, and think instead of language as 'the
system's playing with itself' (37). Kirby then
extends this to say that language 'is the world's
reproduction of itself' through encryption.
The world can be present to itself, engaged in
self absorption, trying to analyse data, a set of
'"presents"'. No individuals are involved, no
individual receivers of something which is to
come. Terms like inaccessibility or the
unrepresentable no longer apply.
We can explore this further by looking at Derrida
on phonocentrism. He wants to criticise the idea
of speech as pure immediate meaning, integrity,
compared to writing. But locating this process
entirely in culture invites 'complacency'. If we
rhetorically replace culture with nature, we can
deconstruct this underlying Gestalt. We have to do
what Derrida encourages to do 'elsewhere' (38) by
questioning conventional space and time [that is
more than just invert culture and nature]. We can
reverse the conventional sequence of time, for
example by asking 'how might writing be speech?'
[Very difficult stuff here]. We might find Husserl
of more value [with his quest for a natural origin
for speech?].
Derrida, glossing Husserl, says that he is arguing
that some grasp of common objects, the Earth, can
be a common ground for science [reminds me of
Popper saying that the basic statement is the
final common ground] however, that would still
leave the problem of explaining the emergence of
this common ground — there would need to be some
transcendental notion of Earth, some underlying
science of the Earth. This would be impossible
because we could never escape our own particular
earthly locations and relative grasp of the Earth.
Human objectifications [in science] would never
extend to grasp the infinite horizon of the Earth,
the Whole.
But this implies that the whole is the usual
notion of a totality internally differentiated
into fragments. This is indeed how languages are
usually understood, with fragments such as words,
letters or phonemes. These fragments produce
particular expressions [or particular scientific
descriptions], while the Whole is the 'horizon of
potentialities' (39), which is never just the sum
of all those fragments.
However, we can be more radical, following
Saussure and [other bits of] Derrida. The unit is
not distinct from the system in the first place,
but is authored by it. The relations between unit
and system is neither structured nor contingent,
because 'relationality is not an "in between"' of
entities. Instead, we can think of fragments or
parts in terms of 'virtual geometry with
hologrammatic resonance'. This in turn would mean
we have to alter classic notions of scale and
dimension in virtual geometry. The generation of
humanness could also be seen as 'an internal
articulation of and within itself'. So there could
be no separation or lack of access to the Whole.
Humanness would be a unique determination yet one
which still 'would speak of earthly concerns'
[terribly vague poetic language here and hints of
the Magic Substance].
We would see human identity not as a secondary
outgrowth of a process moving from speech to
writing or nature to culture. Those conceptions
risk 'anthropocentric relativism' or humanness as
some unique capacity and separation. Instead,
humans would be 'an expression of the world's
measured subjectivity'. Since the human
realisation of this subjectivity clearly involves
reflexivity, we can equally argue with that human
reflexivity is '"the objective science of the
Earth itself"' [to get back to Husserl's interest]
[so we can grasp the Whole]. In this conception,
'the world itself provides the intention to
measure, the object to be measured, and the
apparatus through which that calculation will be
determined' (40). [The Earth wants to get to know
itself and chooses human subjectivity as the route
to self-knowledge. Magic substances abound
throughout].
If we go back to the idea of forensic analysis of
skulls, we can now see the face as 'a connective
tissue wherein flesh and bone resonate with
numbers and names', a figure or figuration. This
is 'decidedly uncanny' because a particular face
is being mirrored in other faces that reference
its contours. Nevertheless, a unique face becomes
evident 'in the myriad faces that have never
encountered it' [a rather mystifying account of
predictive modelling]. Somehow, a unique likeness
is found 'in the anonymity of statistical tables,
shards of bone… DNA signatures… tomographic
separations'. Identity is not something achieved
against these fragments and involves both
'reflection and refraction' to provide a 'strange
unity'. The language involved refers to ideas of
field, system or structure, and it is these
that Derrida means by general language or
textuality 'in other contexts' [with an obscure
quote from one of his afterwords]
There is no doubt that language is a dominant
feature of human status and 'species privilege'
connected with sociation, abstraction, intellect,
something that marks us out among primates, who
can only offer 'comparatively puny… "natural
languages"' (41). However there are still problems
such as 'pheromonal literacy in ants'. Explaining
these as the result of some hardwired instinct is
not helpful because it still needs to explain the
capacity to adapt to unexpected circumstances –
perhaps this should be better understood as 'a
reading/writing program'. Similar considerations
apply to the rapid adaptations to antibiotics
among certain viruses and bacteria, which seem to
involve some calculation somehow expressed in
mutation. Why should genetic characteristics be
shared between fish and tomato plants? It may be
true that we would not even notice these
connections if it were not for 'human experimental
voyeurism' but they do present problems of
'ontological confusion'. The language of life
seems to cross species divisions. If we consider
the extent to which biology is affected by
geologies, we may have to question the distinction
between living and non-living systems. We might
not wish to confine mathematics to human affairs
but see it as involved in 'the poetry of molecular
parsings whose alphabet is the periodic table'.
Are these just metaphors of language or actual
language, and if the latter, what is the subject
which authors and reads? Why has an extension to
nature [of the kind she proposes] been censored?
Her interest was also aroused by reading about
Saussure's obsessions with anagrams [see the
results of my own investigations in Lotringer],
and how his discoveries of an apparently infinite
regress of units led him to doubt his own sanity.
He managed some of the complexity, but by focusing
on the notion of the referent as a constraining
relation with units beneath the word. Kirby 'has a
definite sense' (42) that this might refer to an
expression of life, an energy flow. Saussure was
forced to speculate that there might be some
hidden author or set of poetic conventions to
explain these anagrams, but he was particularly
baffled by those that just seem to appear
spontaneously and in large quantities.
Kirby is particularly interested by the possible
links with mathematics, and how these anagrams
might display '"an algebra of discourse"', with
its own regularities and rules. This would be a
serious challenge for Western metaphysics, and
raises questions about the guarantees of signs. It
indicates a play of language rather than simple
linearity, or simple origins. Lotringer cites
Derrida on the ways in which mathematical notation
has challenged the ideology of the alphabet [I did
not understand it there either]. Saussure achieves
coherence by attempting to return to the
importance of the name, which he assumed was a
reflection [actually shadow] of the number [and
see Kinser for
this ideological detour], and pursuing an analysis
that saw individual elements adding up [geddit?]
to an overall sum, decomposed in the anagram.
Saussure himself was never so sure [!] that the
reader could be excluded from the exercise, and
that was one of the reasons he abandoned the
project.
If we re-examine the project, though we might see
similarity in the reading of ink blots, some
'insistent appearance' of a figure in anagrams as
well, like the fragments used in forensic work on
a face, we would have 'informational chaos whose
poetics exceed even the wildest Joycean
associations' (44) but one which might still have
a coherence.
Saussure had evidence that suggested nonlinear
processes without conventional motivations, 'whose
manifestations were strangely phantasmatic' [in
the Freudian sense?]. Abandoning linearity meant
'a vertigo of infinite connections and
disjunctions' and impossible perversity. Yet there
still seem to be a guiding thread, even though
Saussure was unable to grasp it as a motivation or
some external coherence. This produced a crisis in
Saussure, and he avoided the notion of '"semiotics
freed from the tyranny of speech"' in Lotringer's
words.
Lotringer traced this inability to not considering
psychoanalysis, but this still preserves some
internal coherence for the human subject, some
human exceptionalism. Lotringer assumes that
language is unique to human subjectivity, and
[even with the Freudian Unconscious] cannot
develop a coherent subject at work in anagrams.
This means he sees language as self-sufficient,
but the complexity of language is still seen as 'a
specifically human capacity'. What [nice and
affirmative things] might be concluded?
Saussure achieves progress by abandoning the
referent, but eventually had to recuperate it. He
split the sign into its parts, but then confused
the terms. He tried to separate natural reality
from language yet never succeeded. He insists both
that language is somehow a systemic necessity
[hinting at something beneath words] and yet still
says that the sign is arbitrarily related to the
referent. He discovered both linear order and its
absence in language. He kept finding links with
mathematical calculations, which puzzled him. The
overall problem was that there had to be coherence
and system, including some agreed referents within
a language community, but identity for any data
'was inherently plastic' (45). There was both
living mutation and stability. There was both
specific semiotics and linguistics and a general
semiology.
Lotringer sees the difficulties and tries to
restore the position with [the Freudian
unconscious] and some autonomy for language, but
he still sees language as 'synonymous with
humanity' (46), still arising from some original
loss of the world. Any perception must risk
misrecognition. He is [?] implying that the
Unconscious is the reason for Derrida's aphorism
about no outside, even though Derrida himself
would reject this idea of some origin before
language [what about Lacan's version, that the
Unconscious is language?].
For psychoanalysis, language and writing displaces
an original referent or reality, and so language
becomes a substitute for reality, a signifier
separated from the signified, preventing any final
coherence or fixed meaning. For Derrida, however,
writing is the worldly origin of humanness, where
the referent presents itself. This referent might
be deferred or displaced, but it would be
misleading to see that therefore the entity
referenced is inaccessible [as is 'conventional
within deconstruction'].
We should place the human under erasure, and make
the subject in question language itself. Language
can now re-present itself. Difference becomes not
a space between entities, but an effect of an
internal differential. There is no origin for
presence or speech, nor some absent origin that
permits writing and therefore culture. Writing
instead 'expresses the energetics of an originary
unfolding' [and then an odd implication that the
human subject never actually fails in grasping
referents because the world is so complex that
there can always be 'countenance' (47)].
Returning to the forensic reconstruction of faces,
there is an allusion to other human beings,
seemingly arising by chance, although offering 'a
strange precision'. We can grasp this by thinking
about something underneath the world, or all
possible worlds found in every text in Saussure's
terminology. Or in Husserl's notion of a vital
horizon animating actual measurement
representation. Or Derrida's generalised writing
or textuality. We might conclude that the world,
at least in its becoming world, produces an
'archive' in every word, name or calculation.
'These are difficult thoughts' [!] that we've met
already when considering the nature of
mathematics. Derrida provides a comment in his
discussion of Rousseau where he says '"there is
nothing outside the text": it is not that we can
only access external matters such as details of
the life of Rousseau through language [which seems
to be Lacan's argument]. There are '"are more
radical reasons"' — real-life existence itself
appearing in text '"has never been anything but
writing"'. This is a usefully 'expanded ' sense of
textuality for Kirby, going beyond Lotringer's
attempt to extend the [still human] subject.
Any definition of human assumes some 'nonhuman and
inarticulate outside', and human exceptionalism is
propped up by it. Seeing language as properly
human reproduces human self presence and identity
— 'the tyranny of the human' (48). It is easy to
confine nature to 'babble', but what about the
operations described in anagrams, cryptography,
naming, or reconstructing faces: these are not
merely '"cultural constructions"' ['if we grant
the term "language" to nature in its vaguest
capacities and remark on the invention of its
programs']. [This hints, I think at some possible
circularity in the whole thing — if we allow
nature to have a language, then we can see that
language as behind the complexities of its
programs, which assume a language].
We should 'take very seriously the notion of an
originary writing/mathesis' and an 'original
scriptibility'. There is no nonlinguistic origin.
Everything is writing technology and invention.
Language presents itself in a more radical form.
Normally, we look at the way in which it is
constrained by humans, whether this involves
humanism or antihumanism. Some 'feminist and
minority discourses' show the same problems when
they want to argue for property rights and borders
by excluding themselves from Nature [and thus from
culture too if it has a natural origin]. However,
re-asserting a distinction between nature and
culture can also have divisive effects, even for
antihumanism as long as it still sees culture as
the main constitutive force. Instead we need 'a
more radical commitment to a horizon of
possibility and change', expressed in the dictum
that '"there is no outside of Nature"': that would
be wholly beneficial in 'claiming Nature's
"textuality," it's literacy, as our own'.
[I can still see some problems for univocity,
here, of course. Fascists and patriarchs would
also not be excluded from Nature or culture, rape
would be like sexual flexibility, but these would
require an extra dimension of undesirability or
artificiality: Hindess'n'Hirst with their points
about dogma or incoherence are applicable here.
Their writings are also traceable to general
language and to self-disclosure by Nature. The
commitment to possibility and change is always
assumed to be in the direction of liberation -- it
is good to dispel any limited versions of nature
but philosophy takes us only so far, still
ends in relativism not any positive commitment to
queer sexuality or whatever?].
Chapter 3. Enumerating Language. "The
Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics"
[Gripping questions here like why is maths such a
good representation of natural events compared to
alphabetical language, why don't social scientists
use maths to describe their world]
Popular crime series show us that the 'cryptogram
of the crime scene' (49) can be solved, but is
this just a triumph for mathematical computation
managing seemingly random events, or is there some
other ontological penetration with maths?
Maths is not often discussed, because it usually
requires that you can do it. Many mathematicians
are not interested in philosophy but just want to
solve problems,but it occasionally claims to be
about order, patterns and structure, and may have
the same 'combinatorial possibilities' (50) as
ordinary language. It certainly displays the
internal relations that Saussure notices with
ordinary language, but it is functional [in terms
of applying to referents?], and less ludic or
exuberant: that makes ordinary language more
suitable for human cultural activities.
In ordinary language, we often find 'productive
imprecision of words' and 'subjective nature of
interpretation'. Problems remain with maths, its
symbols and its object, whether it is a cultural
invention again, or whether it has some more
'natural and objective pretensions'. How to
explain its resonance with scientific information,
or its ability to inspire music?
Rotman is both mathematician and cultural analyst.
For him, it is the 'peculiar efficacy' (51) of
maths that leads us to suspect it is the language
of nature, possibly divinely authored, something
to be discovered not invented, and enduring.
[Rotman wants to reject divinity as a source for
the mathematical harmonies of nature]. It is so
different that there is the famous split between
two cultures in academic life, posing serious
problems for those who want to engage in dialogues
[we could replace nature altogether with culture,
but of course Kirby wants to show problems with
that and suggest a synthesis].
We could examine maths' '"foundational
hygiene", or mathematical rigour, provided by
rules, conventions and protocols that produce
intersubjective agreement. One implication is to
reject '"the alphabetic dogma"' [an explanation of
its appearance in the earlier chapter]. This dogma
assumes first that speech is the original form of
communication [because alphabetic characters can
be spoken, pronounced?] [So we get to logocentrism
and other implications]. There are more general
implications too.
[But we have to wait for them] most mathematicians
apparently take a Platonic view of the relation
between maths and real objects — mathematical
objects are not drawn from culture but are real
and objective [says Rotman] Numerals indicate some
underlying reality of number. They do not
constitute, which minimises 'the material
context and bodily engagements' implied in any
form of communication, any notion of performance.
Apart from anything else, this does not explain
the great usefulness of mathematics.
It is tempting to think of the process of
'"writing"' familiar to the humanities, but there
are problems with mathematics, and dangers in
assuming some underlying identity with literature.
Rotman points to alphabeticism, and its
'conventional linear morphology' in writing. This
is a 'prejudice' for Rotman, although it does
appear in maths in the form of '"linear strings of
symbols… [In]… normalised sequences"'. This makes
linearity look logical and proper. That is carried
by '"ideograms such as [mathematical symbols]"'
[eg + or ]
(54). For some mathematicians, these linear
equations are more important than, say, diagrams,
which become mere 'figural ornaments or
superfluous illustrations', even though they have
an essential role in the '"actual doing of
mathematics"'. They appear unrigorous and
imprecise. Again 'alphabeticism's installation of
the grams in implicit and prior say-ability is at
work here'.
Derrida has pointed to an additional
[quasi-autonomous?] underlying conception of time
as linear successivity, since 'phonologism imbues
certain entities and events with a temporal
priority' that becomes 'an ontological integrity',
capable of being disturbed only by something from
the outside, something coming later. Instead we
should see apparently autonomous phonemes as 'an
entanglement of systemic energies ("writing in the
general sense")' [a haecceity or event in
deleuzian terms -- see below].
For Kirby, this implies a holographic conception
where any particular unit can be seen as 'a unique
instantiation of the system's own reinvention (or
rewriting) of itself' (55), [Hegelian stuff?] and
this is what 'confounds linearity'. This preserves
a very general [virtual] notion of language, going
beyond the specifics of sayability [or leaving it
as a specific actualisation to be explained in
phonographic language]This will also imply that
there is the same split between speech and writing
within mathematical representations, so that
mathematical language [expression] 'is always a
writing practice', although this might involve
disagreement with Rotman.
Maths does have an illustrative logic which takes
the form of the sentence, and also an apparent
'"timeless and agentless language of sets"'
[Rotman]. This formal structure gives rigour, and
the seemingly universal applicability and beauty
of maths. This implies an emerging difference with
ordinary language about the relation between
speech and writing. Conventional language is
understood as involving speech as the true
expression of experience, something immediate and
true, even if it involves deliberate deception.
Writing become something secondary, supplementary,
with more chances of misrepresentation and
alienation because it is beyond personal control:
it can even be an 'external violation' (56) of
these expressive qualities of speech. This makes
writing in ordinary language, especially its
capacity to abstract, both instrumental and
morally suspect.
Mathematical notation appears instead as
'originary writing', however, where abstraction is
accepted as some sort of 'pure voice of reason
itself', something virtuous, something beyond
human distortions, not affected by motivations or
context and thus appearing as some truth, 'the
inexorable unfolding of a natural calculation', a
'mathesis naturalis' [wouldn't this be the mistake
of denying positionality for feminists? Affects
Kirby's naturalism too?] . It displaces
human beings as original author. Rotman sees this
as a problem because it neutralises perception and
motivation. The very fallibility of mathematical
calculation somehow guarantees an independent
existence. Kirby wants to rescue this by saying
that we can read him as suggesting there is still
a natural foundation for human activity, that
nature has conceived the human just as humans
conceive concepts. Arguing otherwise is to restore
human exceptionalism and to risk phonocentrism
again as an example of the cultural domination of
nature. This will also leave the 'informational
transfer' (57) found in mathematics unexplained.
Rotman seems to assume that scriptability is
introduced into a mathematical imagination,
whereas for Kirby it is 'already at work in…
Nature'. He assumes that the characteristic
'"foundational hygiene" is not natural — but what
if the body, or Nature is 'already that field of
mathematical imagination and invention'?.
We need to go beyond Rotman to explain how the
gram actually works in culture. He does notice
'exuberant bodily connectivities' that are found
in mathematics [he says they enable mathematics,
but Kirby thinks we can just say they are
mathematics]. He suspects there is virtual
writing, something more than Derrida's
archewriting. This would not involve grams [I
think]. However, Derrida has an underlying
'graphematic structure' which supplements [well--
accounts for?] the gram. The gram is just a
visible sign of it. The relation is not simple one
[of course] [assuming additional dimensions which
can be added together] but presupposes some
fundamental identity [a holographic one again for
Kirby where each atomic identity 'resonates
through webs of implication'. This is where
quantum physics can be generalised --'webs of
implication that are universally encompassing is
[sic] not peculiar to quantum physics'. (58).]
Even systems that see nature and culture as
separated occasionally refer to their mutual
dependence, although this odd combination is not
explained. Einstein's own work, challenging
'"spooky action at a distance"' at least
acknowledged the puzzle. In the humanities, though
there is still a belief in a physical reality,
something unaffected by our representations,
something with constancy and temporal priority.
There is often simply a view that work in the
physical sciences can have very little to do with,
say, literature — but 'the questions we engage are
often uncannily similar' (59). The analytic unit
is a problem, for example [it is 'chimerical'],
and we already have some notion of 'an
always/already that undermines causality', or
problems relating ideas to material factors. The
usual explanation is that we have an inadequate
linguistics and representational scheme, and it is
these 'secondary technologies' that produce
distortions and errors. This really keeps
intact the investment in the underlying binaries
such as speech/writing, presence/absence: we are
critical of them in our field, but not in science.
Derrida's implications similarly are seen as
restricted to the humanities, but if he is right
to suggest 'a general writing… an "inclusive
systematicity"' then nature can no longer offer us
fixed and immutable lessons, not separate, but
part of the articulations of complexity. If the
gram means more than the classic atom of thought,
it appears more like a quantum entity, 'its
apparently tiny dimensions have a universal
resonance' and the prospect of a mathesis
generalis is back on.
Going over some of the steps, it is obvious that
mathematics 'figures', meaning both to produce a
shape and to take the form of one. The lines drawn
between items are as problematic as the entities
they connect. Yet there is something in maths and
in all writing systems [for her] that makes them
legible ['their "presenting"' (60)]. Rotman begins
with the constraints of alphabetic and its
ambiguous legacy — a stabilising anchor, grounded
in speech and its unfolding, but also implying
some 'unmediated reality, or referent, whose
haecceity [sic] speech instantiates'. The
alphabetic text is particularly authoritative, and
this can mean that it's taken as definitive
writing, with mathematical writing as something
non-linguistic.
The distinction actually is confused. Rotman
points to the support for alphabetic writing in
literature which produces a phobic response to the
use of mathematical signs. The same goes for the
absence of 'schematic visual representation'.
Words are just seen as self-sufficient, diagrams,
really rare, let alone '"figures, arrows, vectors,
and so forth"'. However, we can extend this by
arguing that alphabetic letters also have a
dimension of visual representation or diagram, but
there is no barrier to those being sayable [unlike
the term
].
The way in which those graphemes produce phonemes
is unexamined and taken for granted, although we
are talking about exterior and different
representations in each case: Derrida himself says
that it is unlikely that graphic and phonic
representations can be simply derived from each
other.
How does mathematical notation gain such status,
when it can be seen as inferior to the closure and
clarity of alphabetic writing? [There are
apparently hints in Saussure of a strange tendency
for alphabetical language to not just mean
something in the usual sense, but to show '"coming
to count"']. Cryptography shows 'intimate
connections' between maths and literature, we
could see the spacing of symbols and their
operations as a kind of algebra, imposing a
pattern. How might we explain all these
connectivities, especially if they dispense with
linearity?
[As a diversion, she offers an exercise with her
students to present them with all sorts of
different representations — Braille, voice prints,
hieroglyphs, genetic codes and so on, she even
considers 'the pheromone trails of ants', the
phenomenon of grafting in plants or the 'syntax of
the atomic tables'. These are unfamiliar examples
designed to provoke questions about what they
might have in common, how their machinery actually
works, why one system is deemed to be more
coherent than others, why they can be translated
into forms that bear no obvious relation to them,
and what legibility actually is. The idea is to
get to how meaning and reference are produced,
whereas they just appear self-evident in ordinary
language, how solid they are, how confined to
numbers, or languages].
Rotman says that maths is a uniquely human
technology, not some Platonist correspondence to
reality, especially when applied, and obviously
contaminated by cultural and historical context.
The issue is how its '"unreasonable
effectiveness"' (62) remains nonetheless. It is a
similar problem with we consider natural bodies,
which can also be grasped as abstractions from
particular empirical patterns and regularities.
The body too poses problems of connections between
its internal differentiations [different
modalities, maybe different senses?], and is not
immediately and simply present. It's inner
coherence displays both a set of discriminations
and some 'geometry that eschews division'.
If we consider perception, for example
interpretation produces coherence from
disconnected events. This is not seen as the same
as 'intellection', however. There seem to be
differences again with reading or writing. Maybe
perception provides a kind of general abstractive
potential as well as the raw materials. This could
easily be seen as a kind of 'inherent literacy',
just like conventional literacy which also
involves some perceptual discrimination within 'an
intricate immersion'.
These operations clearly go on and terms like
'corporeal practice' can minimise them. In
Rotman's terms, the body is a kind of physical
container that enables calculation, but still with
some Cartesian subjective pilot. Carnality is not
the same as actual calculating and thinking.
Corporeality itself is not seen as being able to
'intelligently take measure of itself' (63). There
is still a split between inside and outside, even
though the origin of mathematics is not in some
platonic reality but in grounded human practice.
There is still phallocentrism, where perception
provides the raw materials, and conscious reason
organises them. There is danger of needing to
split humanness from nature as well in order to
stave off Platonism.
How does Rotman think that we get intellectual
activity from biological performativity, without
them being the same? The idea of a body given to
us before cultural interpretation is still like
theology or Platonism, with mathematics as a kind
of '"miraculous gift"' (64). Is there another kind
of corporeal intelligence available to us? Vision
operates in a complex 'synaesthetic' way, beyond
simple recognition, for example. There is
'amplitude', with consequences for other
biological processes — our blood races at
particular sights.
One example of this is in a study on conversion
hysteria, which classically is seen [to be cured]
in terms of a restoring the body to knowledge
production, in effect 'somatophobia'. This
particular study is not particularly compatible
with some feminisms, but it has an unusual rigour.
It's focused on how hysterics actually convert
mental processes into physical responses. One of
Charcot's patients could actually operate on her
hysterical performances, performing on cue, or
arranging them into various other tableaux, but
this apparent control was gained at the expense of
another hysterical symptom — 'she began to see
everything in black and white' [after being
repeatedly photographed] (65). One source of
misunderstanding is Charcot's own 'dehumanising
desires and insensitivities' that prevented him
seeing the whole person, but there is distortion
as well from an attempt to explain symptoms via an
expert 'hidden agenda' [by other feminists --
symbolic violence of course]. Apart from anything
else, this ignores the 'quite extraordinary
representational capacities' involved, and places
all the emphasis on the unconscious rather than on
the role played by the body and biological forces
in their own right. Kirby proposes that this whole
performance, which is 'intersubjective,
psychological, biological and even machinic
[connecting with the camera]' could itself be seen
as a gram, [with an implied underlying graphematic
structure].
If mathematical processes are explained by
cultural and social contexts alone, how does this
lead to emergent enduring patterns that can even
react back on themselves? Why should this not be
seen as reading and writing? If the body has the
capacity to engage in corporeal mathematics, why
can't it do these extra functions as well? We
could instead see nature itself as 'actively
literate, numerate and inventive' (66) as much as
culture is, and this might explain conversion
hysteria, or perception. Does the distinction
between culture and nature still stand, and if it
does not, how might 'distinctive differences [be]
effectively synthesised'?
There is still a tendency to domesticate the
implications of the studies of mathematics or
biology, as a recent exchange between a
mathematician and a neurobiologist in France
indicates. The latter begins by seeing
mathematical reality as entirely cultural, but
when he considers the human brain and its amazing
capacities, there is clearly an excess there
again, beyond the normal consideration of what is
human. If it is this brain that achieves
mathematical reasoning and other forms of
creativity, through biological energy, the agency
of culture arises from 'a misguided dichotomy'.
Instead, we should begin to think of biology as 'a
"unified field" of operational differentiation… a
mathesis naturalis', a form of 'evolving and
implicate calculation'.
There might well be a subject with
self-consciousness in this field, but we might be
able to render its characteristic self-discovery
as a 'reinvention'. [Reversing Foucault and
Deleuze] 'exteriority then, would be but a fold in
interiority' [so usually it is the externality of
nature that is also produced, or rediscovered,
while really it is the subject that is the
external fold] (67) by the biological energies of
the brain. Platonic argument that mathematics is
discovered in nature can be reconciled with the
view that it is 'also fabricated in the synchrony
of what appears at that same moment of discovery'
[the synchrony between it appearing in nature and
appearing to humans?].
To end with, this might help us uMPack Derrida's
aside about the relations between rationalism and
mysticism — '"a certain complicity"'
Chapter 4 I have notes on this
already
Chapter 5 (Con)founding "the
Human"
[Several themes here, including a specific
critique of an essay by Butler which I have not
read, part of her general discussion of Butler
that she has carried on elsewhere. The main thing
for me was the rethinking of the old two-stage
nature/culture issue, where nature provides the
material base, as it were, and culture then adds
significance meaning and social and cultural
dimensions. Butler seems to have this view. Kirby
wants to argue it out in terms of a discussion of
Freud. In essence, it concerns the bit where Freud
is deriving heterosexual identity from an
initially unfocused and libidinous and sexuality
or bisexuality. BUt he also offers a model of
homosexuality that implies an illness or lack of
social maturity. This is connected to Lacan on the
mirror phase, where there is the same kind of
cultural regulation of natural states, and also to
Lacan on the emergence of the phallus as the
general signifier, and its connection with male
and female sexual organs. In essence, I think
Kirby is arguing that this transition should be
seen rather in terms of an original connection.
The implication may be that cultural constraint is
also natural in origin, although generally, the
thrust seems to be that heterosexual identities
for men and women should be understood as a
'loss', with consequences for connections between
sexual identity and illness, specifically
hypochondria. It does seem to jar a little with
people who argue that nature provides excess:
Kirby seems to be arguing that it provides
constraint as well? It's very difficult technical
and I may not have understood very well]
There have been criticisms of the humanist subject
of several kinds, including from psychoanalytic
interpretations which have raised doubts about the
reliability of their recollections of subjective
pasts and personal desires, and therefore of
agency and accountability. Discourse theories too
want to challenge the subject as a self-sufficient
agent, in favour of 'cultural "patternments"' (89)
[a note on p.150 explains that patternment is a
term used by the linguists Sapir and Lee Whorf,
trying to explain how particular gestalts have
'functional purchase' over other equally likely
patterns, how an apparent bond between a sign and
a functioning referent develops. Apparently, this
has led to further debates about reality and the
practice of science]. It seems as if subjects have
to be interpellated first [presumably not just by
culture though] if they are to be recognisable to
themselves and others.
Sexual identity and sensual pleasures raise
further problems in that bodily experience is
affected by historical and cultural contingencies.
Our anatomy is not simply a natural fact — for
example, 'what constitutes pleasure and pain
varies dramatically across time and space' (90).
It seems impossible to break out of historical and
cultural frames to access some external and
different form of life. There seems to be a
necessary boundary between nature and the animal,
and culture and the human. In some ways cultural
developments depend on this barrier as being
absolute [we escape nature etc]. Culture is seen
as producing purely internal effects on relations,
across the board [of social theorists] , and this
is also favoured by political activists.
Naturalist arguments produce genuine unease:
nature is ineffable, primordial and inaccessible,
except through science. However, there is a
lurking conservative legacy here, despite a
humanist version [of Cartesianism] if we argue
that these differences are simply apparent,
reproduced in reflection. Even introducing the
unconscious will not correct this reflectionist
view that we can easily detect the 'difference
between a fact and an interpretation'. Thought and
the technology of language preserve human
exceptionalism, even for some feminist and queer
theory wanting to attack associations with nature
as restrictive.
Keeping nature at bay is 'a political practice in
itself' (91), and it is increasingly threatened by
'medical and computational breakthroughs'
especially in the sciences [because of the
'referential purchase' of things like forensic
investigation, genetic testing or the 'predictive
capacity' of maths]. It is hard to see how
representation and abstraction actually work if
cultural constructs 'cannot in reality be that
world'. Of course scientific results are still
contestable. The point is to ask how they can hold
to the truth, and still be open to cultural
criticism: it is not simply a matter of pointing
to 'errors' in either field.
Recent scientific advances have deepened the
crisis by grasping the world 'as a body of
interlocking information' (92) at all scales.
There are 'interwoven, interacting sign systems',
suggesting that the different languages familiar
to the human world [including linguistics and
science or maths as above] 'are not alien
technologies' transmitted between different
entities. Instead, material being can be seen as
'also information' [hint of a magic substance],
denying a split. Hence 'there is no outside the
textile of information'. And the question is how
identities are individuated, from the process of
emergence and reproduction and maintenance.
Is this just a further development of cultural
processes like metaphysics and epistemology? Kirby
thinks that 'these terms have assumed such curious
dimensions' that we must now think that nature
itself is a 'meta-physics', 'an involved
meditation, mediation and reproduction of itself
that is essentially queer in character'.
We have to acknowledge the importance of cultural
interventions especially that address identity and
forms of communication that produce them, but we
should not be insisting on segregating out what is
cultural from something else deemed to be alien
and inarticulate. She does not want to support
cultural constructionism which sees nature as an
appearance disguising culture, nor in grasping
some underlying 'logic of assemblage, Nature and
Culture'. She wants to identify instead 'strange
condensations confusing collapsed differences into
the mirror maze of an "always/already"', which she
intends to describe as 'facts of Nature' (93). [Resembles
Latour on the intertwinings of human and
mechanical such that there is no point in
distinguishing them in general terms? Based on
quantum indeterminacy though? ]
.
Butler has conceded that cultural constructionist
arguments may be inadequate to explain empirical
complexity, but she still confined nature to
something inaccessible and unrepresentable, even
though we cannot dispense with it. She also hints
that she perhaps overemphasised culture over
nature in her earlier work [Gender Trouble]
in order to avoid any justification for natural
heterosexuality. She now realises that there may
be something else in nature that cannot simply be
used to legitimate these.
Her particular favourite is a certain A
Fausto-Sterling [AFS] who looked at the
possibility of productive contributions from both
sides — how biology conditions cultural life, and
how cultural life affects biological reproduction
in particular. She goes on to describe the
relation between nature and culture as 'chiasmic'
rather than determinist from either end. However,
this still sees nature and culture as two
different entities or systems, even if related by
a chiasm [note 5,.151 sees these terms especially
associated with Merleau-Ponty and can be defined
as a kind of interactivity between entities rather
than an entanglement — this seems to miss the
apparently contradictory form of the chiasm, as in
Adorno]. This does mean that nature does not
exactly collapse into culture, and allows for some
kind of intercourse between them. — Kirby likes
the implication for copulation and prejudices
about sex. Butler is right to argue that
apparently natural facts are informed by cultural
bias, and this will have to be taken into account,
[I'm not sure Kirby ever actually does this,
because she never develops a sociology] but a
different perspective is available.
Nature and culture seem to be seen as separate
before they interact, sometimes with nature
temporarily prior, although this can lend some
support to the idea that identity was originally
'coherent and wholesome' before being violated by
otherness (95). Butler also installs 'a sort of
incest taboo', a moral prohibition about what
counts as intercourse and the forms it can take —
cultural activity is equated with political
activity, especially restrictive and dominating
forms. This is almost seen as acceptable — at
least it is not used in instrumental calculation.
But this makes intention and calculation traceable
only to [and a major function in] culture, a sort
of fall from grace scenario, mirrored in the work
of AFS and minimising [non-dominating] agential
processes.
Lots of arguments once accepted that human beings
depended on nature — 'even Descartes'-- but it is
less easy to accept that humans 'are inherently
natural' instead of just composed of two entities
added together. What if culture collapsed into
nature? What if nature reads and writes,
'calculates and copulates with itself' in both
creative and destructive ways? What if nature is
political through and through, and if even the
arguments in this book are 'a manifestation of
natural intent'? We have to addresses issues even
though they are normally considered to be
'improper, unspeakable — unnatural'.
Cultural criticism has often stressed inherited
logics and assumptions as initial conditions for
evaluation of behaviours. However, if we borrow
arguments from quantum theory, there may be no
initial conditions preceding final conditions, but
rather 'space-time condensation' (96), where all
sorts of concepts seem to collapse together
including ideas and material reality.
Butler [Bodies That Matter] argues that
idealisations can be realised or materialised, but
she uses this mechanism to explain how cultural
valuations are embodied, as controlling and
regulating mechanisms. It is true that nature
offers some resistance and is not fully compliant.
Barad has rebuked
this argument as a matter of offering puns on
'matter' [rich coming from her!], a matter of
materialisation being in practice seen as
signification — hence the complaint that
everything matters except matter.
Butler does rely on temporal and spatial
separation that quantum theory challenges, and
performativity itself follows because culture
never fully naturalises norms. The several areas
can interpenetrate in the chiasm, but this is
still not complex entanglement. It does not take
into account asynchrony 'where thought experiments
can anticipate what will have already taken place'
(97). Kirby insists that these experiments have
produced results which have been 'retrospectively
actualised and empirically verified' [note
8, 152 cites a certain J Wheeler arguing that
quantum resonance between the choice of the
observer and the compliance of the observed
phenomenon also implies the collapse of separate
events in time — 'and this appears to be the
case'. {Much more cautiously} 'the spatial
separations of causality, at least in the
presumption of a single origin of influence and
efficacy, will not hold in quantum explanations'.
This is been met with 'overwhelming acceptance in
the scientific community' although it still
'remains contested' Davies is quoted as saying
that the world is a network of relations, that he
takes an approach associated with Heisenberg,
which Kirby sees as similar to Butler's
understanding of interference. Kirby cites Barad
on the dispute with Böhr. None of this can justify
the claim of empirical verification, though]
If we look at cultural constructionism but allow
certain 'incestuous outcomes', greater perversity
and involvement, we might think that attributing
arguments to Nature is 'an anthropocentric
projection' (97). This is what Butler thinks —
that whenever we represent natural qualities, we
attribute cultural and political significance to
them. She recognises that this makes it difficult
for her own additive solution to link nature and
culture. Kirby intends instead to explain that all
the complexity attributed to culture arises from a
'unified, if heterogeneous, field of expression
[which] is "Nature"'.
This reawakens problems of determinism or the
collapse of categories, but we have to risk this
in order to explore the full implications. Kirby
realises that the difference attached to the human
might be minimised. An implication follows for
science, and at the end, it might be nature that
is 'political, perverse, contestatory' (98), and
that we should grasp its mutatability.
We can start with Butler again and sexual
identity. We are going to argue that the
complexities involved stem from Nature, requiring
no supplement from culture. Kirby is not
suggesting that we can apply conventional physical
and biological sciences, but that arguments
intended to exemplify Culture actually reveal 'the
impossibility of such a claim' [immanent critique
then], drawing on the notion of entanglement.
Butler's essay on the lesbian phallus will be
examined in detail.
This begins with Freud's essay on narcissism.
There is an underlying libido which is fluid and
provides energy and this is what accounts for the
personal significance of bodily experience,
'excitations'. We can understand the movement as
offering a kind of economy, investing forces with
different intensities, responding to things like
pain and injury with different intensities.
However, we know that the experience of pain
actually varies across different cultural and
social contexts and within subjects. It is common
to see this as arguing that pain is both physical
and psychical, one of these additions again with
biology as the first cause.
Freud explains toothache like this, but thinks
hypochondria is more complex, and offers the
reverse 'explanatory direction' -- it arises from
psychical forces first that 'manifest as
biological symptoms' (99). Generally, for Freud,
physical and imaginary injury are theoretically
inseparable. Butler says that this has an
implication for what constitutes a body part of
any kind, especially an erotogenic one. So for
example, with narcissism hypochondria '"lavishes
libido on a body part" that does not actually
exist for consciousness until it is so invested.
As with Lacan and the mirror stage, Freud thought
that a sense of self was acquired through the
realisation of body boundaries in the process of
separation from the mother, but again there is the
paradox that consciousness seems to have provoked
this sensation — but it also seems to have been
present at the start of the process. The pain [of
self-discovery ?]might be of the hypochondriac
type. Similarly, there might be an underlying
erotogenicity that means the idea of a particular
body part is 'coincident with the phenomenology of
its perception'.
The general question is how physical
manifestations actually happen. Kirby's view is
that the physical body conceives itself
differently, including through ideas 'such that an
idea is a biological cause/effect' (100). The
initial conditions for manifestations are always
'inherently unstable and mutable', and it would be
wrong to give consciousness a particular priority
over biological complexity.
Freud is still ambiguous about what comes first.
For example he says that the original biological
process of an organ becoming sensitive to pain is
changed into a genital organ being excited. Of
course he thinks of the masculine case as a
universal one However, any erogenous zone can
respond in a similar way. The genitals may be
prototypical but 'they do not inaugurate this
chain of substitutions'. Freud says that all
organs are erotogenic. Butler is able to explain
that if male genitals are not ontologically
privileged, the development of phallic masculine
privilege is simply one of several possible
transfers of the erotogenetic. By implication
then, the phallus conferring masculine privilege
is not the same as the single organ of the penis,
because its erotogenetic qualities is a property
of all organs, something infinitely plastic and
transferable. The phallus is important as a
process of investiture of libidinal energy. Any
one particular organ actually has a threatened
identity by this process and its complex
'congested and condensed network system of
referral' (101). Even a toothache can invoke
a vagina dentata, orifice, something being
penetrated and so on, with the tooth both
something which enters and which is entered.
Freud wrongly conflates the phallus with the male
organ. It justifies patriarchy only when a
transformative process is stopped and connected to
a thing — which is when 'man appears to have the
phallus'. For Butler, a lesbian phallus is an
interesting object. It might be a substitute for
women's lack. Lesbianism cannot be explained from
some single origin — nor can any sexual identity.
At the personal level, it arises through the
processes of the infant's self recognition, and
before that process takes place 'the plenum of the
world is selfsame with the child'. Even if the
infant does apparently coincide with the world,
this should not be understood either as a
homogenous unity, or something provided by 'the
cut of difference' in language or culture. Self
sameness is originary, inherently entangled in
processes of non-identity and referral. Infants
need to manage this complexity '"properly"'. Even
Freud originally described human sexuality as
'constitutionally bisexual and polymorphously
perverse' (102). We have to be careful here
because bisexuality can also assume separate
identities added together. Kirby is more
interested in 'bisexuality as the splitting of
desire that renders all identity incoherent and
perverse from the start', with no single origin.
Sexuality does eventually 'segregate bodies and
pleasures into distinct identities and appropriate
practices', but this has no 'fixed and stable
foundation'.
It is wrong to think of the libido as originating
in the male organ — 'an imaginary illusion'.
Libidinal energy is much more plastic and
destabilising. That the whole system is fragile is
emphasised by Freud's connection with erotogenetic
self-discovery and illness and suffering, as in
hypochondria. This link between sexuality and
illness is developed when hypochondriacs are found
to be associated with and structured by guilt.
'Normally' narcissism gets externalized to other
objects and other people, and refusing to do this
produces 'guilty pleasure', whose ambiguity
produces physical illness as well as an
affirmation of narcissism if the deception [of
being ill] works.
Butler goes on to argue that conformity to
regulatory sexual practices requires prohibition
and the threat of pain, but this will also 'induce
irregular outcomes' (103). They might lead to
important body surfaces capable of erotic transfer
that are not conventionally located in any
anatomical sexuality. The lesbian phallus is
Butler's example. Freud originally saw the
connection of sickness and narcissism as something
found in homosexuality, 'the love of self – same'
which must be turned around and aimed others in
heterosexuality. This necessarily coincides with
'a conscience — the will to conform to social
regulation'. This implies that normal sexuality
'is built on the pain and guilt' associated with
homosexual pleasures. For Butler, more creative or
productive solutions are available in the
appearance of the body as 'an imaginary schema of
meaningful parts' [I think the implication is that
the conventional notion of the body has to be
constantly reinforced by the conventional
'libidinal investments', and if these are not
available, more imaginary bodies can develop]. In
particular, Butler talks of '"compensatory fantasy
and a fetishistic mask"' as an alternative to
either conventional heterosexuality, or illness
and pain.
Butler also considers Lacan and the mirror stage.
The child develops a notion of itself as coherent
only by identifying itself from another's
perspective, a process of recognition in a mirror.
As a result, our subjective notion of the body is
always 'a dynamic vacillation between projection
and misrecognition' (104). We never resolve the
tension between seeing ourselves as an 'amorphous
ubiquity and a coherent entity with agency. The
ego remains attached to the body, but this is not
fixed but dynamic, engaging in recognition and
mutation. There is a connection between this whole
scheme and how we perceive the visible world, 'the
shape and definition of otherness'. The subject
becomes the process of projection and
misrecognition, differentiating both self and
world, but always unstable, necessarily taking the
form of an '"imago, that is, as an identificatory
relation"' [quoting Butler], and identifications
are never just achieved but always 'insistently
constituted, contested and negotiated'.
The child's ego is peopled with others, as Lacan
argues, just as its anatomy is engaged with social
relations and various conversions, including a
perceived anatomy [a particularly open-ended
perception leaves open the possibility of the
lesbian phallus]. However, Lacan sees the Symbolic
order as 'a given system of binary
identifications' (105) operated by a
'transcendental signifier — the phallus'. It
operates at a universal system of differentiation
not something specifically cultural or social,
which is why Lacan agrees that the phallus can
never be just the penis or any other organ.
However Butler's emphasis on political
inequalities leads her to suggest that there is a
'performative consequence' that this position ends
with the penis having the same symbolic privilege
as the phallus in patriarchy [so this is a
patriarchal appropriation of a universal
possibility?]. That arises because Lacan fails to
distinguish adequately between the Symbolic and
the Imaginary [seen here as a 'wishful process of
representational identification that enables the
infant to overcome (and deny) its inadequacies'].
Kirby thinks that the same division appears in
Butler when she thinks that cultural forces are
quite different from natural ones, and interprets
findings instead to stress '"the constant
instability" of biology'.
If any body part is to be identified as separate,
this takes place against the overall
erotogeneticity of the body and its ability to
signify, [especially in representing wholes of the
body in terms of parts, maybe]. Lacan acknowledges
in principle that the phallus can take 'myriad
imaginary forms' not just the penis [which might
be denied in effect when Butler talks about the
lesbian phallus?]. This means that sexual identity
is no longer fixed by the position of body parts.
Butler goes on to identify a nasty ambiguity for
those who do identify the phallus with the penis —
their '"anatomical part is never commensurable
with the phallus itself"' (106), so they might
experience castration and loss. For those who do
not perform this identification, including Lacan
who says that women can therefore have a phallus,
there might still be castration anxiety [of a
symbolic kind]. [Butler also points out that women
being able to have a phallus introduces an
'implicit heterosexuality' into lesbian relations,
and and implicit homosexuality in hetero ones].
We find in the bodily ego these necessary
'phantasmic crossovers', meaning that the usual
binaries of identity and desire will never fit and
must be sustained by '"marginal" subjectivities'.
For Butler, the margins and the centre are the
same [but this complicates 'a pluralist politics
of inclusion' and also celebration of marginality
as a site of play]. For Butler, there is no
central point of identity, no logic of
non-contradiction, only identities that are
'thoroughly messy, implicated, and ambiguous'.
Whoever has the phallus is not a matter for
anatomy. Constant reference to the phallus [as in
phallogocentric philosophy as well as everyday
practice?] is therefore 'a performative fiction'.
For Lacan, the phallus inaugurates signification,
precisely because it cannot be represented,
producing a dynamism. This affects the 'lived
significance of anatomy' which must be always in
play, including its referents. The phallus cannot
be symbolised only through anatomy, for Butler,
hence the possibility of the lesbian phallus, but
this risks '"an aggressive reterritorialization"'
[to match the one in patriarchy?]. The concept of
the lesbian phallus thus points towards the
complexity of phantasmatic anatomy for everyone,
and the way in which desire is condensed into
different objects and expressions.
Butler has a return to consider anatomy in order
to show that it is unstable as a reference, that
it takes an imaginary form, driven by the 'pain of
loss… failure and incapacity' to represent an
ideal, a necessary misrecognition of itself, a
compensatory fantasy. Nature has become
inaccessible and forbidden again. Butler sees
hypochondria as the general process at work where
pain and loss is rewritten as pleasure. She also
sees 'masculine, heterosexual melancholy' is a
necessary consequence for being unable to accept
loss, unlike [hetero] women who can compensate
through the heightening of feminine identification
[maybe, 108]. Ironically, the most melancholy
lesbian true to herself is therefore the straight
woman.
The problem is that anatomy is seen as inherently
mutable, but also as an illusion or fiction, and
Butler is therefore still attempting to penetrate
the ambiguity to reveal some underlying truth. For
Butler, this would be the notion of femininity
that defines the mother [Kirby suggest this might
be the only adequate way to compensate for loss].
But for Kirby, the mother is phallic, lacking
nothing, representing the whole world, offering
endless 'transfiguration and genesis' for the
child, that even enables children to express their
own difference and develop their own desires. This
cannot be the subject of misrecognition or
masquerade. Instead we find 'the incestuous nature
of Nature, it's "unnatural" capacity to reproduce
itself in myriad manifestations that, in a very
real sense, are all true'
Should we understand this as a cultural
misrecognition of what is actually or naturally
true? Freud saw hypochondria as a 'foil for
narcissistic self attention', which has to be
guiltily hidden. We cannot apply this to 'the
plenitude of primordial erotogeneticity' (109),
however. That is not individuated, something
separate from children and worlds, something
'originally consubstantial' [attributed to
Saussure,says note 14, p. 153,indicating the sign
is ambiguous as both an entitiy and as a token in
a system of referral. Suassure also should
have abandoned the idea of 'separate and
different functions and attributions' says
Kirby] something that endures as well as
showing variants [magic substance] which defies
any easy resolution of the paradoxes discussed by
Butler, certainly not a simple reversal. The
different identities are not segregated and then
implicated. Instead 'identity is never given', and
the identities are always entangled. [Bit of magic
substance?]
Butler wants to deny simple understandings of
homosexual, especially lesbian sexuality. She
wants to reject the idea that there is
narcissistic self possession at the origin that
turns into homoeroticism. That will lead to the
argument that only the male heterosexual is
properly socially mature, while other erotogenic
paths are pathologised, as in hypochondria. Butler
saw it as particularly relevant to stress this
when homosexuals are being blamed for AIDS.
The violence of homophobia does need more than
moral appeals. The logic of discriminating needs
to be challenged. Homophobia misogyny and racism
are all 'nourished by the notion that a primitive
type of sexualosed self absorption precedes the
social' (110) and this threatens social order and
legitimacy. Of course there is hypocrisy here in
the idea that legitimacy requires repression. It
meshes with other narratives about movements from
primitive to civilised or from nature to culture.
Butler needs to question the idea that nature is
inherently selfsame.
Seeing the social and cultural as a regulating
force coming in after nature sees identity as
dualist, 'either present or absent, true or
fictional'. It offers a view of differentiation as
something within a system, separated from the
outside. It is just like reifying the phallus,
turning the process into a thing. Butler tries to
question the origins of such ways of thinking, and
she does offer 'open-ended… possibility'. But she
also seems to preserve 'an incest taboo' that
connects legitimacy with prohibition. It also sees
the cogito as only available to humans. What if
nature was 'always/already multiple, contrary,
disseminated, incestuous?'. Why should culture
exist only to repress? [maybe].
Chapter 6 Culpability and the
Double – Cross. Irigaray with Merleau-Ponty
[it's not Hegel, it's Merleau-Ponty that links
the world and the knowing subject. Kirby opts for
general otherness not originally split, unlike
Derrida. Merleau-Ponty gives a great example of a
magic substance that also contains all its own
differences and contradictions]
She really rated Irigaray at first, especially the
way of revaluing the negative and its deficiency.
Political inequities seem to be mirrored in
binaries in language, a hidden structure that
equated otherness with incapacity, something
'feminised, racialised, broken, and somehow wrong'
(111). She became particularly interested in the
connections between simplification and life
itself, bodily being. Irigaray was inspiring
because she critiqued binary logic in
phallocentrism which led to seeing woman as a
failed man, not a subject. Binary differences in
language were 'sexually and racially inflected'
(112). They all seem to join up, so that being
feminised also involved being primitive, while
males were more evolved and somehow had escaped
their primordial origins'— this is 'tautologous
logic'. Irigaray was to argue that conventional
notions of equity will be always compromised by
the binaries which install man as the reference
point. However, her project offered 'a form of
mimicry, a loving "espousal of the philosophers"'
involving close attention to phallocentric logic
to disclose the value of what is repressed and
disavowed.
Painstaking investigation led to 'transgressive
leverage from within', a 'difference "on the
inside" of phallocentrism', In particular how it
argues for 'an identical self sameness and an
absolute prohibition'. The concepts are
incoherent. Man is no longer a solid reference
point, so women cannot stand for insufficiency.
Despite all the efforts to develop 'coordinates
and cross-referencing' the system is not stable —
'like Dr Who's Tardis'(113) there are all sorts of
surprising interior dimensions. Kirby noticed the
similarity to Derrida, especially in arguing that
freedom or play in the system is not external
requiring something outside like a bricoleur, but
rather internal, generated by 'the system's own
internal operations'. It follows that there can be
'no outside [of?] logocentrism' either, but this
does not lead to quietism, since feminism and
other contesting programs are 'born within
the interstices of logocentrism's commitments and
practices'. There is a different possible 'economy
evaluation, indeed, different worlds' found within
the structure. Both Irigaray and Derrida work with
'contamination and confusion rather than… thinly
disguised forms of purity and redemption'.
However, Irigaray still believed that 'sexual
difference is irreducible' amid all the ambiguity.
She develops this in a conversation with
Merleau-Ponty (MP). Kirby wants to argue that all
identity is still 'necessarily fragile and
contingent' and to build on 'feminism's
promiscuous appearance in unexpected places and
forms'.
Irigaray in An Ethics of Sexual Difference
explains why it is difficult to conceive justice
and a sense of right, because these rest on
'devaluation and erasure of the feminine', seen in
the attempt to exclude 'corporeal demands and
connections such as affect' (114). We need a
complete overhaul and reinterpretation extending
to the issue of relations between the subject and
discourse, the subject and everything else, why
the subject is always written in the masculine
form even if it claims to be universal or neutral.
This subject masters time and orders the world.
Merleau-Ponty offers another discussion of the
feminine and the maternal, rejecting the old split
of mind and body and thus of materiality and
cognition. In The Visible and the
Invisible, there is a choice to develop
non-dualistic ontology, developed from within
[which looks to me at first light as an extension
of Husserl and
apperception, or Schutz
— I'll try and read it]. It is different from
Irigaray. Irigaray still wants to differentiate
the feminine within 'the identity of humanity
proper', especially re-evaluating the maternal.
Merleau-Ponty still talks of '"the flesh of the
world"' which seems neutral: Irigaray wants to
talk instead of the [foundational] '"maternal
feminine" [apparently in French, the term feminin
means both cultural connotations and the female
sex, which questions the old nature culture
split].
Merleau-Ponty has a broader interest, humanity and
how it emerges in Nature as '"the flesh of the
world" (115). Irigaray thinks he has just
appropriated feminine attributes in this
discussion like 'the doublecross that corrupts and
divides the identity of the maternal from itself'
and which leads to the exclusion of the feminine
and sexual difference. Kirby wants to see it
differently, as essential to 'an ethics of any
sort'.
Irigaray's discussion of the maternal points to
history and origins and implies some time when
there was some original 'nurturing maintenance' of
life. She warns us that we should not be nostalgic
because this threatens an ethics of the modern
world. She wants to consider '"the whole
problematic of space and time"' [not just return
to some golden time]. Nostalgia does reveal all
the ways in which we are constantly trying to
'discover and reconnect' (116) with our roots. It
really reveals anxiety especially about 'the
carnality of [human, in her case male]
...history'. This leads to commodification, a
desire to make things accessible and controllable
while at the same time keeping it in the past.
This is a constant circling, an attempt to return
to the maternal, prevented by constant
'"envelopes, containers, houses"' which always
intervene. Men are always building homes for
themselves, including in language and theory:
culture is itself 'an inherently masculine set of
endeavours and attributes' guided by the need to
inhabit.
This prevents a real understanding of foundations
and origins, in the flesh. The world itself
becomes uninhabitable because it is dominated by
unfortunate images, especially producing '"an
uninhabitable" [functional] body, like the
technical world and all its sciences. Or like the
scientific world and all its techniques"'
[obviously Kirby is not going to go along with
that]. Scientific enquiry is entirely
instrumental, deceptive and managing the world,
but this is a highly specific form of being. The
very notion of reflection and management of the
world 'recapitulate[s] the alienated relationship
he has to his own flesh'. He has to distance
himself from his body in order to control it, to
replace some crucial '"organic rhythm"', and to
produce a generally distanced stance 'in the
triumphant guise of scientific mastery and
machinic usefulness'.
Irigaray wants to explore this alienated space,
and work out the implications of even the usual
notions of the feminine, as something attuned to
the outside, something sensuous. An alert
sensibility produces a perception that is 'mobile,
active, and generous' (117). It is not distant or
closed. There is a 'corporeal capacity for
generosity, receptivity, and caring' even in the
conventional notions of the woman and feminine.
The female subject is indeed elusive, but this
only shows the inadequacy of the conventional
definitions that find her lacking, negative,
passive. We need to thoroughly reconstruct and
revalue these consequences.
Merleau-Ponty's last chapter on the intertwining
and the chiasm helps us develop this idea,
seemingly in some state of resonance with
Irigaray. His stuff on the phenomenology of
perception is helpful in challenging most of the
conventional notions of subjectivity, and the
corresponding usual anti-humanist critique. He
wants to abolish the division between the ideal
and the material, culture and nature, human and
other. This is done by describing the world as
'"the flesh" which implies 'intelligence usually
reserved for human subjectivity' (118). The world
is sensible and can perceive itself through a
'will to self-knowledge'. This takes the form of a
'worldly becoming' without any final arrival or
single beginning. Humanness is not some entity in
the world and separate from it, something
exceptionally engaged in intellection. 'The world,
by implication, would always have been in the
process of discovering, exploring, redefining, and
reinventing the nature of its humanity'.
The flesh embraces itself
(and,in a lot of tautologous magic substance
stuff], this is reversible, so perception
can only be 'a form of self- encounter'
(118). So what is the Self? --something
'comprehensive and comprehending'. There is
an 'expansive corporeal personification of
"the Sensible"' Luckily, this causes a
'transsitive collapse' of lots of
distinctions -- 'birth and thought,
substance and form, body and mind, and
origin and outcome'. To an extent, M-P sees
this as the maternal --Nature and flesh are
the mother -- but this is a disrupted view
of maternity, a 'complete dislocation of the
temporal and spatial coordinates'[which
means really radical and good for
Kirby] This is what Irigaray picks up,
although she does not agree with the
specific form of M-P's disruption, which she
says erases the specificity of the feminine.
Irigaray's
whole ethical position depends on there being
sexual difference, although she also agrees
that we should reconsider space and time as
well. She finds MP to be misguided, dispersing
maternity into some general capacity, the
flesh. For Kirby, sexual specificity is not
precluded, however, and Irigaray misses this
by just seeing MP as working with the same old
logic of the same.
For
Irigaray, perception in feminist terms must
involve openness to the difference of others,
'a gesture of generosity'. Any conceptual
duality is seen as threatening closure,
keeping back from the good and the creative.
MP does find a way through, though. He also
sees perception working through the feminine
and invokes a specifically feminine term
'"invagination"' to describe how the flesh of
the world folds back upon itself [cf Deleuze on the
fold]. Perception must therefore depend on an
experience of difference, non-coincidence, and
this energises how the world perceives itself.
The intention is to grasp 'the essential
fullness of Being in all its expressions'
(119). The flesh has an insatiable desire for
carnal knowledge which takes diverse and
perverse forms: even when it seems to withdraw
into itself 'it nevertheless remains in touch
with itself'. This is 'thoroughly
comprehensive' in its unqualified openness:
'even closure is intrinsic to its make up'
[proper magic substance]. All dualities and
negations are within it, never independent, so
the flesh cannot be defined against closure —
'closing, sealing, and separating are
intrinsic to its desire for itself', so any
closure is really 'an internal movement, or
differential of "the flesh"'.
Nevertheless
there must be internal divergence, dissonance,
which is where perception turns into self
interrogation. This is the context to the
understanding of the feminine. There is a debt
to the maternal, but MP wants to undo the
limits of maternity, its 'spatial and temporal
location as straightforwardly in the past, in
a single, identifiable place… Given by only
one body, one gender and through one sexual
act' (120). Perception instead is akin to
conception. It is a 'desiring organ',
encountering its own alienness and thus
reconceiving itself. In this conception,
knowledge is related to birth, 'epistemology
emerging as the entanglement of ontology' a
form of 'perverse intercourse': the subject
questions 'porous being' and receives '"a
confirmation of its astonishment"', in a form
of gestation — 'one same corporeity or
visibility in general' in the very depth of
being.
The
flesh displays a turning back onto itself,
'chiasmic reversibility'. It does not seek to
return to one origin. Instead it offers
'dehiscence, or bursting open, of the origin'
in infinite iterations. Perception does not
depend on the subject or some primordial self
pre-existing the capacity to engage the world,
despite a hint of this in the earlier work.
A
lengthy extract from Signs says that
we discover others in the world's flesh, that
recognition does bring them into existence,
but that it is possible to decipher some kind
of self presence. It is impossible to
understand the world or to develop a vision
without invoking the '"whole fabric of the
perceptible world… and with it… the others who
are caught in it"' (121). Others are not
fictions arising in spirit but '"twins or the
flesh of my flesh"'. They are distant, but
when we consider the perceptible world, we
realise that it can '"haunt more than one body
without budging from its place"' we might have
an individual perception of a table, but we
also '"know that at the same moment it presses
upon every glance in exactly the same way. For
I see those other glances too"' together,
these glances can offer '"a new compresence"'
[it is the notion of apperception and the
ability to take the view of the other in
Husserl and Schutz ].
So
ontological differentiation is semiotic,
leading to experience and understanding. It
all takes place outside of conventional space
and time, as a kind of 'contagion'. What seems
to be preexistent is still becoming. MP claims
that this is not just an ideal based on
'philosophical abstraction' [of course it is].
Irigaray notes this via MP's own awareness
that philosophy must be more than reflection
since this presumes some pre-judgement and he
suggests that we should philosophize with new
experiences that have not been worked over,
that these will provide resources for
philosophy [which smuggles in realism].
Irigaray
soon parts company, though and operationalises
MP's original harmony by saying that we must
go back to pre-discursive experience, but this
implies some notion of linear time again.
Irigaray criticises this nostalgia in male
consciousness, but reproduces it here. MP has
a much broader project, and an 'interrogative'
one rather than an attempt to find some
foundation for sexual difference as if we
already knew how these differences emerged and
what they were. We can see the differences in
Irigaray arguing that we need to find some
'originary space' for something before
dispersion or incarnation. She imposes a
sequence between first cohering and then
connecting as we develop our sense of touch,
while vision both 'dissects and forgets'
(123). There is some original integrity which
gets split. This might be explained by her
psychoanalytic understanding of subject
formation, where the child's entrance into
culture involves loss and denigration of the
'(m)othered part of itself'. The whole thing
is inspired by fear of increasing
technological and scientific dissection and
dissolution.
For
MP, there is life even in dispersion. There
was no original beginning to be split, 'all
identity is given chiasmically'. Indeed
dispersion can be understood as maternity
where a particular identity arises from a
continuing involvement of the flesh. Of course
there might well be particular locations or
condensations, singular experiences, but these
still depend upon shared understandings [as
with the perception of the table] [I think he
will probably see it as shared participation
in the flesh rather than mundane
understandings].
Fields
are unified by their very 'enduring intention
to differentiate', [handy!] so particularity
is permitted' there are no atomic entities
uniquely and particularly located in linear
time, but rather a set of coordinates 'whose
"compresence" evokes the whole of the world as
"the flesh" takes measure of itself' through
difference. The bodily senses are measuring
instruments for being, 'dimensions' not to be
seen as anything [empirically?] adequate or
immanent.
Kirby sees a parallel between
this 'wild and counterintuitive logic' and some
quantum implications: MP has split 'the atom of
identity', refused any separation into agent or
representation. He sees becoming an entity as like
the 'spreading movement and expansive pool and
undertone of a wave' (124) [the actual quote talks
about coiling, circling and, indeed, a wave
linking what is visible immediately with a horizon
— maybe — which helps him talk about the
development of whole other consciousnesses into
landscapes?]. These points are magical, poetic,
'suggestive', but there is enough to argue that
there is no stance 'against the feminine', despite
Irigaray, partly because to defend it against
improper use would imply that we validate it as a
concrete manifestation in the first place. Instead
we have an 'utterly referential' interior grasp of
the Sensible. It coheres because it offers 'an
implicated weave' that both connects the visible
together in a fabric, and also connects it to '"a
fabric of invisible being'' [proper magic
substance]. So identity is only a particular node
in a way, '"a concretion of visibility"'.
Semiosis itself is 'corporealised' as flesh, in
contact with itself, 'articulate in its
perceptions. Both subject and language are
incorporated. Irigaray sees this as 'masculinist
reductionism', but this 'might be misguided'
(125), baffled by MP's 'quite exquisite feel for
the intricacy and wonder in this seemingly simple
word, "language"'. [As anyone normal would be].
Irigaray shows 'irritations', arising from her own
nostalgic desire for self presence which emerges
after all.
MP sees an ontological discourse, 'a becoming
sensible' proceeding by making explicit '"the
architectonics of the human body", how it sees and
hears itself and constructs a mute world that also
contains '"all the possibilities of language"'.
The phenomenological world is its langue,
neither prior to specific words, nor subsumed by
them, but rather representing 'intertwining…
enfoldings'. This is similar to what is implied by
entanglement in contemporary physics — 'a living
ground'.
In both discourses despite very different objects
and methods, the gap between the ideational and
the physical 'entirely collapses, and for similar
reasons' and is replaced by notions of
intertwining and entanglement. There is also a
sense of 'an "in between" [God help us]
pre-existing entities'. Space and time as
localising reality does not obtain, in MP nor 'in
current evidence of quantum complexity' [note 2
just says that Einstein was wrong to want to
return to a classical understanding of the
universe, and refers us to chapter 1, note 1,
which summarises Einstein's position and a debate
with John Bell — apparently Einstein {the EPR
thesis} 'could not reproduce the myriad
predictions of quantum mechanics. Somebody called
Aspect operationalised Bell to produce an actual
experiment that confirmed it 'and proved quantum
non-locality'].
Perhaps the debate in science has relevance for
Irigaray and the location of the feminine?
Irigaray's 'complaint against MP echoes the wider
debate about non-locality. Einstein himself had
doubts when he realised that reality was not
easily divided into separate entities but was
entangled — he referred to '"spooky action at a
distance"' (126). He simply asserted that we
should still try to hold onto physical reality,
something existing and actual, something 'real in
one part of space' which could be seen as
independent of something thought of as real in
another part of space. Einstein insisted that it
could not depend on measurement [Barad 2007,p.315
is the source for this discussion]. Irigaray seems
to have a 'shared commitment' to classical notions
of locality and identity, something that
preexistent measurement representation. Einstein
would have been defeated by later experiments that
confirmed Bohr, argued Barad, and this is 'in
rhythm with my reading of MP'.
Kirby goes on to quote Barad on how our sense of
reality is made up of individual objects, but we
should really deal with phenomena 'whose very
being is always and only an articulation of
entanglement'. The two slit experiment, showed
this, including the delayed-choice variant.
MP apparently has the same understanding 'of
phenomenal complexity — phenomenal reality' (127).
He denies that the senses can provide a material
ground, some realm which then has to be
imperfectly translated into language [Kirby sees
these as reflecting nature and culture
respectively]. He's like Derrida in reworking
language, agreeing that language is 'the brain
twisting suggestion of difference itself… A
process that gives rise to the perception of an
event as a divided phenomenon'. There is no
outside ground of reference, no substance, but
only something 'already intrinsic to its
systematicities'. Meanings are not added as a kind
of layer, but as given with the words themselves,
becoming '"the totality of what is said, the
integral of all the differentiations of the verbal
chain"'. For MP, '"language is everything, since
it is the voice of no one, since it is the very
voice of the things, the weights, and the
forests"' (128).
Meaning always involves disjunction, for example
between what is heard and what is said, some
internal dialogue. MP still wants to privilege the
visible, though, and this is phallogocentric for
Irigaray. For MP, the relation between touch and
vision 'is intricacy itself', however so that a
particular perception leads to 'a relational
enfolding' [apperception]. Vision is associational
and synaesthetic, saturating all the senses.
This makes visibility the same as Derrida's
textuality or general writing. Derrida is not
privileging writing over speech, just
destabilising the usual distinctions between them,
so that we get to see the limits of ideas about
origins, or progress from simple to complex, and
from truth to intellectual corruption. This is the
same 'founding division that informs the nostalgic
imperative' in Irigaray — nature as something
feminine dominated by the masculinist something
secondary and instrumental. She also interprets
the ambiguities in MP 'as simply erroneous'.
MP on 'corporeal semiosis', the articulation of
flesh with itself denies any self presence or
'separate sensory modalities'(129). Nor can the
world just be seen as an assembly of individual
bodies. His approach is 'like a grammatology writ
large'. In one phrase, he says that we can detect
the presence of other people within ourselves, and
that we can deduce that our bodies are in some
sort of system with other bodies, a fold that
continues to touch itself 'even as it opens itself
up', as with invagination.
Irigaray erases this 'utterly extraordinary…
Reading of carnal speech', a generalisation of the
two lips approach. She sees it as masculinist
theft, and restores a hierarchy between flesh and
language. She admits that we can no longer contact
this primordial ground, but says we should not
bury maternity altogether as if it had no
relevance to the present — this is what denigrates
it, seeing it as a past 'expendable moment'.
Instead she says the past is still present to us,
while any attempt to represent maternity will
reify it and repress its specificity. If we
explore the differences between these two we can
get to see the need for sexual ethics for her.
For Kirby, this still works with a notion of
duration [sic] as linear time linking separate
moments. This is even presumed when Irigaray tries
to see 'tactility at the origin' (130) [instead of
vision]. This becomes some ground or 'nurturing
support', something feminised, which loses itself
in what becomes sensible. Maternity is the given,
not parented by anything else.
MPs vision of maternity differs. He does
acknowledge a debt that was given, of which we can
still feel the effects. But he radicalises the
conventions of space and time and the mechanism of
transfer. So maternity can revalue the future as
well as the past, and should be understood as 'the
generative capacities of men as well as women' and
even a general vitality found in the animate. His
vision is actually the same as tactility, and
there is no primordial segregation and alienation,
no erasure of primordial voice, no distortion of
it into reified law. This would wrongly appeal to
the origin in its immediacy, 'speech before
writing' (131), nature violated by culture and
language. Flesh is not itself engendered but is
something given that proceeds becomings, 'in
simple terms, it just is'. Irigaray does
acknowledge some internal movement or differential
within, but the primordial essence is somehow
preserved.
The origin is sealed off, requiring some outside
encounter — sexual encounter, which renders men as
obviously 'violating perpetrator'. Women cannot
engage in intercourse among themselves. This sees
heterosexual encounter as the foundation of sexual
difference. The very identity involved is 'already
a scene of ethical consideration' for Kirby,
however. Irigaray's ethics of sexual difference is
about how we encounter someone alien, not just an
inversion of ourselves, but this still leaves
otherness is a mystery and it is not clear why we
should ground an ethics on sexual priority,
'assuming we know what that is.' Ontological
difference involves a much more general notion of
a copula, and we need to investigate it to explain
sexual difference.
Irigaray advocates a provision to be made for the
maternal feminine, to preserve its difference, and
avoid total or masculine appropriation. This is
the basis of her ethics. MP, on the other hand
wants to rethink the implicit 'metaphorics of
purity and danger'. We cannot manage something
from the outside. Penetration might be understood
as the ability of the flesh to touch itself, which
is also an investigation of itself. We will have
to rethink the whole notion of violation.
There are differences in the conception of
language which runs throughout the entire projects
of both thinkers. Irigaray takes a Lacanian view
of subject formation, where language is already in
the world ready to replace maternal origins,
already acting as a kind of duplication of '"the
maternal gift of flesh"' (132). Language must
always therefore display some lack in its attempt
to substitute for 'carnal beginnings'. MP by
contrast sees no difference between the body and
language, but sees instead 'carnality as
thoroughly garrulous; as an originary
vociferousness', something already containing all
the possibilities of language.
Irigaray sees the internal dialogue of the flesh
as a repression of difference, with language
simply reproducing the same, without contact with
carnal foundations. She finds MP puzzling in
asserting that an origin 'could be pregnant with
language' and tends to see this only as an erasure
of the feminine, by implying that the feminine
cannot be a source of extra creativity. MP however
sees language as an expression of the world, a
process of 'self violation/self evolution' (133).
The tactile is itself a language that
differentiates and discriminates: we see this in
Braille and also in our response to pressures and
textures where touch becomes a kind of 'sensate
writing/reading'. Touch is not undifferentiated
[or something simple or primitive] but depends on
'an entire field of corporeal sensation'.
Language is not just a representation or model of
a world, but 'an ontological energy through which
the world makes itself known (to itself)'. MP sees
drawings and maps, as having this capacity to
implicate what is being mapped, not just represent
it, that maps and what they depict have a '"common
inner framework"'. They are reality in another
dimension, and '"Being is dimensionality itself"'
so that is accessible by perception at a number of
levels of scale. This is the same
'counterintuitive complexity that Barad captures
in her descriptions of quantum entanglement' [well
— both are counterintuitive, and both seem to deny
any particular effects of scale itself]. MP is
agreeing that the desire to know 'is implicated in
the very ontology of what it is that he is looking
at'. A perceptual event depends on an intention to
look as well as anything inherent in the object.
Overall the world itself does 'language,
representation, modelling' as part of its 'ongoing
manufacture'. There is no violation, nothing to be
condemned [indeed, everything is forgiven as
usual], 'no moral flaw in this scene of genesis'
(133 – 4). [So we have to find out what's bad by
applying some additional preferences?]. For MP,
'identity is utterly violated' and 'corruption
engenders' (134), so masculinism 'could be said to
mother feminism in the same gesture that discovers
feminism… affirming masculinism'. Appropriation is
birth as well as theft. Identity emerges
[actualises from 'structured moments and rhythms
of intercourse'], but 'every act is generally
born, and yet never in the same way'. Sameness is
no longer a problem, nor do we need radically
different identities to found sexual ethics
'radical alterity is already present 'within the
apparent unity and coherence of individual
identity'. Thus sameness is actually 'impossible'.
Culture and masculinity cuts itself apart from
nature, and this is seen as a wounding, masculine,
outside for Irigaray, but for MP 'this fault line
is chiasmatic… fractured and dispersed' ubiquitous
and across the scale 'like a Mandelbrot filigree
of repetitive transformation that is integral to
all identity'. So if there is this cut, 'the
entire universe is essentially at fault' [entirely
apologetic at this stage].
So 'no one is to blame'. We can't develop an
ethics based on blame, any more than we can find
pure and indivisible lines anywhere else,
especially in separating human from nonhuman.
Derrida says as much, and recognises that this
will leave us 'uncertain about how to proceed' —
his only response is that we should openly welcome
doubt, responsibility and the difficulties of
being ethical as the '"unrescindable essence of
ethics"' [like one of these absolute but
unattainable commitments to otherness —
philosophical rigour preserved by abandoning any
actual evaluations]. Blame and violence are not
precluded exactly, but culpability 'cannot be
attributed to any one', has no origin or cause.
This should at least make us 'more forgiving and
generous' when we make judgements and political
decisions, and cause us to think about them again
afterwards [become like Christ really and float
above all the mundane struggles].
Irigaray began by calling for thorough
reinterpretations between subject, world, language
and everything. This does make the male subject
unstable with a 'friable identity' but, so is the
'collective subject of Mankind' (135) our whole
notion of shared humanity and its capacities,
which can no longer be defined against some
nonhuman inferior world. Mankind is a sexist term,
but we do not avoid instability by simply
re-describing it as a more inclusive Humankind.
One of MP's passages is 'literally, wonderful'. It
avoids the usual split between humanist and
anti-humanist positions, but neither are dismissed
'as simply mistaken', an example of his 'inclusive
sense of generosity'. He does not intend visible
flesh to just refer to humans, but talks of
'carnal being' at different levels, latent being,
prototypes of Being of which our own bodies are a
variant, however remarkable. This will not lead us
immediately to want to end sexual discrimination
or racism, or even global exploitation.
Apportioning culpability might be 'pragmatically
necessary' but we can not 'fail to acknowledge
that behaviours, even when individual, are enabled
by/through community'. The reversible flesh gives
us a general sense of responsibility when no one
is to blame, since 'all individuals and acts
issue' from it, in a 'constant process of
realignment and renewal, intertwining.
This will help us disarticulate the negative
associations of the feminine and the corporeal,
including those attached to the notion of the
primordial other. Nor is woman the origin of
everything, later violated by man. The single term
man 'will not locate the culprit' (136). So we are
provoked to practice politics differently: 'to
effectively instrumentalise a critique of
instrumentality… to explain inequality and
oppression without reinforcing their terms of
reference… to appreciate that puzzles about "the enigma
of woman" have universal application'. This will
sacrifice the coherence of feminism, but feminists
have always recognised that they are riddled with
their own 'undoing... impropriety... wilful
curiosity.'
Back to Barad on the inseparable parts of the
phenomenon. For Kirby, 'if this truly resonates
with the science and drama of MPs Vision — and
originary chiasmatic structure', not relations
between separated entities, we can reconsider
difference. It is not just loss or failure.
Alterity is intrinsic in Being, 'an expression of
[its] intra-ontology'. There are no entities that
limit my situation or knowledge. All limits are
'chiasmatically given'. An individual situation is
always 'more than local'.
There is another likeness between the quantum
problematic and MPs Vision. Someone called Dastur
draws on MPs ideas on temporality, especially how
we can see it as fractured in Cezannes' paintings.
MP sees vision as a means where we can become
absent from ourselves and take part in '"the
fission of Being from the inside"', and Dastur
adds a gloss. Vision reveals a splintered presence
not a unified agency, and this is '"the mystery of
simultaneity"', something that can coexist across
distance and time [via the
through-and-through-interconnectedness of
subjective time, for me]. This is how MP has
reframed the central questions of ontology,
epistemology, ethics and science 'by radically
recasting the anthropological'
[Good eg of the difficulties
of monism - -everything can be forgiven, no-one is
to blame etc. Politics becomes philosophy or
general ethics. Interesting to see this as an
ethical implication of entanglement in Barad
--more than she does?]
Kirby page
|